MAICS Cincinnati 2012 April 21-22, 2012. Why does « acceptance » deserve your attention? Used in a descriptive way to characterize a system’s knowledge.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers.
Advertisements

Joe Levines Purple Haze. Physical/Phenomenal Gaps P = the complete microphysical truth Q = a phenomenal truth Q1: Is there an epistemic gap between.
Hyperintensionality and Impossible Worlds: An Introduction
Passage Based Reading for the Sat
The Extended Mind.
Theories of Knowledge Knowledge is Justified-True-Belief Person, S, knows a proposition, y, iff: Y is true; S believes y; Y is justified for S. (Note:
Naturalizing epistemic norms May 16, Why does « acceptance » deserve attention? Used in a descriptive way to characterize a systems knowledge in.
By Anthony Campanaro & Dennis Hernandez
Authority and Democracy
Value conflicts and assumptions - 1 While an author usually offers explicit reasons why he comes to a certain conclusion, he also makes (implicit) assumptions.
The Logic of Intelligence Pei Wang Department of Computer and Information Sciences Temple University.
Intelligence Give a definition of intelligence that you could defend, explaining why you believe you could defend it. Give examples of ways your definition.
Thinking Critically in Psychology Introduction to Psychology Simon Fraser University.
SESSION-4: RESPECTING OTHERS AS HUMAN BEINGS. What is “respect”? Respect has great importance in everyday life Belief: all people are worthy of respect.
1 Intuitive Irrationality: Reasons for Unreason. 2 Epistemology Branch of philosophy focused on how people acquire knowledge about the world Descriptive.
Abby Yinger Mathematics o Statistics o Decision Theory.
Chapter 10.  Real life problems are usually different than just estimation of population statistics.  We try on the basis of experimental evidence Whether.
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education Chapter 5 Individual Perception and Decision- Making 5-1 Essentials of Organizational Behavior, 11/e Global Edition.
Ethical Decision Making
The Problems of Knowledge
How Can Knowledge Be Justified?
Social Cognition AP Psychology.
Definitions – John Dewey
Argumentation - 1 We often encounter situations in which someone is trying to persuade us of a point of view by presenting reasons for it. We often encounter.
2013/2014 RELATIONS OF CHAPTER “EMOTIONS” (In the Book of Robert Nozick “Examined Life”) Lezione 22 31/3/14 by Gabriele Buratti & Maria Teresa Carini.
Deontological tradition Contractualism of John Rawls Discourse ethics.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
Section VI: Comprehension Teaching Reading Sourcebook 2 nd edition.
Are noetic feelings a potential source of epistemic entitlement? Joëlle Proust institut Jean-Nicod Paris EPISTEMOLOGY WORKSHOP.
Error theory Michael Lacewing
Philosophy 148 Moral Arguments. The first of many distinctions: Descriptive (what the text calls ‘non-moral’) versus Normative (what the text calls ‘moral’)
1 Dr. Jerrell T. Stracener EMIS 7370 STAT 5340 Probability and Statistics for Scientists and Engineers Department of Engineering Management, Information.
Thinking Actively in a Social Context T A S C.
Learning Objectives. Objectives Objectives: By the conclusion to this session each participant should be able to… Differentiate between a goal and objectives.
Copyright ©2011 Pearson Education
SLB /04/07 Thinking and Communicating “The Spiritual Life is Thinking!” (R.B. Thieme, Jr.)
Rationality Through Reasoning John Broome. When someone believes she ought to F, often her belief causes her to intend to F. How does that happen? Call.
“There's intelligent life on other planets.” Would you accept this claim? Accept the claim as TRUE Reject the claim as FALSE SUSPEND JUDGMENT.
Making a Claim Grounds for Claim Evaluation Beyond Brainstorm.
BUS 290: Critical Thinking for Managers
Kant and Moral Duties.  We don’t require moral theory(ies) to tell us that lying and homicide are wrong, and helping those in need is a good thing.
Formal Models in AGI Research Pei Wang Temple University Philadelphia, USA.
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
Chapter 6 Attitudes.
Responsible Engineers Framing the Problem. How do we address a problem? When addressing an ethical dilemma, we usually experience moral disagreement and.
- Recall / Recognition - - Forgetting.  Identify several memory retrieval processes.  Explain the processes involved in forgetting.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
02 Truth and Rationality Philosophy. 2 Part I: Sentences and Propositions.
Philosophy 224 What is a Theory of Human Nature?.
Worries about Ethics Norms & Descriptions. Hume’s gap In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark'd, that the author.
1 Lesson 4 Attitudes. 2 Lesson Outline   Last class, the self and its presentation  What are attitudes?  Where do attitudes come from  How are they.
Academic Reading ENG 115.
 An article review is written for an audience who is knowledgeable in the subject matter instead of a general audience  When writing an article review,
Randolph Clarke Florida State University. Free will – or freedom of the will – is often taken to be a power of some kind.
Miracles: Hume and Howard-Snyder. * For purposes of initial clarity, let's define a miracle as a worldly event that is not explicable by natural causes.
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Prentice Hall 9-1 # Copyright © 2015 Pearson Education, Inc. Leadership and Decision Making 9.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
Six Steps To Problem Solving A simple systematic approach to problems and issues faced by students By MK NKWANE g15N7271 TUESDAY GROUP.
Writing a Classical Argument
Decision Making ET 305, Spring 2016
The Toulmin Method. Why Toulmin…  Based on the work of philosopher Stephen Toulmin.  A way to analyze the effectiveness of an argument.  A way to respond.
Ethics and Moral reasoning
Moral Theory Review.
Formulate the Research Problem
Dr Nick Hutcheon SWAP East Co-ordinator
Section VI: Comprehension
Introduction to Logic Lecture 1 What is Critical Reasoning?
Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece
Evaluating Deductive Arguments
Presentation transcript:

MAICS Cincinnati 2012 April 21-22, 2012

Why does « acceptance » deserve your attention? Used in a descriptive way to characterize a system’s knowledge in terms of propositional contents and attitudes such as beliefs and desires (« belief box » paradigm) Semantic problems arise when treating acceptance as a belief-like attitude Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20122

Why does « acceptance » deserve your attention? Descriptive accuracy requires IA designers to explore how cognitive agency determines attitude selection and relation of attitude content to decision to act on it. Dynamics of cognitive agency imposes recognizing the various epistemic dimensions relevant to cognitive revision Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20123

Outline 1. Introduction: epistemic norms and their relation with mental actions. 2. Why is acceptance problematic? 3. A two-tiered view of acceptance: 4 ideas 1. Complex mental actions 2. Instrumental selection of epistemic norms 3. Epistemic evaluation autonomous 4. Strategic acceptance: final say 4. Conclusion: 3 types of error in accepting Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20124

Epistemic norms and their relation with mental actions Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20125

Mental actions = ways of controlling one’s cognitive activity. Examples: controlled memory (versus automatic memory) Perceptual attention (vs passive registering) Accepting (versus automatically believing) Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20126

Epistemic norms determine which mental action is being performed Example: trying to remember accurately who was there at a meeting: correction requires no false positives, but tolerates omissions. Trying to remember exhaustively who was there at a meeting: correction tolerates false positives, but requires no omission.  two distinct cognitive actions, which respond to different norms. Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20127

What are epistemic norms? The normative feature of epistemic norms derives from the structure of action being polarized (success vs failure) A given norm is what regulates self-evaluation, i.e. action monitoring. the computational and semantic properties underlying the various norms derive from the various dimensions of information which can be profitably controlled and monitored in mental agency (through metacognition) Joëlle Proust - MAICS 20128

9

No consensus about the norm(s) of acceptances Velleman (2000) regarding a proposition P as true, even though it may not be "really true” Cohen (1992): "a policy for reasoning, (..) the policy of taking it as a premise that P”. Stalnaker (1987): “Sometimes it is reasonable to accept something that one knows or believes to be false” Bratman (1999): “Acceptances conjoin epistemic and practical goals”. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Why is accepting contextual? It is left unclear how a context of acceptance can be construed in a way that justifies applying fluctuating epistemic standards. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Puzzles about acceptance The lottery paradox (Kyburg, 1961, p. 197) arises from considering a fair 1000 ticket lottery with one winning ticket: It is rational to accept that some ticket will win, while also accepting that ticket 1, 2 etc. will not win.  Aggregating acceptances results in inconsistency Joëlle Proust - MAICS

The preface paradox A writer may rationally accept that each statement in his book is true, while at the same time rationally accepting that his book contains at least one error (Makinson 1965).  Aggregating acceptances again results in inconsistency Joëlle Proust - MAICS

A slippery slope between truth and utility? Some authors seem to consider that acceptance conjoins epistemic and instrumental norms, which questions the very notion of having epistemic norms in the first place (what if truth can be accommodated according to utility?) Joëlle Proust - MAICS

« For almost twenty years there have been signs that the theory of rational acceptance suffers from deep foundational difficulties. These difficulties ultimately call into question the very intelligibility of what we are saying when we say of someone that she accepts a proposition ». Mark Kaplan (1981) Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Although a simple mental action cannot be subject both to epistemic and non-epistemic norms, a complex action can Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Discussion: how do epistemic actions contribute to world-directed action? An epistemic action is usually embedded in an instrumental (world- directed) action. For example: In order to shop for food, I need to remember the items on the list (which I forgot to bring with me). Joëlle Proust - MAICS

The epistemic norm guiding a mental action is selected on the basis of the ultimate goal of the world-directed action Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Example: The particular strategy of remembering (exhaustivity/accuracy) is selected for instrumental reasons. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Epistemic action: Epistemic norm(s) Instrumental action: norm of utility Joëlle Proust - MAICS

A wide variety of epistemic norms are available to control cognitive activity Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Norms for acceptance: Accuracy (memory, reasoning) Comprehensiveness or exhaustiveness (memory, reasoning) Coherence (fiction, demonstrative reasoning) Consensus (negociation) Relevance (conversation) Intelligibility or fluency (perceptual judgment, epistemic vigilance) Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Context determined by the relation between epistemic norm and strategy Utility dictates that a given norm will be used to control cognitive activity given one’s ultimate goal. Context is determined by selecting a cognitive action as relevant to an ultimate goal. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

A cognitive action is successful iff the corresponding epistemic norm is actually satisfied. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Selecting a norm for instrumental reasons does not influence correctness Agents' epistemic confidence in accepting n P (accepting P under norm n) is not influenced by the cost or benefit associated with being wrong or right: the epistemic content is not influenced by utility. Thus we don't need to endorse the view that an epistemic acceptance of P is yielding to utility considerations, as Bratman suggests. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Solution of lottery puzzle An agent accepts at (as accurate truth) that there is one winning ticket in the one thousand tickets actually sold She does not need to accept pl (as plausible or likely) that the single ticket she wants to buy will be the winning one. There is no contradiction between the two acceptances, because they respond to different epistemic norms. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Solution of the preface puzzle The author's epistemic goal is one of offering an ideally comprehensive presentation of his subject matter: she can accept ct (comprehensive truth) that her book includes all the truths relevant to her subject, while accepting pl (accepting as plausible or likely) that one of her claims is false. Hence, a mental act of acceptance ct does not allow aggregation of truth, because its aim is exhaustive (include all the relevant truths) rather than accurate truth (include only truths). Joëlle Proust - MAICS

From epistemic to strategic acceptance Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Why strategic acceptance ? A subject may or not decide to act on his/her epistemic acceptance, depending on the risk and benefit at stake. Utility does not just influence the selection of certain epistemic norms of acceptance. It also influences decision to act in a way that may depart greatly from the cognitive output of epistemic acceptance. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Conceptual argument The existence of an autonomous level of epistemic acceptance enables agents to have a stable epistemic map that is independent from local and unstable instrumental considerations.  It is functionally adaptive to prevent the contents of epistemic evaluation from being affected by utility and risk. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Argument from metacognitive studies (Koriat and Goldsmith, 1996) In situations where agents are forced to conduct a cognitive task, strategic acceptance is ruled out: agents merely express their epistemic acceptance. In contrast, when agents can freely consider how to plan their action, given its stakes, they can refrain from acting on the unique basis of their epistemic acceptance. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Argument from metacognitive studies A decision mechanism is used to compare the probability for their acceptance being correct and a preset response criterion probability, based on the implicit or explicit payoffs. Agents are allowed to strategically withhold or volunteer an answer according to their personal control policy (risk-aversive or risk-seeking), associated with the anticipated costs and benefits (Koriat and Goldsmith, 1996). Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Argument from metacognitive studies Strategic acceptance can be impaired in patients with schizophrenia, while epistemic acceptance is not (Koren et al. 2006) this suggests that epistemic and strategic acceptances are cognitively distinct steps. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Context: also determined by stakes Acceptance is context dependent for two reasons: 1. Its norm (constituting this type of accepting) is strategically dependent on the instrumental context of a plan to act. 2. The decision to act on its content (what is finally accepted) is secondarily adjusted to the expected gain/cost of content being correct or incorrect. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Three types of errors: instrumental Instrumental errors occur when selecting an epistemic norm inappropriate to a context, (for example, trying to reconstruct a shopping list accurately, when comprehensiveness is sufficient), when incorrectly setting the decision criterion given the stakes (taking an epistemic decision to be non-important when it objectively is, and reciprocally). Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Three types of errors: epistemic Epistemic errors occur in applying the selected norm to cognitive content, (for example, seeming to remember that P when one merely imagines that P) in forming an incorrect judgment of confidence about one’s epistemic performance (for example, being highly confident in having correctly learned an item when one will actually fail to retrieve it ). Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Three types of errors: Strategic Strategic errors occur when incorrectly setting the decision criterion given the stakes i.e., taking an epistemic decision to be non- important when it objectively is, and reciprocally. Joëlle Proust - MAICS

Analysis of strategic acceptance: Subjective Expected Utility theory Parameters: Value Probability Expected Utility = value x probability Each course of action (x i ) should be evaluated by myltiplying a subjective valuation of its consequences (reward) u(x i ) by their probability of occurrence P(x i )  i u(x i ) P(x i ) Joëlle Proust - MAICS