Week 7b. Language Universals, part one CAS LX 400 Second Language Acquisition.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
(Say each word as it appears on the screen.)
Advertisements

(Say each word as it appears on the screen.)
Frequency Words.
Unit 9 Saving the earth Grammar--Inversion.
Come.
List 1 Sight Words.
Psych 156A/ Ling 150: Acquisition of Language II Lecture 12 Poverty of the Stimulus I.
Defining Syntax. Lec What is Syntax? O Syntax is the scientific study of sentence structure O Science: methodology of study O Hypothesis  observation.
Week 3a. UG and L2A: Background, principles, parameters CAS LX 400 Second Language Acquisition.
High-Frequency Words Second Grade Room B10.
Grammar = Connection Girl the a Monday fell found feather then on she revery into and. The girl found a feather on Monday and then she fell into revery.
NOUN CLAUSE Noun clauses as the name implies, function as nouns. That is, they are word groups with their own subject and verb that in turn function as.
Unit 13: Relative Pronouns
Week 10. Transfer and the “initial state” for L2A, plus some language universals for good measure GRS LX 700 Language Acquisition and Linguistic Theory.
CAS LX b. Questions. Seeking truth Much of what we’ve done this semester has to do with characterizing (our knowledge of) the conditions under which.
© red ©
Week 12. Language Universals, and the beginnings of a model GRS LX 700 Language Acquisition and Linguistic Theory.
Research on teaching and learning pronunciation
Dolch Vocabulary Words
The.
220 Dolch Words.
Second Language Acquisition Theories Week 6. Contrastive Analysis Hypothesis (CAH) Theoretical bases: structural linguistics and behaviourist psychology.
Psych 156A/ Ling 150: Acquisition of Language II Lecture 16 Language Structure II.
Created by Verna C. Rentsch and Joyce Cooling Nelson School
Contrastive analysis: an Overview Raung-fu Chung Based on Thu Nguyen.
I am ready to test!________ I am ready to test!________
Sight Words.
Dr. Monira Al-Mohizea MORPHOLOGY & SYNTAX WEEK 11.
Complete Dolch Sight Word List Preprimer through Third
Find the Letters Find the letters on your keyboard or Pre-Keys Play Pads to make the following word lists as they appear on the screen. Use your left hand.
High Frequency Word Phrases
High Frequency Word Phrases
Parts of Speech Notes. Part of Speech: Nouns  A naming word  Names a person, place, thing, idea, living creature, quality, or idea Examples: cowboy,
Dolch Vocabulary Words
BLT # go help look at run.
The. to and a I you it in said for up look.
Dolch list for Ms. Hrouda’s Class!. List 1 the was.
Sight Word List.
Dolch Word List Directions: This is the Dolch words list. They are 220 words that occur frequently in reading. Your child should be able to recognize.
Universal Grammar Functional Approaches
Multi Sensory Grammar Color Coding Sentences. Nouns Nouns-They tell us things. They are the names of people, places, things, or ideas. They are colored.
2.3 Markedness Differential Hypothesis (MDH)
Sight Words.
The Writing Process Basic Sentence Structure Complete Sentences Types of Sentences Fragments Run-Ons Paragraphs Elements of a Paragraph Outlining.
1 Syntax 1. 2 In your free time Look at the diagram again, and try to understand it. Phonetics Phonology Sounds of language Linguistics Grammar MorphologySyntax.
Dolch 220 Sharks! a is it am to an red up.
Sight Words and are a I can for go have he.
Popcorn Words blue orange eight red purple nine.
Second Grade Dolch Words egreay. a and away big.
Dolch Word List Directions: This is the Dolch words list. They are 220 words that occur frequently in reading. Your child should be able to recognize.
Dolch Word List By: Beth Terracina. Preprimmer a.
Typological Universals & Second Language Acquisition (Eckman, 2012: ) The goal of SLA theory: to explain the development of linguistic competence.
A. Kindergarten Dolch List 2013 Sight Words am are.
A. and away big blue can come down find for.
OUTLINE Language Universals -Definition
The Teachability Hypothesis. Stages of acquisition of morpho-syntactic structures follow a set developmental order. Stages cannot be skipped as a result.
QUESTIONS & NEGATIVES.
Theoretical Discussion on the
2nd Language Learning Chapter 2 Lecture 4.
Watch Pete the Cat here:
Sight Word Lists (141 words)
New Horizon College English II
Like.
Sight Word Test.
What Color is it?.
Traditional Grammar VS. Generative Grammar
Grammar SENTENCES – PART 1.
Linguistic aspects of interlanguage
Sight Words
Presentation transcript:

Week 7b. Language Universals, part one CAS LX 400 Second Language Acquisition

Typological universals 1960’s and 1970’s saw a lot of activity aimed at identifying language universals, properties of Language. Class of possible languages is smaller than you might think. If a language has one property (A), it will necessarily have another (B). –+A+B, –A–B, –A+B but never +A–B.

(Typological) universals All languages have vowels. If a language has VSO as its basic word order, then it has prepositions (vs. postpositions). VSO? Adposition type Yes (VSO)No PrepositionsWelshEnglish PostpositionsNoneJapanese

Markedness Having duals implies having plurals Having plurals says nothing about having duals. Having duals is marked—infrequent, more complex. Having plurals is (relative to having duals) unmarked. Generally markedness is in terms of comparable dimensions, but you could also say that being VSO is marked relative to having prepositions.

Berlin & Kay 1969: Color terms (On the boundaries of psychophysics, linguistics, anthropology, and with issues about its interpretation, but still…) Basic color terms across languages. It turns out that languages differ in how many color terms count as basic. (blueish, salmon-colored, crimson, blond, … are not basic).

Berlin & Kay 1969: Color terms The segmentation of experience by speech symbols is essentially arbitrary. The different sets of words for color in various languages are perhaps the best ready evidence for such essential arbitrariness. For example, in a high percentage of African languages, there are only three “color words,” corresponding to our white, black, red, which nevertheless divide up the entire spectrum. In the Tarahumara language of Mexico, there are five basic color words, and here “blue” and “green” are subsumed under a single term. –Eugene Nida (1959)

Berlin & Kay 1969: Color terms Arabic (Lebanon) Bulgarian (Bulgaria) Catalan (Spain) Cantonese (China) Mandarin (China) English (US) Hebrew (Israel) Hungarian (Hungary) Ibibo (Nigeria) Indonesian (Indonesia) Japanese (Japan) Korean (Korea) Pomo (California) Spanish (Mexico) Swahili (East Africa) Tagalog (Philippines) Thai (Thailand) Tzeltal (Southern Mexico) Urdu (India) Vietnamese (Vietnam)

Eleven possible basic color terms White, black, red, green, yellow, blue, brown, purple, pink, orange, gray. All languages contain term for white and black. Has 3 terms, contains a term for red. Has 4 terms, contains green or yellow. Has 5 terms, contains both green and yellow. Has 6 terms, contains blue. Has 7 terms, contains brown. Has 8 or more terms, chosen from {purple, pink, orange, gray}

Color hierarchy White, black Red Green, yellow Blue Brown Purple, pink, orange, gray Even assuming these 11 basic color terms, there should be 2048 possible sets—but only 22 (1%) are attested.

Color terms BWJalé (New Guinea) ‘brilliant’ vs. ‘dull’ BWRTiv (Nigeria), Australian aboriginals in Seven Rivers District, Queensland. BWRGIbibo (Nigeria), Hanunóo (Philippines) BWRYIbo (Nigeria), Fitzroy River people (Queensland) BWRYGTzeltal (Mexico), Daza (eastern Nigeria) BWRYGUPlains Tamil (South India), Nupe (Nigeria), Mandarin? BWRYGUO Nez Perce (Washington), Malayalam (southern India)

Color terms Interesting questions abound, including why this order, why these eleven—and there are potential reasons for it that can be drawn from the perception of color spaces which we will not attempt here. The point is: This is a fact about Language: If you have a basic color term for blue, you also have basic color terms for black, white, red, green, and yellow.

Implicational hierarchy This is a ranking of markedness or an implicational hierarchy. Having blue is more marked than having (any or all of) yellow, green, red, white, and black. Having green is more marked than having red… Like a set of implicational universals… –Blue implies yellowBrown implies blue –Blue implies greenPink implies brown –Yellow or green imply red Orange implies brown –Red implies blackGray implies brown –Red implies whitePurple implies brown

L2A? Our overarching theme: How much is L2/IL like a L1? Do IL/L2 languages obey the language universals that hold of native languages? This question is slightly less theory-laden than the questions we were asking about principles and parameters, although it’s similar… To my knowledge nobody has studied L2 acquisitions of color terms…

Question formation Declarative: John will buy coffee. Wh-inversion: What will John buy? Wh-fronting: What will John buy? Yes/No-inversion: Will John buy coffee? Greenberg (1963): –Wh-inversion implies Wh-fronting. –Yes/No-inversion implies Wh-inversion.

Wh-inversion  Wh-fronting English, German: Both. –What will John buy? Japanese Korean: neither. –John will buy what? Finnish: Wh-fronting only. –What John will buy? Unattested: Wh-inversion only. –*Will John buy what?

Y/N-inversion  Wh-inversion English: Both –Will John buy coffee? What will John buy? Japanese: Neither –John will buy coffee? John will buy what? Lithuanian: Wh-inversion only. –John will buy coffee? What will John buy? Unattested: Y/N-inversion only. –Will John buy coffee? What John will buy?

Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989) L1: Korean (4), Japanese (6), Turkish (4) L2: English Note L1s chosen because they are neither/neither type languages, to avoid questions of transfer. Subjects tried to determine what was going on in a scene by asking questions.

Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989) Example Y/N Qs: –Did she finished two bottle wine? –Is Lou and Patty known each other? –Sue does drink orange juice? –Her parents are rich? –Is this story is chronological in a order? –Does Joan has a husband? –Yesterday is Sue did drink two bottles of wine?

Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989) Example Wh-Qs: –Why Sue didn’t look solution for her problem? –Where Sue is living? –Why did Sue stops drinking? –Why is Patty’s going robbing the bank? –What they are radicals? –What Sue and Patty connection? –Why she was angry?

Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989) wh-inversion implies wh-fronting? results %WHINV%WHFR SMK25NO100YES UAT54NO100YES TSJ70NO100YES MKK80NO100YES ROJ88NO100YES KOJ95YES100YES MHJ95YES100YES NET95YES100YES SIJ95YES100YES GT100YES100YES MAT100YES100YES STJ100YES100YES TMK100YES100YES YKJ100YES100YES

Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989) YN-inversion implies wh-inversion? results %YNINV%WHINV SMK8NO25NO MKK38NO80NO YKJ51NO100YES TSJ67NO70NO TMK83NO100YES ROJ85NO88NO BGT86NO100YES MAT88NO100YES UAT91YES54NO KOJ93YES95YES MHJ95YES95YES NET100YES95YES SIJ100YES95YES STJ100YES100YES

Eckman, Moravcsik, Wirth (1989) Yes/no inversion Wh-inversion Yes (VS)No (SV) Yes (VS)54 No (SV)14

Eckman’s Markedness Differential Hypothesis Markedness. A phenomenon or structure X in some language is relatively more marked than some other phenomenon or structure Y if cross- linguistically the presence of X in a language implies the presence of Y, but the presence of Y does not imply the presence of X. –Duals imply plurals. –Wh-inversion implies wh-fronting. –Blue implies red.

Markedness Differential Hypothesis MDH: The areas of difficulty that a second language learner will have can be predicted on the basis of a comparison of the NL and TL such that: –Those areas of the TL that are different from the NL and are relatively more marked than in the NL will be difficult; –The degree of difficulty associated with those aspects of the TL that are different and more marked than in the NL corresponds to the relative degree of markedness associated with those aspects; –Those areas of the TL that are different than the NL but are not relatively more marked than in the NL will not be difficult.

MDH vs. CAH –Those areas of the TL that are different from the NL and are relatively more marked than in the NL will be difficult; The MDH is a bit better than its predecessor, the Contrastive Analysis Hypothesis because it anticipates (and attempts to systematically predict) that not every difference between TL and NL cause learners difficulty.

MDH example: Word-final segments Voiced obstruentsmost marked Surge Voiceless obstruentsCoke Sonorant consonantsMountain Vowelsleast marked Coffee All Ls allow vowels word-finally—some only allow vowels. Some (e.g., Mandarin, Japanese) allow only vowels and sonorants. Some (e.g., Polish) allow vowels, sonorants, but only voiceless obstruents. English allows all four types.

Eckman (1981) Spanish L1Mandarin L1 GlossIL formGlossIL form Bob[b p]Tag[tæg ] Bobby[b bi]And[ænd ] Red [r  t] Wet[w t] Wet[w t]Deck [d  k] Sick[s I k]Letter [l  t r] Bleeding[blid I n] c c e e e e e

MDH example: Word-final segments Voiced obstruentsmost marked Surge Voiceless obstruentsCoke Sonorant consonantsMountain Vowelsleast marked Coffee Idea: Mandarin has neither voiceless nor voiced obstruents in the L1—using a voiceless obstruent in place of a TL voiced obstruent is still not L1 compliant and is a big markedness jump. Adding a vowel is L1 compliant. Spanish has voiceless obstruents, to using a voiceless obstruent for a TL voiced obstruent is L1 compliant.

MDH and IL The MDH presupposes that the IL obeys the implicational universals too. Eckman et al. (1989) suggests that this is at least reasonable. The MDH suggests that there is a natural order of L2A along a markedness scale (stepping to the next level of markedness is easiest). Let’s consider what it means that an IL obeys implicational universals…

MDH and IL IL obeys implicational universals. That is, we know that IL is a language. So, we know that languages are such that having word-final voiceless obstruents implies that you also have word-final sonorant consonants, among other things. What would happen if we taught Japanese L2 learners of English only—and at the outset—voiced obstruents?

Generalizing with markedness scales Voiced obstruentsmost marked Surge Voiceless obstruentsCoke Sonorant consonantsMountain Vowelsleast marked Coffee Japanese learner of English will have an easier time at each step learning voiceless obstruents and then voiced obstruents. But—if taught voiced obstruents immediately, the fact that the IL obeys implicational (markedness) universals means that voiceless obstruents “come for free.”

Nifty! Does it work? Does it help? Answers seem to be: –Yes, it seems to at least sort of work. –Maybe it helps. Point is: Learning a marked structure is harder. So, if you learn a marked structure, you can automatically generalize to the less marked structures, but was it faster than learning the easier steps in succession would have been?

Change between pre- & post-test Eckman, Bell, and Nelson (1988)

The Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy Keenan & Comrie (1977) observed a hierarchy among the kinds of relative clauses that languages allow. The astronaut [(that) I met yesterday]. Head noun: astronaut Modifying clause: (that/who) I met — yesterday. Compare: I met the astronaut yesterday. This is an object relative because the place where the head noun would be in the simple sentence version is th object.

The Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy There are several kinds of relative clauses, based on where the head noun “comes from” in the modifying clause: The astronaut… –[I met — yesterday]object –[who — met me yesterday]subject –[I gave a book to —]indirect object –[I was talking about —]obj. of P –[whose house I like —]Genitive (possessor) –[I am braver than —]obj. of comparative

The Noun Phrase Accessibility Hierarchy Turns out: Languages differ in what positions they allow relative clauses to be formed on. English allows all the positions mentioned to be used to make relative clauses. Arabic allows relative clauses to be formed only with subjects. Greek allows relative clauses to be formed only with subjects or objects.

Resumptive pronouns The guy who they don’t know whether he wants to come. A student who I can’t make any sense out of the papers he writes. The actress who Tom wondered whether her father was rich. In cases where relative clause formation is not allowed, it can sometimes be salvaged by means of a pronoun in the position that the head noun is to be associated with.

NPAH and resumptive pronouns Generally speaking, it turns out that in languages which do not allow relative clauses to be formed off a certain position, they will instead allow relative clauses with a resumptive pronoun in that position. Arabic: allows only subject relative clauses. But for all other positions allows a resumptive pronoun construction, analogous to: –The book that John bought it. –The tree that John is standing by it. –The astronaut that John gave him a present.

NPAH The positions off which you can relativize appears to be an implicational hierarchy. LanguageSUBDOIOOPGENOCOMP Arabic–+++++ Greek––+? ++ Japanese––––+/ – Persian–(+)++++

NPAH in L2A Very widely studied implicational universal in L2A—many people have addressed the question of whether the IL obeys the NPAH and whether teaching aa marked structure can help. Eckman et al. (1989) was about this second question…

Change between pre- & post-test Eckman, Bell, and Nelson (1988)

Next week Anna Do, graduate student in the Applied Linguistics program here at BU, has looked at this question focusing on English speakers learning Korean, trying to determine (a) whether the learners’ IL obey the NPAH, and (b) to what extent there is transfer of the position of the L1 on the NPAH to the IL (where the TL is at a different position). Next week, she’ll be here to tell us about her experiment and her results.

            