Albert Gatt LIN3021 Formal Semantics Lecture 12. In this lecture We continue (and conclude) our discussion of tense and aspect. We discuss modality.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Present Perfect.
Advertisements

Albert Gatt LIN1180– Semantics Lecture 12. In this lecture We focus on tense and grammatical aspect Progressive/non-progressive Perfective/imperfective.
Direct and Indirect Speech
Modal Verbs.
Modality Lecture 10. Language is not merely used for conveying factual information A speaker may wish to indicate a degree of certainty to try to influence.
Direct Speech Vs Indirect Speech. Three Kinds of Direct Speech displays.
Modal verbs: permission, obligation and necessity - 1 Can, must, should, ought to, had better 1. These are the most common verbs for talking about permission.
Syntax Lecture 10: Auxiliaries. Types of auxiliary verb Modal auxiliaries belong to the category of inflection – They are in complementary distribution.
CAS LX 502 4b. Tense and aspect Situations We can think of sentences as referring to situations (events, states, eventualities). A sentence like.
Basic Verb Tenses.
Verbs and situation types continued LIN1180 Semantics Lecture 11.
Albert Gatt LIN1180 – Semantics Lecture 10. Part 1 (from last week) Theories of presupposition: the semantics- pragmatics interface.
Present perfect, Simple, past and future Tenses. SIMPLE PRESENT TenseSignal wordsUseFormExamples Simple Present every day sometimes always often usually.
CAS LX 502 Semantics 9a. Tense and aspect Ch. 8 etc.
Verbs, Tense, and Auxiliaries (Plus some final information on Nouns and Pronouns)
LING 364: Introduction to Formal Semantics Lecture 26 April 20th.
Introduction to Textual Analysis. Descriptive CategoriesFields of Study Sound SystemPhonetics and Phonology Word FormationMorphology Sentence StructureSyntax.
The Semantics of VP - understanding talk about situations English Grammar BA – 2nd semester Lecture 9 Torben Thrane.
English Verb Tense Review
AuxiliariesAuxiliaries. Auxiliaries A verb used to add a functional or grammatical meaning to a clause in which it appears. Functions in a supporting.
Present and past perfect tenses
Prof. Myrna Monllor English 112
By Miguel.  Grammer  Exercise  Solutions  Questions.
Reported Speech Roll No Presented By:- Class: Ixth “A”
Sentence semantics.
Aspect and Aspectuality Robert I. Binnick
Reported Speech Dragana Filipović.
Albert Gatt LIN 3098 Corpus Linguistics. In this lecture Some more on corpora and grammar Construction Grammar as a theoretical framework Collostructional.
Aspect Lecture 11. What is the meaning of aspect?  Aspect concerns the manner in which the verbal action is experienced or regarded.  The grammatical.
Albert Gatt LIN3021 Formal Semantics Lecture 11. In this lecture Having discussed a leading theory of the semantics of events, we now consider the representation.
The L2 Acquisition of the semantics and morphology of Aspect: a study of the acquisition of the Spanish imperfect- perfective contrast by native speakers.
Present Perfect and Present Perfect Progressive Unit 3.
Perfect Forms Lecture 15. The perfective aspect ► An earlier action or state has relevance at a later reference point, or point of orientation. ► perfective.
English In motion 4 December grammar and vocabulary review Saint Louis School English Department Carlos Schwerter Garc í a.
© Child language acquisition To what extent do children acquire language by actively working out its rules?
Overview of Verb Tenses UUEG, Chapter 1. The Simple Tenses Simple Present Simple Past Simple Future These tenses make up 90% of the verb tenses we use!
Present Perfect Simple vs. Present Perfect Continuous.
Time, Tense and Aspect Rajat Kumar Mohanty Centre For Indian Language Technology Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian.
PRESENT PERFECT SIMPLE & CONTINUOUS. PRESENT PERFECT SIMPLE FORM : have / has + past participle USES : 1. LIFE EXPERIENCES (NEVER/ EVER) I’ve been to.
1 Present Perfect Continuous. 2 Form n HAVE/HAS + BEEN + -ING n Example: n I have been working. She hasn‘t been working. Have they been working? How long.
Lecture 7: Tense and Negation.  The clause is made up of distinct structural areas with different semantic purposes  The VP  One or more verbal head.
Verbs L/O: to revise/learn the function and effects of verbs to revise/learn the function and effects of verbs Quick revision: What is a modifier? What.
Time is a universal, non-linguistic concept with three divisions: past, Present and future. Tense is a linguistic concept. It is the correspondence between.
SIMPLE PAST TENSE PAST PROGRESSIVE FUTURE PROGRESSIVE PERFECT ASPECT.
PRESENT PERFECT SIMPLE & CONTINUOUS. PRESENT PERFECT SIMPLE FORM : have / has + past participle USES : 1. LIFE EXPERIENCES I’ve been to China She’s ridden.
Helping Verbs By, Jake Maloof What are the helping verbs? Well there are 23 different helping verbs and they are: am, are, was, were, being, been, have,
What is a Tense? TRUE or FALSE? There are 12 tenses in English. Right answer: Technically speaking, there are only 2: The Present Simple & the Past.
OVERVIEW OF VERB TENSE.
Direct speech is a form of sentences which use to reporting something that’s being said now. Direct speech also use to talk each other. For example: 
Inflection. Inflection refers to word formation that does not change category and does not create new lexemes, but rather changes the form of lexemes.
Tuesday, April 6, 2016 Level 3 Week 7. Announcements CASAS #2 tonight Units 8-12 test tomorrow Review for the midterm on Monday Midterm on Tuesday.
English Verb Tense Review By Smt Archana Saxena Lecturer Govt. Girls H.S.S. Shivpuri.
The Present Perfect vs The Past Simple. The Present Perfect The present perfect simple has a basic correspondence with the Spanish ‘pretérito perfecto’,
THE PAST SIMPLE TENSE The past simple tense is used for: actions or events in the past: I visited Egypt last year. actions or events which happened one.
VERB TENSES Everything you need to deal with it!!!!
Present perfect tense is a grammatical combination between the present tense and perfect tense. Type tenses in English which is used for an act of activity.
Present Perfect.
THE TENSES.
THE TENSES.
Structure of the English Language By Stacey Reilly
Josh, Xochilt, Alexandria
Verb tenses.
PAST AND PERFECT TENSES
Past Perfect Tense Past Perfect Continuous Tense
FORM PRESENT PAST FUTURE
Direct and Indirect Speech
Unit 2 Grammar Present Perfect Tense can be used in three situations: 1. To indicate something that has happened at an indefinite time in the past. I.
Presentation transcript:

Albert Gatt LIN3021 Formal Semantics Lecture 12

In this lecture We continue (and conclude) our discussion of tense and aspect. We discuss modality.

Part 1 Tense, the perfect and the progressive aspect.

A brief reminder “Aspect” is primarily about the internal dynamics of events and states, rather than their “location” in time. Lexical aspect (“aktionsart”) Cf. Vendler’s distinctions Mainly concerned with the lexical meaning of verbs (or rather, VPs) and how they specify the temporal dynamics of a situation. Sometimes referred to as “aspectual class” to distinguish it from grammatical aspect. Grammatical aspect Mainly concerned with grammatically specified aspects of the temporal dynamics. We shall focus mainly on the progressive and the perfect

Lexical aspect (Vendler) eventualities State know Greek (-telic) event Accomplishment run a marathon (+telic) (+progressive) Achievement recognise Pip (+telic) (-progressive) Activity push a cart (-telic) (+progressive)

The Past Perfect When I woke up, he’d already gone. R = the time I woke up E = the time of his going Typically, with the past perfect: R < S E < R he goes (E)I wake up (R)Speech time S

The Present Perfect Jack has been in jail for two years. There are two possible interpretations here: 1. Jack is still in jail (and has been for 2 years)  Continuative reading 2. Jack left jail a while ago (so we can say ‘he’s been in jail for 2 years’ to mean ‘he spent two years in jail at some point in the past) But compare: I’ve had dinner. Here, the continuative reading is ruled out. It seems that the continuative present perfect is only available with states.

The Present Perfect States: Continuative: Pip has been in jail for 2 years (and is there still) Non-continuative: Pip has been in jail for 2 years (but now lives in California) Events: Non-continuative: Pip has eaten his dinner. In general, with the present perfect we have: E < R R = S (the reference time is the present) But in the continuative case, we don’t have E<R, since E is ongoing.

Some puzzles with the present perfect It looks like we can’t use the present perfect in some cases: ?Einstein has discovered relativity. Does the fact that Einstein is deceased make a difference? Compare: Jack has rediscovered relativity (alone, in his bedroom) ?Paul has been released from jail yesterday. The explicit reference time provided by yesterday seems to block the perfect. Compare: Paul has been released from jail. Compare: Paul has been released from jail in the past two days (but we’re not sure which day exactly)

The progressive Jim is screaming in the street. Jim was screaming in the street (at 5pm) Present progressive: R = S (present) R  E E.g. The present moment is within the interval of Jim’s screaming. Past progressive: R < S (past) R  E (Jim was probably screaming before 5pm, and continued to scream after) This seems to depend a little on how we specify R: Jim was screaming in the street yesterday E  R?

A parallel between the progressive events and states? R  E is what we observed for states in the non-progressive case: R  E Jim is screaming in the street R  E Jim has a cold Notice that states can’t occur in the progressive: ?Jim is having a cold. Does this mean that the progressive is turning the event into a state?

Telicity Telic VPs usually have an end-point: Jim crossed the street I mowed the lawn These are Vendler’s accomplishments (and achievements) But in the progressive, we seem to “suspend” the requirement of an endpoint: Jim was crossing the street (when he was hit by a bus) I was mowing the lawn (when I spotted Sue roasting a pheasant)...

Completion Some progressives (with accomplishments) are never completed: Jim was crossing the street when he was hit by a bus. It’s no longer the case that R  E here: If E is the time of the event of crossing the street, then it never really comes to an end because it’s (sadly) interrupted. Paradox: accomplishements have end-points (+telic), but this one doesn’t reach its end-point! Dowty (1977) noted that we can’t have the whole story just by thinking of the relationship between R and E. Effectively, Dowty’s analysis takes into account alternatives (i.e. other worlds where the event does complete).

Dowty on the progressive Jim was crossing the street when he was hit by a bus. In the actual world, the event doesn’t terminate: But in other, conceivable worlds, it might (i.e.we can conceive of worlds where Jim is not hit by a bus). (And in yet others, it might be interrupted even earlier.) In short, we can imagine situations where the occurrence of the street crossing, relative to the bus hitting Jim, varies. Event of crossing the street Bus hits Jim Endpoint of event (not reached)

Inertia worlds Dowty gives special importance to those worlds where the event does reach its end point. He calls these inertia worlds – worlds where things continue to their normal completion. Actual world: Jim was crossing the street when a bus hit him. Inertia worlds: Jim crossed the street. (Crucially, we can use the non-progressive in inertial worlds, because the event does complete) So what is the meaning of the progressive? The progressive sentence S describes an event e in w iff the non- progressive sentence S’ describes the same event e for all inertia worlds.

What this says about progressives According to Dowty’s theory, the progressive utilises modality for those cases where: A non-progressive sentence won’t describe the event in the actual world (for example, because it’s interrupted, or because we don’t know if it actually terminated). In this case, we create a sentence using the progressive to describe the event as it would happen in case it did come to its end point. Note: the whole point of this analysis is that in order to understand the progressive, we need to understand the event that’s being talked about, as if it happened in the normal way.

Summary Tense can be analysed as a relation between three times: R, S, E In this way, we also observe some interesting parallels with anaphoric NPs Grammatical and lexical aspect can alter the temporal relationships.

Part 2 Modality

Where does modality crop up? Like tense and aspect, modality often has to do with events: Tense: the time point (relative to a reference time and a speech time) of the event Aspect: the internal “constituency” of the event (duration, telicity etc) Modality mostly concerns either: the status of the proposition expressing the event E.g. Is it something we’re certain of? The status of the event itself E.g. Is it something which should be done?

Possible worlds play an essential role A proposition denotes those worlds in which it is true. Alternatively, we view the proposition as a function from worlds, to truth values (the characteristic function of the set) Proposition means Worlds in which the proposition is true

A few comparisons (I) Situation: Jacqui is known by her flatmate Tricia to be a bit of a slob. Tricia walks into the flat with Sam, and finds a mess. Intuitively, what would you say is the difference between: 1. Jacqui was here this morning. 2. Jacqui must have been here this morning. 3. Jacqui may have been here this morning. 4. Jacqui might have been here this morning. In (2-4), unlike the bald assertion (1), the speaker seems to be asserting a proposition together with a statement of the evidence for its truth.

“Modals” and other sources of modality The example relies on the so-called modal auxiliaries (may, must etc). But the semantic category of modality crops up in other places, especially with adverbs: Jacqui was definitely here Possibly, Jacqui was here... Semantically, we should not exclude the possibility that some of what we say about modal auxiliaries applies equally well to these adverbs.

A few comparisons (II) Situation: Jacqui gets back home and finds Tricia glowering in the kitchen. 1. You didn’t clean the kitchen. 2. You must clean the kitchen. 3. You should clean the kitchen. In (2-3), there is an expression of the degree of obligation in the event. In (1), there is simply the assertion of a proposition concerning the event (which didn’t happen).

“Modals” and other sources of modality Again, the example relies on the so-called modal auxiliaries but the same can be expressed in other ways: You are required to clean the kitchen You are obliged to clean the kitchen... Semantically, we should not exclude the possibility that some of what we say about modal auxiliaries applies equally well to these adverbs.

A few comparisons (III) Situation: Jacqui, after a gruelling four-hour cleaning marathon, is exhausted. Tricia: 1. You can stop now. 2. You may stop now. Situation: Jacqui, observing Tricia during her marathon: 3. Man, you can clean! In (1-2) we have something like “permission” Notice that the same auxiliary (can) is used to ability (willingness?), rather than permission, in (3).

Types of modality Epistemic: Related to knowledge, evidence etc Focuses on the evidence for a proposition Jacqui must have been here (her clothes are all over the kitchen floor) Deontic/dynamic Focuses on the status of the event expressed by a proposition. Deontic: related to permission or obligation, typically arising from sources external to the subject You must clean the kitchen You can go now Dynamic: related to ability and/or willingness Jacqui can run several miles without stopping.

Some preliminaries All the cases we’ve discussed involve propositions about events which don’t (or didn’t) occur. We are in the realm of possibility/necessity/ability etc. The possibility/necessity of something may arise from various sources: Evidence/knowledge Obligation/permission Ability/willingness In general, our understanding of modality requires us to understand both the force and the source.

Why possible worlds? In all of these cases, we are envisaging situations which may be different from the way the actual world is: All students should study at least six hours a day This may not be the case in the actual world, i.e. Alternatives are conceivable. The problem for semantics: How do we account compositionally for a proposition which is modal? The possible worlds framework allows us to conceive of the alternatives involved fairly straightforwardly.

Part 3 Possible worlds analysis of modality: an example

Example sentence Suppose someone utters: Stanley must have nicked the car. Suppose there are four facts that constitute the evidence: The car is not parked where it should be. The speaker was not driving the car. Stanley left his cigarette lighter, engraved with his name. There is a big footprint on the pavement and Stanley is the only person with a size 48 shoe in the town.

Example sentence Suppose someone utters: Stanley must have nicked the car. Suppose there are four facts that constitute the evidence: The car is not parked where it should be. The speaker was not driving the car. Stanley left his cigarette lighter, engraved with his name. There is a big footprint on the pavement and Stanley is the only person with a size 48 shoe in the town. Notice that each of these facts is itself a proposition. The proposition denotes a set of worlds, those in which it’s true.

The facts as sets of worlds Fact 1: car not parked Fact 2: speaker didn’t drive Fact 3: cigarette lighter Fact 4: footprint The worlds where all the facts are true

We’re not quite there yet... Stanley must have stolen the car. Relevant proposition: Stanley stole the car. The way we reason about the “must” statement is that the proposition Stanley stole the car is likely to be true given the facts. So we assume that those worlds in which Stanley did steal the car must overlap quite considerably with those where all four facts are true. But they don’t necessarily overlap completely: E.g. It’s possible that S stole the car in a world where it is true that he left his lighter, but none of the other facts are true.

The facts as sets of worlds Fact 1: car not parked Fact 2: speaker didn’t drive Fact 3: cigarette lighter Fact 4: footprint The worlds where all the facts are true

The facts as sets of worlds Fact 1: car not parked Fact 2: speaker didn’t drive Fact 3: cigarette lighter Fact 4: footprint The worlds where all the facts are trueThe worlds where Stanley stole the car

The main issue The interpretation of a sentence with a model depends on the identification of which possible worlds are relevant to its truth or falsity. How do we accomplish this? The modal verb gives a clue. (e.g. Must works differently from may). But this isn’t sufficient. Compare: Stanley must have stolen the car. Relevant worlds: those in which the evidence holds. Stanley must give away all his belongings. Relevant worlds: those in which morally good actions are done. So the hearer must be relying on something else, apart from grammatical form.

A bit of pragmatics The identification of relevant worlds is in part a pragmatic matter: the hearer must know (from the context etc) which worlds are relevant. Example: The rich should give money to the poor. Relevant worlds: those in which certain ethical principles hold. NB: these principles don’t have to hold in our own world! (They do, but our world could have been different) The speaker who utters this is clearly assuming that her listeners know which worlds these are.

So is the sentence true? The rich should give money to the poor. If we take the perspective of our world, we need to identify those other worlds where the same ethical standards hold. If we take the perspective of a different world (say w’), we need to identify other worlds where the ethical standards of w’ hold. (So the truth of some modals depends on the perspective we adopt. That’s why deontics tend to be arguable.)

So is the sentence true? The rich should give money to the poor. If we want to interpret this sentence from the point of view of world w, we need to identify those possible worlds which are relevant to the truth of the sentence in w. In other words: those worlds which are accessible to w given the relevant standards, knowledge etc.

Accessibility relations Let’s suppose we have worlds where: people behave charitably: w1, w2, w3 people behave greedily: w4, w5, w6 nobody has anything: w7 charity is sanctioned by moral principles: w1, w5 greed is sanctioned by moral principles: w2, w4 having nothing is sanctioned: w3, w6, w7 w1 w2 w3 w4 w5 w6 w7 Note: worlds can be accessible to themselves... Example: W1 is a world where charity is good and where people behave charitably. Interpreting our sentence in w1 means we have to take into account those other worlds where people behave charitably.

Accessibility relations Our sentence is true in some world if all the worlds accessible to it are ones where rich people give money to the poor. Accessible worlds: w1 itself, plus w2 and w3 w1 w2 w3 w4 w5 w6 w7 Note: worlds can be accessible to themselves...

Why do accessibility relations matter? The notion of an “accessible” world can help to distinguish between the kinds of modality we observed at the start: Deontic relations pick out those worlds which are “good” or “correct” according to some (predefined) principle(s). Examples: should, must Epistemic ones pick out those worlds where what is known to be true holds.

Force The other thing that distinguishes modals is their “strength”: Must is “stronger” than may Etc In the possible worlds framework, a “stronger” modal is one which makes several worlds accessible for its interpretation.