Politeness Principle. 1.Approaches to politeness: a review.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Conversational Implicature (Based on Paltridge, chapter 3)
Advertisements

The Cooperative Principle
1 MODULE 2 Meaning and discourse in English COOPERATION, POLITENESS AND FACE Lecture 14.
EL1101E WEEK 10: PRAGMATICS Group members: Elaine Ong Ong Min Thakshayeni Skanthakumar Jeannie Poon.
Talk in Life and Literature LO: to understand the basis of the question and the differences between crafted and ‘real’ talk.
Phil 160 Kant.
AS English Language Unit 3 Spoken Interaction Conversation Analysis Conversation Theory.
Conflict Management.
Language of Meetings PPTX What needs to be said?.
CAS LX 502 7a. Speech acts Ch. 8. How to do things with words Language as a social function. — I bet you $1 you can’t name the Super Tuesday states. —You’re.
1 Introduction to Linguistics II Ling 2-121C, group b Lecture 10 Eleni Miltsakaki AUTH Spring 2006.
Politeness Lecture 11.
Unit 9 The use of English (II). Review What are the three aspects of a speech act, according to John Searle? Use an example to illustrate. What are the.
HRM-755 PERFORMANCE MANAGEMENT
Chapter 2: Taking Charge of your health
Consolidating Grice, Brown & Levinson, and Goffman
Politeness Starter – How might Politeness be connected to English Language and Literature? Learning Objective – to explore Brown and Levinson’s politeness.
Brown and Livenson’s Politeness Theory.
S OLIDARITY AND P OLITENESS Drs. Liliek Soepriatmadji, M.Pd.
Politness and Face theory
thinking hats Six of Prepared by Eman A. Al Abdullah ©
1 The Purpose of Written Communication “Think now; write later”. ● Before one can begin to plan the “How”, he or she has to understand the “Why” of business.
POLITENESS Hanifa Rahmawati Bella Stita R. Firnantia Lara L. Weni Agustiningrum Dwi Esti J.N.
Introduction to linguistics II
Pragmatics.
Chapter Seven Pragmatics
Collaboration Works, Inc. IEP Facilitation: Preventing and Effectively Engaging Conflict in Meetings October 5, 2007 Karen Hannan Collaboration Works,
Boston Legal Class Exercise Selene Mize Faculty of Law, University of Otago NIFTEP 6 November 2009.
Semantics 3rd class Chapter 5.
 We have been considering ways in which we interpret the meaning of an utterance in terms of what the speaker intended to convey.  However, we have.
6.3 Macropragmatics Speech act theory The cooperative principle The politeness principle.
Functions of Speech 1. Expressive 2. Directive 3. Informative (Referential) 4. Metalinguistic 5. Poetic 6. Phatic 7. Heuristic 8. Commissive 9. Performative.
Communication and Transitioning: From Our Eyes By Jennifer Lindner And BJ Gallagher PhD, CCC-SLP By Jennifer Lindner And BJ Gallagher PhD, CCC-SLP.
STUDY QUESTIONS 1)In what sense is indirectness “costly and risky”? 2)Despite the fact that indirectness is costly and risky, people frequently resort.
Chapter 6 Pragmatics. 6.1 Introduction Review of semantics  Meaning in lg.  words Mothervs.Mother-in-law  sentence: in, am, I, T-shirt, today.
Introduction to Critical Thinking Developing Critical Thinking Skills.
Some Tools For Team Building an Introduction 2010 Faith and Light International Formation Project Team.
Politeness & Speaking Style Discourse & Dialogue CS 359 November 15, 2001.
Some Tools For Team Building Faith and Light International Formation 2010.
Everyone Communicates Few Connect
Presentation about pragmatic concepts Implicatures Presuppositions
Welcome Back, Folks! We’re travelling to a littele bit far-end of Language in Use Studies EAA remains your faithful companion.
UNIT 2 - IMPLICATURE.
Discourse and pragmatics. Meaning and context situational context background knowledge context co-textual context.
6 Steps for Resolving Conflicts STEP 1. Begin the Process Calmly approach the person you are having the conflict with, and explain to them that you have.
ADRESS FORMS AND POLITENESS Second person- used when the subject of the verb in a sentence is the same as the individual to.
Looking Out/Looking In Thirteenth Edition 11 Interpersonal Conflicts CHAPTER TOPICS The Nature of Conflict Conflict Styles Conflict in Relational Systems.
Sight Words.
Jody Blanke, Professor Computer Information Systems and Law.
Unit II PERFORMANCE FEEDBACK.
Chapter 7 Pragmatics English Linguistics: An Introduction.
FACE. Goffman’s Face Erving Goffman was intrigued by what lay behind everyday expressions such as ‘losing face’, ‘saving face’ and ‘being shamefaced’.
SPEECH ACTS Saying as Doing See R. Nofsinger, Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991.
Pragmatics. Definitions of pragmatics Pragmatics is a branch of general linguistics like other branches that include: Phonetics, Phonology, Morphology,
Principles of conversation
Implicature. I. Definition The term “Implicature” accounts for what a speaker can imply, suggest or mean, as distinct from what the speaker literally.
Politeness.
Promoting young children’s readiness and ability to learn is a natural and vital priority to children’s lives however, it is also essential for children.
Translatability. Noam Chomsky ("hómski“) In Chomsky's view, every phrase, before being formulated, is conceived as a deep structure in our mind. A phrase.
Speech Acts: What is a Speech Act?
Chapter 8 Spoken Discourse. Linguistic Competence communicative competence: the knowledge we bring to using language as a communicative tool in conversation.
MODULE 2 Meaning and discourse in English
POLITENESS PRINCIPLE:
PRAGMATICS 3.
COOPERATIVE PRINCIPLE:
The Cooperative Principle
POLITENESS If we really want co-operation… … we also need to be polite.
Nofsinger. R., Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991
The Cooperative Principle
Nofsinger. R., Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991
Presentation transcript:

Politeness Principle

1.Approaches to politeness: a review

Before Leech, there are two main approaches to politeness. Firstly Lakoff sees Grice’s rules as essentially rules of clarity, and proposes that there are two prior rules of pragmatic competence: “Be Clear” and “Be Polite”.

Here, clarity amounts to a condensed version of the Gricean maxims, while politeness serves to avoid conflicts between participants. She proposes her own three rules of politeness:

1)formality: don’t impose/remain aloof; 2)hesitancy: give the addressee his options; 3) equality: act as though you and the addressee were equal/make him feel good.

Secondly, the face-saving view of politeness, proposed by Brown and Levinson (1978) is related to the folk expression “lose face”. They suggest two kinds of face.

One is “negative face” or the rights to territories, freedom of action and freedom from imposition; essentially the want that your actions be not impeded by others.

The other is “positive face”, the positive consistent self-image that people have and want to be appreciated and approved of by at least some other people.

2. Leech’s approach to politeness

Grice’s cooperative Principle ( with its attendant Maxims ) may be interpreted as follows. In order to maintain effective communication, users of language may be supposed to do their best to preserve certain regulative goals:

They will try to be appropriately informative ( Maxim of quantity), truthful ( maxim of quality), relevant ( maxim of relation) and clear, orderly, etc. ( maxim of manner).

If a speaker manifestly appears not to observe these precepts of good communicative behaviour, then according to Grice, a reason may be that he intends the hearer to infer from his utterance some meaning additional to the conventional sense of the words and other signals he has uttered.

But why should a speaker resort to such oblique methods of communication? Why, for example, instead of saying “Could you give me a light?” does he not say more tersely and directly “Give me a light?”

The answer lies in other regulative goals which he has to keep in view, notably the goal of being polite.

This goal may conflict with the illocutionary goal; e.g. a request is inherently “impolite” in requiring the hearer to do something not in his interests.

It may also conflict with the regulative goals subsumed under Grice’s cooperative principle: the need for politeness may lead one to abandon truthfulness, and to tell “white lies.”

To Grice’s cooperative principle we therefore add a second principle, the politeness principle primarily expressed in the negative imperative “ Do not offend others,” but also including the positive imperative “ Be nice to others.”

Politeness in communication require us to adopt strategies of (a) maximising “ polite beliefs” and (b) minimising “ impolite beliefs.”

Polite beliefs is the terms conveniently used for beliefs ( expressed or implicated ) favourable to the other person or unfavourable to the speaker; and impolite beliefs are those which are unfavourable to the other person, or favourable to the speaker.

There is therefore a basic asymmetry in polite conversation: whatever is a polite belief for the speaker is impolite belief for the hearer. This can be illustrated with reference to the following maxims of politeness, which tend to go in pairs, and which are comparable to the maxims of the cooperative principle: MAXIMS OF POLITENESS.

(i) Minimise the cost to others; (b) maximise the benefit to others; (ii) The Generosity maxim: (a) Minimise the benefit to self; (b) maximise the cost to self;

(iii) The Approbation ( or flattery) maxim: (a) Minimise dispraise of others; (b) maximise praise of others;

(iv) The Modesty Maxim: (a) Minimise praise of self. (b) maximise dispraise of self;

(v) The Agreement Maxim: (a) Minimise disagreement between self and others; (b) maximise agreement between self and others;

(vi) The Sympathy Maxim: (a) Minimise antipathy between self and others; (b) maximise sympathy between self and others.

On what grounds can the politeness principle be justified?

1) The politeness principle helps to explain asymmetries in the acceptability of utterances

2) It also helps to explain asymmetries in the interpretation of utterances.

3) Without it, the cooperative principle is not fully explanatory.

3. PP under attack 3.1Conflicts between maxims

If PP is applied in some cases, one maxim may run counter to another. A: Let me help you. (a) B: How nice of you! (b) A: Such a heavy case is a piece of cake. (c) B: Thanks.(d)

A’s polite offer 1(a) can be accounted for by either the Tact Maxim or the Generosity Maxim. By the Generosity Maxim, A is maximizing cost to himself. By the Tact Maxim, A is maximizing benefit to B.

In both cases, A is polite. B’s acceptance is polite in that he obeys the Approbation Maxim — maximizing praise of others — praising A’s kindness. B’s acceptance is also impolite in that he flouts the Tact Maxim — minimizing cost to others because B’s acceptance indicates A realizing his offer, thus carrying the heavy case, inevitably unfavorable to A.

In Sentence 1(b) the Approbation Maxim is at odds with the Tact Maxim. Such conflicts between the maxims can also be found in Sentence 1(c). A’s suggestion that the suitcase is heavy is in accordance with the Generosity Maxim which requires A to maximize cost to himself.

On the other hand A is praising or boasting his ability to carry such a heavy thing, which goes against the Modesty Maxim.

In this case, one of A’s goals is clear, i.e. offering help in a polite way. It is safe to say that PP indeed functions in regulating A’s linguistic behavior.

But A has another goal, i.e. expressing his sincere wish to offer help and not suggesting that B owes something to A which is reflected in the phrase “a piece of cake”, a task easy enough for A to be greatly willing to do. PP does not help realize this goal, but hinders its realization instead.

Interlocutors will meet a difficult problem: which maxim should be obeyed to produce an utterance that is the most acceptable to opponents.

3.2 Less concern for a third party

Any literature on aspects of speech situations will mention participants, but the relationship among participants is only restricted to addressers and addressees. No wonder that CP requires the cooperation of the two sides and PP demands speakers’ politeness to hearers.

In fact, a third party, implicit or explicit, also affects the progress of linguistic communication, or the linguistic means of achieving goals.

Though Leech does not deny the existence of a third party, he fails to give enough weight to it.

Here’s an example. The hostess comes back home only to find her crying baby with thoroughly wet diaper as well as the maid who is watching TV. The hostess carries her baby, saying:

“You should cry loudly to remind the aunt of changing your diaper.”

It is obvious that the real addressee is not the baby in the cradle but the irresponsible maid. But the hostess achieves her goal of criticizing and urging her to change the diaper quickly in an indirect way for politeness or saving face.

The maid involved in communication is a third party present in the speech situation. It is easily imagined that the hostess will hold different attitudes if the maid is not present.

Maybe she will roar, purple with anger, “Damned! I will fire her.” It makes much difference whether a third party is present or not in the speech situation. As a rule, more politeness is shown towards a third party present than absent.

3.3 Less consideration for situational and social constraints

Another important aspect of Leech’s concept of politeness is pragmatic scales: the cost-benefit scale, the optionality scale, and the indirectness scale.

The cost-benefit scale “is made up of two distinct scales: cost/benefit to s and cost/benefit to h. Whatever is beneficial to s is at a cost to h, and whatever is at a cost to s is beneficial to h, especially in impositives and commissives”.

But some impositives which are beneficial to h are not necessarily at a cost to s. The announcement in an airport, for instance, full of impositives beginning with “Attention, please”, reminds passengers of departure information for their convenience.

Those impositives which are beneficial to passengers are not at a cost to the airport represented by the announcer but on the contrary are helpful to its smooth operation. Therefore, the cost-benefit scale sounds an absolute concept.

The optionality scale refers to the degree of directness of speakers’ sending utterances and the amount of options in hearers’ receiving. The less optional for the hearer the utterance in favor of the hearer is, the more polite it is. The more optional for the hearer the utterance in favor of the speaker is, the more polite it is.

a. Would you like to have another sandwich? b. Have another sandwich. c. Do have another sandwich. d. You must have another sandwich.

The most optional way of invitation such as the sentence above may imply that the speaker does not care whether the hearer accepts or not, and thus he is not warm or hospitable. a. Would you like to have another sandwich?

Conversely, Sentence d above is the most polite because the extremely hospitable speaker gives the hearer no space for option. d. You must have another sandwich.

From Sentence a to Sentence d politeness increases in order. a. Would you like to have another sandwich? b. Have another sandwich. c. Do have another sandwich. d. You must have another sandwich. least polite most polite

Suppose a little change is made — replacing “sandwich” with “bath”, things will be different. A glance at these four utterances will show that from Sentence a to Sentence d politeness decreases in order.

From Sentence a to Sentence d politeness decreases in order. a. Would you like to have another bath? b. Have another bath. c. Do have another bath. d. You must have another bath. Most polite Least polite

Sentence d may give the impression that the hearer always refuses to have a bath and the speaker has to give the ultimate. Certainly the propositional content of the utterance is beneficial to the hearer, but the least optional is the least polite, which is contrary to Leech’s idea.

The indirectness scale indicates the direct proportion between indirect speech acts and politeness in the processes of achieving goals.

a. Lend me your bike. b. May I borrow your bike please? c. I’d like to borrow your bike if you wouldn’t mind. d. Could you possibly lend me your bike for just a moment? e. There wouldn’t I suppose be any chance of you being able to lend me your bike for just a moment, would there?

a. Lend me your bike. b. May I borrow your bike please? c. I’d like to borrow your bike if you wouldn’t mind. d. Could you possibly lend me your bike for just a moment? e. There wouldn’t I suppose be any chance of you being able to lend me your bike for just a moment, would there? The indirectness scale shows that Sentence a is the least polite while Sentence e is the most polite. Least polite Most polite

However his idea of inherently impolite acts has been overturned by his account of the optionality scale.

3.4 Less regard for culture influence

Despite the universality of the actual manifestations of politeness, the ways to realize politeness and the standards of judgement differ in different cultures.

5.A (an American visitor): You did a good job. B (a Chinese waitress): No, there are still some shortcomings.

B’s response is a case of point of pragmatic failure. In Western cultures, those who are praised should express their gratitude to show their agreement with the praiser, which realizes the Maxim of Agreement for politeness. Native speakers will answer, “I’m glad to hear that” or “Thank you”.

But in Chinese culture, those who are praised should negate others’ praise, even humiliate themselves to show their modesty, which accords with the Modesty Maxim. Since both cultures justify their users’ expression, clash is inevitable between the two maxims required by different cultures.

In addition, Chinese’ acts of persuading guests to eat more puzzle the Western people a lot. But such acts are manifestations of Chinese hospitality.

Things that should be talked about indirectly or even be avoided in China are considered as good news in Western countries. Women’s pregnancy is seldom talked about among the Chinese in public, even privately.

Direct speech acts are not necessarily impolite. Here’s a dialogue between “I” and “ a soldier” of the same hometown:

I: How old are you? Solider: Nineteen. I: How many years in the army? S: One year. I: How are you drafted? S: I followed the Red Army when they retreated towards the north. ( to be continued)

I: How about your family? S: There are my father, mother, aunt, sisters, and brothers. I: Haven’t you a wife?

Such conversation involved in direct speech acts is sure to be impolite in the West because it is rather like questioning a criminal. But in Chinese everyday life, it is far from impolite because it expresses the speakers’ warmth and intimacy.