Transient Unterdetermination and the Miracle Argument Paul Hoyningen-Huene Leibniz Universität Hannover Center for Philosophy and Ethics of Science (ZEWW)

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Knowledge as JTB Someone S has knowledge of P IFF: 1. S believes P 2. S is justified in believing P 3. P is true.
Advertisements

Joe Levines Purple Haze. Physical/Phenomenal Gaps P = the complete microphysical truth Q = a phenomenal truth Q1: Is there an epistemic gap between.
On the relationship between the notions of independence in matroids, lattices, and Boolean algebras Fabio Cuzzolin INRIA Rhone-Alpes, Grenoble, France.
NOVEL PREDICTION AND THE UNDERDETERMINATION OF SCIENTIFIC THEORY BUILDING Richard Dawid Univ. of Vienna.
Introduction to Proofs
A Scientific Argument for the Existence of God
Justification-based TMSs (JTMS) JTMS utilizes 3 types of nodes, where each node is associated with an assertion: 1.Premises. Their justifications (provided.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Chapter 1 Critical Thinking.
PHILOSOPHY 107 (STOLZE) Notes on Geoffrey Gorham, Philosophy of Science, Chapter 3.
Hume’s Problem of Induction. Most of our beliefs about the world have been formed from inductive inference. (e.g., all of science, folk physics/psych)
Kant, Transcendental Aesthetic
Other Info on Making Arguments
Prepared By Jacques E. ZOO Bohm’s Philosophy of Nature David Bohm, Causality and Chance in Modern Physics (New York, 1957). From Feyerabend, P. K.
Philosophy of Science Psychology is the science of behavior. Science is the study of alternative explanations. We need to understand the concept of an.
Me Talk Good One Day When Language and Logic Fail to Coincide.
For Friday, read chapter 2, sections 1-2 (pp ). As nongraded homework, do the problems on p. 19. Graded homework #1 is due at the beginning of class.
March 10: Quantificational Notions Interpretations: Every interpretation interprets every individual constant, predicate, and sentence letter of PL. Our.
Lecture 6 1. Mental gymnastics to prepare to tackle Hume 2. The Problem of Induction as Hume argues for it 1. His question 2. His possible solutions 3.
Scientific method - 1 Scientific method is a body of techniques for investigating phenomena and acquiring new knowledge, as well as for correcting and.
BASIC CONCEPTS OF ARGUMENTS
EE1J2 – Discrete Maths Lecture 5 Analysis of arguments (continued) More example proofs Formalisation of arguments in natural language Proof by contradiction.
Building Logical Arguments. Critical Thinking Skills Understand and use principles of scientific investigation Apply rules of formal and informal logic.
Philosophy of Religion Michael Lacewing
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
What Exists? The nature of existence. Dictionary definition (Merriam-Webster) To exist: To have real being whether material or spiritual. Being: The quality.
Part 2 Module 3 Arguments and deductive reasoning Logic is a formal study of the process of reasoning, or using common sense. Deductive reasoning involves.
Validity All UH students are communists. All communists like broccoli. All UH students like broccoli.
Chapter 13: Weighted Voting Banzhaf Power Index Shapley-Shubik Power Index Equivalent Systems Examples.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
Logic and Philosophy Alan Hausman PART ONE Sentential Logic Sentential Logic.
Debate: Reasoning. Claims & Evidence Review Claims are statements that serve to support your conclusion. Evidence is information discovered through.
Basics of Probability. A Bit Math A Probability Space is a triple, where  is the sample space: a non-empty set of possible outcomes; F is an algebra.
Basic Concepts of Discrete Probability (Theory of Sets: Continuation) 1.
Explanations Explanations can be thought of as answers to why-questions Explanations can be thought of as answers to why-questions They aim at helping.
Advanced Topics in Propositional Logic Chapter 17 Language, Proof and Logic.
The Science of Good Reasons
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
Logic. What is logic? Logic (from the Ancient Greek: λογική, logike) is the use and study of valid reasoning. The study of logic features most prominently.
All my course outlines and PowerPoint slides can be downloaded from:
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 8 RELATIONS.
Academic Research Academic Research Dr Kishor Bhanushali M
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
DEDUCTIVE VS. INDUCTIVE REASONING. Problem Solving Logic – The science of correct reasoning. Reasoning – The drawing of inferences or conclusions from.
Critical Thinking. Critical thinkers use reasons to back up their claims. What is a claim? ◦ A claim is a statement that is either true or false. It must.
Chapter 10 Lecture Notes Causal Inductive Arguments.
Intertheoretic Reduction and Explanation in Mathematics
Eliminative materialism
LECTURE 18 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT: ANOTHER ATTEMPT TO PROVE THAT SOME THING NECESSSARILY EXISTS.
I think therefore I am - Rene Descartes. REASON (logic) It has been said that man is a rational animal. All my life I have been searching for evidence.
INTUITIONISM: GE Moore, PRITCHARD & ROSS LO: I will understand GE Moore’s idea of naturalistic fallacy. STARTER TASK: Read through the exam essay from.
What is an argument? An argument is, to quote the Monty Python sketch, "a connected series of statements to establish a definite proposition." Huh? Three.
Free Will and Determinism Chapter Three Think pp
Understanding Science 5. The Burden of Proof © Colin Frayn,
Two central questions What does it mean to talk of, or believe in, God? –Is talk about God talk about something that exists independently of us? Or a way.
Péter Hartl & Dr. Tihamér Margitay Dept. of Philosophy and the History of Science 1111 Budapest, Egry J. st. 1. E 610.
Meta-ethics What is Meta Ethics?.
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
WHAT MODELS DO THAT THEORIES CAN’T Lilia Gurova Department of Cognitive Science and Psychology New Bulgarian University.
Philosophy of Religion
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
Joe Levine’s Purple Haze
The Problem of Evil.
Recap Key-Terms Cognitivism Non-Cognitivism Realism Anti-Realism
Logic, Philosophical Tools Quiz Review…20 minutes 10/31
Total Energy is Conserved.
FCAT Science Standard Arianna Medina.
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Validity and Soundness, Again
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Presentation transcript:

Transient Unterdetermination and the Miracle Argument Paul Hoyningen-Huene Leibniz Universität Hannover Center for Philosophy and Ethics of Science (ZEWW)

The subject of the talk TU  ¬ MA TU = transient underdetermination MA = miracle argument 2

Outline 1. Notions of underdetermination a)Radical underdetermination (RU) b)Transient underdetermination (TU) 2. The miracle argument 3. The miracle argument in the light of transient underdetermination 4. Presuppositions of the miracle argument 5. Conclusion 3

Radical underdetermination (RU) “Radical” or “strong” or “Quinean” underdetermination (RU): For any theory T, there are always empirically equivalent theories that are not compatible with T Formally: Let D T be the set of all (possible) data compatible with a given theory T Definition: RU holds iff  T  T [T is compatible with D T   (T  T)] RU seems to kill scientific realism because there is no data on the basis of which we can decide between T and T 4

Transient Underdetermination (TU) “Transient” or “weak” underdetermination (TU) Presuppositions: Let D 0 be a finite set of data that is given at time t 0 Let T 0 be the set of theories such that T 0 := {T 0 (i), i  I, T 0 (i) is relevant for and consistent with D 0 } where I is some index set; T 0 ≠ Ø 5

Definition of TU: 1 st attempt TU holds iff  T  (T  T 0 )   T (T  T 0   (T  T))] “  (T  T)” means that T and T are not compatible Note that there are many possible sources for the incompatibility of theories, including incommensurability! This is too weak as a definition of TU: the existence of two minimally differing theories consistent with the data fulfills the condition It is only a necessary condition for TU We need the possibility of radically false theories that are compatible with the available data 6

TU: Presuppositions Partition of T 0 into the two subsets: (approximately) true theories and radically false theories (not even approximately true) T 0 AT := {T 0 (i), i  V, T 0 (i) is true or approximately true} T 0 RF := {T 0 (i), i  W, T 0 (i) is radically false} where V and W are the respective index sets with V  W = I (which implies T 0 = T 0 AT  T 0 RF ) Assume T 0 AT  T 0 RF = Ø Intuitively, radically false theories operate with radically false basic assumptions in spite of their agreement with the available data (e.g., at some historical time, phlogiston theory or classical mechanics) 7

Definition of TU: 2 nd attempt TU holds iff T 0 RF ≠ Ø For the purposes of my argument, this is still too weak: there must be “quite a few” radically false theories in T 0 8

Definition of TU: 3 rd attempt Intuitive idea of TU: In T 0, there are many more approximately true theories than true theories, and many more radically false theories than approximately true theories (Stanford: unconceived alternatives) In order to formalize this idea, I need the concept of a measure on the space of theories A measure is a generalization of the concept of volume for more general “spaces” The measure says how big a subset of the space is Simplistic example for a theory space and a measure on it: Space of theories: {T k  0 ≤ k < ∞, T k : F(x) = k} Possible measure μ({T k  a ≤ k ≤ b, T k : F(x) = k}) := b - a 9

Simplistic example F(x) bF(x)=k b-a b-a ax 10

Definition of TU: 3 rd attempt (2) Let μ be a measure on the set of theories T 0 Definition of TU: TU holds iff μ(T 0 AT ) << μ(T 0 RF ) In what follows, I will presuppose transient underdetermination in this form 11

TU: Simplistic example (1) with arbitrary numbers F(x) F(x)=k true theory F(x)=1 true theory F(x)= domain of approximatively true theories x 12

TU: Simplistic example (2) with arbitrary numbers T 0 :={T k  0.5 ≤ k ≤ 1.5, T k : F(x) = k} T 0 AT :={T k  ≤ k ≤ 1.001, T k : F(x) = k} T 0 RF :={T k  0.5 ≤ k <  < k ≤ 1.5, T k : F(x)= k} μ(T 0 AT ) = 0.002; μ(T 0 RF ) = Indeed, μ(T 0 AT ) = << μ(T 0 RF ) =

The miracle argument (MA) There are several forms of the miracle argument I will discuss the following form: 1. Scientific realism is the best explanation for novel predictive success of theories; other philosophical positions make it a miracle 2. Therefore, it is reasonable to accept scientific realism Let us articulate this argument more explicitly 14

The miracle argument (2) Let D 0 be a finite set of data that is given at time t 0 Let T 0 := {T 0 (i), i  I, T 0 (i) is relevant for and consistent with D 0 }, I is some index set Let T 0 AT and T 0 RF be the partition of T 0 into true or approximately true and radically false theories Let N be some novel data (relative to D 0 ) that is discovered at time t 1 > t 0 Let there be a theory T*  T 0 capable of predicting the novel data N already at t 0 15

The miracle argument (3) Where does T* belong, to T 0 AT or to T 0 RF ? If T* belongs to T 0 AT, its novel predictive success is not surprising because it gets something fundamental about nature (approximately) right If T* belongs to T 0 RF, its novel predictive success would be surprising because T* lacks all resources for successful novel predictions; it would be a miracle Therefore, it is very probable that T* belongs to T 0 AT – realism explains the novel predictive success of science 16

Transient underdetermination and the miracle argument First, note the following connection between a measure and the prior probability: What is the prior probability to find an element s of some set S in a subset A of S? It is proportional to the “size” of A, i.e. proportional to μ (A) [technically: p(s  A  s  S) = μ(A)/μ(S)] Common sense: Is the probability of winning the lottery small or large? 17

TU & MA (2) Due to this connection, TU supports antirealism: Argument 1 T 0 = T 0 AT  T 0 RF and T 0 AT  T 0 RF = Ø TU: μ(T 0 AT ) << μ(T 0 RF ) Therefore for any T  T 0, it is very probable that T  T 0 RF In other words: due to TU, any theory fitting some data is probably radically false, i.e., TU supports anti- realism 18

TU & MA (3) But here comes the miracle argument: Argument 2 T 0 = T 0 AT  T 0 RF and T 0 AT  T 0 RF = Ø  T*  T 0 such that T* makes the novel prediction N For any T  T 0 RF, it is very improbable (or even impossible) to make prediction N Therefore, it is very probable (or even certain) that T*  T 0 AT In other words: novel predictive success supports realism 19

TU & MA (4) Note the tension between the conclusions of arguments 1 and 2: Conclusion 1: Therefore for any T  T 0, it is very probable that T  T 0 RF Conclusion 2: Therefore, it is very probable (or even certain) that T*  T 0 AT Argument 1 is overruled by argument 2 because the latter’s conclusion about T* states a posterior probability based on additional information [technically: Hempel’s requirement of maximal specificity for statistical explanations] In other words: with the help of MA, realism beats antirealism that relies on TU! 20

TU & MA (5) But TU strikes back: Apply TU at t = t 1 again, namely to the new situation with the new data set D 1 := D 0  N At time t 1, I will do exactly the same as what I did at time t 0 with data set D 0 and theory set T 0 : with data set D 1 := D 0  N and theory set T 1 21

TU & MA (6) D 1 := D 0  N is a finite set of data given at time t 1 T 1 := {T 1 (j), j  J, T 1 (j) is relevant for and consistent with D 1 } where J is some index set Obviously, T*  T 1 Partition of T 1 : T 1 AT := {T 1 (j), j  Y, T 1 (j) is (approximately) true} T 1 RF := {T 1 (j), j  Z, T 1 (j) is radically false} where Y and Z are index sets with Y  Z = J TU: μ(T 1 AT ) << μ(T 1 RF ) 22

TU & MA (7) On this basis, I can formulate an argument analogous to argument 1: Argument 3  T*  T 0 such that T* makes the novel prediction N Therefore, T* is relevant for and consistent with the data D 1 = D 0  N, i.e., T*  T 1 T 1 = T 1 AT  T 1 RF and T 1 AT  T 1 RF = Ø μ(T 1 AT ) << μ(T 1 RF ) Therefore, for any T  T 1, it is very probable that T  T 1 RF. As T*  T 1, it is very probable that T*  T 1 RF 23

TU & MA (8) The conclusion of argument 2 was: it is very probable (or even certain) that T*  T 0 AT it is very probable (or even certain) that T*  T 0 AT The conclusion of argument 3 is: it is very probable that T*  T 1 RF Note that T 1 RF  T 0 RF (every radically false theory that is consistent with D 1 = D 0  N is also consistent with D 0 ) Together with T 0 AT  T 0 RF = Ø, it follows that T 0 AT  T 1 RF = Ø Thus, arguments 2 and 3 put T* with high probability into two disjoint sets which is inconsistent 24

TU & MA (9) As both arguments are formally valid, at least one of the premises of at least one argument must be false Let us look at these premises 25

TU & MA (10) Premises of Argument 2 T 0 = T 0 AT  T 0 RF and T 0 AT  T 0 RF = Ø  T*  T 0 such that T* makes the novel prediction N For any T  T 0 RF, it is very improbable (or even impossible) to make prediction N Premises of Argument 3  T*  T 0 such that T* makes the novel prediction N Therefore, T* is relevant for and consistent with the data D 1 = D 0  N, i.e., T*  T 1 T 1 = T 1 AT  T 1 RF and T 1 AT  T 1 RF = Ø μ(T 1 AT ) << μ(T 1 RF ) 26

TU & MA (11) Thus, the core assumption of the miracle argument: For any T  T 0 RF, it is very improbable (or even impossible) to make prediction N is inconsistent with transient underdetermination, i.e., is false, given TU In other words: TU kills MA Question: How come that the Miracle Argument appears to be so plausible? 27

Presuppositions of MA Remember the crucial assumption of MA: For any T  T 0 RF, it is very improbable (or even impossible) to make prediction N In Putnam’s words: “The positive argument for realism is that it is the only philosophy that doesn’t make the success of science a miracle” There are two (hidden) presuppositions in these statements: 1. There is a uniform answer, i.e., an answer that is not specific of T, to the question why T is predictively successful 2. There are only two alternative answers of the required kind, namely realism and antirealism 28

Presuppositions of MA (2) Both presuppositions are extremely problematic 1. Why a theory is predictively successful may have many different reasons: sheer luck, the novel predictions only appear to be novel, similarity to more successful theories (not yet known), approximate truth, etc. 2. Even among the uniform answers, there are other alternatives, i.e., empirically adequate theories Thus, even without TU, MA is highly problematic 29

Conclusion 1. In general, the miracle argument is a highly problematic argument 2. Given transient underdetermination in the form discussed, the miracle argument is definitively invalid 30