Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Department of Computer Science Center for Cognitive Science Rutgers University Lewis and the Semantics-Pragmatics Divide Ernie Lepore Matthew Stone.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Department of Computer Science Center for Cognitive Science Rutgers University Lewis and the Semantics-Pragmatics Divide Ernie Lepore Matthew Stone."— Presentation transcript:

1 Department of Computer Science Center for Cognitive Science Rutgers University Lewis and the Semantics-Pragmatics Divide Ernie Lepore Matthew Stone

2 Outline Rethinking semantics and pragmatics coordination (Lewis 1969) the conversational record (Lewis 1979) Linguistics and the social Implications for philosophical practice

3 Background Last time: Intentions Intention recognition is an important ingredient of understanding, collaboration BUT Problematic to locate linguistic knowledge using intentions Need to look elsewhere to get clear on the scope of linguistic rules as social constructs

4 Coordination Situations where agents’ actions must agree but no intrinsic reason to prefer one joint strategy over another

5 Coordination Examples from Lewis (1969) Arrange a meeting Restart an interrupted phone call Row a boat Share the road when driving Perform a search as a group Collude to set prices Signal a choice

6 Coordination as a game C1C2C3 R11;10;0 R20;01;10;0 R30;0 1;1

7 Games and reasoning If an agent chooses her action deliberately, she must consider her expectations about her partner. Idealization: equilibrium no player would change his move, given the moves the others make

8 Games and reasoning We generally expect equilibria in real life where agents play repeatedly they can learn to match one another even if individual decisions are heuristic Equilibrium describes regularity in behavior Lets us ascribe certain states to agents (perhaps tacit or implicit)

9 State underlying equilibrium It’s common knowledge that (1) everyone conforms to R (2) everyone expects everyone else to conform to R (3) everyone prefers to conform to R on the condition that others do

10 Lewis: this is a convention Objections: Silent about how conventions are instituted That’s the point. Lewis describes how we can get convention from salience, precedents and convergence – but this is just one story among many

11 Games and reasoning A range of mechanisms explain equilibrium Architecture – we’re only biologically capable of one equilibrium Salience – we’re so constituted that preferred equilibrium leaps to mind Experience – we’ve learned that others follow a given equilibrium

12 All potentially relevant to language faculty Architecture: Universal Grammar Salience: Primitive preferences for particular patterns of interpretation Experience: Acquired lexical items, syntactic parameter settings, etc.

13 Lewis: this is a convention Objections: We don’t have to know all these things (Burge) Fair point – let’s talk about ‘social competence’ instead as whatever lets us solve (certain) coordination problems – not prejudging the actual status of skills, knowledge, choice & alternatives

14 Lewis: this is a convention Objections: Lewis’s conventions are always followed – this seems too strong (Gilbert, Millikan) Examples: handing out cigars, using ‘bank’ to mean financial institution

15 Lewis: this is a convention Objections: Lewis’s conventions have to achieve preferred outcomes – this seems too strong (Gilbert, Millikan) Examples: decorating for Christmas specifically with red and green

16 Lewis: this is a convention Objections: Seems to assume coordination problem exists antecedently of equilibrium – this seems too strong (Marmor) Examples: playing chess by the rules

17 Response In keeping with idea of social competence, let’s think of coordination problems are rational reconstructions

18 Lewis on Signaling One party produces signal, knowing the state of the world The other acts, having seen the signal Explains information carried by signal, but a long way from meaning

19 Signaling example ‘one if by land, two if by sea’ Sexton hangs certain patterns of lights conditional on what British are doing Revere prepares particular pattern of defense conditional on what lights he sees They want equilibrium

20 Signaling games 1L2S1S2L 1L2S1;10;0 1S2L0;01;1

21 Problems Meaning is underdetermined 1 light: the British are coming by land or 1 light: prepare the land defenses! or both?

22 Problems Meaning only present at equilibrium So what about coordination that succeeds through other mechanisms – salience? good luck? partial or tentative precedents?

23 Lewis on Convention Lewis attempts to generalize to language by directly understanding truth conditions as conventions for agents to use certain sentences in certain conditions (namely, when they are true)

24 Lewis on Convention This is very cumbersome And doesn’t seem to get at the real difficulties

25 Another idea Language combines social competence with specific institutions targeted at meaning Specifically: the conversational record (Lewis 1979)

26 Conversational record List of propositions associated with discourse Specifies interlocutors’ environment what has been said already what the purposes and plan is what standards of meaning are in play what issues are open what conversation is committed to (Lewis 1979, Thomason 1990)

27 Conversational record Record is dynamic topic can change meaning standards can be negotiated presuppositions can be challenged interlocutors can commit to new propositions or rescind previous commitments Utterances specify updates generally, as a matter of meaning

28 Conversational record Abstraction Free to specify discourse referents, standards for vague predicates, other constructs from formal theories Need not be tied to interlocutors’ knowledge or belief

29 Record is arbitrary In key respects, it’s up to us how the record changes So it’s natural to think of the record as an object of coordination

30 Coordinating on the Record One way of thinking I have my version of what’s happened You have your version of what’s happened When it lines up, we’ve communicated Compare Neale’s presentation here

31 Coordinating on the Record One way of thinking I have my version of what’s happened You have your version of what’s happened When it lines up, we’ve communicated Drawback: describing cases of miscommunication, clarification, etc.

32 Coordinating on the Record An indirect way of thinking Each of us defers to practices Meanings specify how to update the record We coordinate on what we defer to

33 Coordinating on the Record An indirect way of thinking Each of us defers to practices Meanings specify how to update the record We coordinate on what we defer to Promises a better handle on miscommunication, clarification

34 The Received View Semantics linguistic specification of reference, truth settles what the speaker is saying Pragmatics general principles of inference and strategy settles what speaker is doing

35 Problems Fails to describe linguistic knowledge more linguistic facts than supposes e.g., rules for indirection, presupposition, information structure, etc. Fails to describe interpretive inference wide range of practices for engaging with imagery, drawing insights

36 Overall picture Key theoretical notion is inquiry process (normally collaborative) in which interlocutors settle how things are Requires public meanings open to negotiation, debate

37 Overall picture Inquiry privileges conventional meaning depends on conversational record depends on coordination Allows for a broad understanding of meaning Excludes insight or point of open-ended, idiosyncratic engagement with utterance

38 Inquiry and CR Conversational record tracks inquiry Assertion registers proposition on record as commitment of one party Enables further follow up, such as clarification questions, arguments for or against, agreement or disagreement by other parties Record ensures a shared interpretation

39 How will this affect philosophy? Better arguments, but more difficult ones. Close with case study: Grice versus ordinary language philosophers

40 Color: the dialectic Claim: color supervenes on appearance Something is red just in case it looks red under normal conditions to appropriately endowed observers. Objection (Austin): Hogwash! You’d only say something looked red if it wasn’t red!

41 Color: the dialectic Reply (Grice): Well, yes, you wouldn’t say something looks red unless it wasn’t red. But, that’s not part of the meaning of “it looks red”, it’s an implicature. Us: Sorry Grice, your linguistics is bogus.

42 What next? Us: Sorry Austin, your linguistics is bogus too! Often say “something looks red” when it is: His fake tan looks orange. Contaminated water still looks clear. The distant shores look green and inviting. (examples after google searches)

43 What next? Us: Sorry Austin, your linguistics is bogus too! When “it looks red” means it’s not, it’s because of intonation. No objection to analysis of color, as long as you don’t use that intonation!

44 Similar cases Believe and know. Try and succeed. Or and and. Ordinary language folks: 1 st suggests not 2 nd Grice: That’s just an implicature. Us: You’re both wrong. 1 st suggests not 2 nd if marked elsewhere lots of times 1 st doesn’t suggest not 2 nd.

45 Basic point Our theories need to acknowledge the richness and complexity of language and communication. We can do the linguistics and philosophy we want without unhelpful categories like “conversational implicatures”.


Download ppt "Department of Computer Science Center for Cognitive Science Rutgers University Lewis and the Semantics-Pragmatics Divide Ernie Lepore Matthew Stone."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google