Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson. 2 Section 1. Introduction.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Reasons for (prior) belief in Bayesian epistemology
Advertisements

Knowledge as JTB Someone S has knowledge of P IFF: 1. S believes P 2. S is justified in believing P 3. P is true.
Believing Where We Cannot Prove Philip Kitcher
By Anthony Campanaro & Dennis Hernandez
The Cogito. The Story So Far! Descartes’ search for certainty has him using extreme sceptical arguments in order to finally arrive at knowledge. He has.
The ontological argument
Hume’s Problem of Induction 2 Seminar 2: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 14 September
Philosophy of Mind Matthew Soteriou. Functionalism and Qualia Critics of functionalist accounts of the mental often appeal to thought experiments in which.
The Ontological Argument
1 From metaphysics to logical positivism The metaphysician tells us that empirical truth-conditions [for metaphysical terms] cannot be specified; if he.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 5 SEQUENCES, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, AND RECURSION SEQUENCES, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, AND RECURSION.
Hume’s Problem of Induction. Most of our beliefs about the world have been formed from inductive inference. (e.g., all of science, folk physics/psych)
Malcolm’s ontological argument Michael Lacewing
Philosophy 120 Symbolic Logic I H. Hamner Hill CSTL-CLA.SEMO.EDU/HHILL/PL120.
Models -1 Scientists often describe what they do as constructing models. Understanding scientific reasoning requires understanding something about models.
The “Explanatory Gap” Where it is said that identity theory is not necessary false, but merely unknowable.
So far we have learned about:
Short Paper By Anselmus Sudirman Th Laksmi Widyarini STIKES Jenderal Ahmad Yani Yogyakarta.
The Problem of Knowledge. What new information would cause you to be less certain? So when we say “I’m certain that…” what are we saying? 3 things you.
Phil 1: An Introduction to Philosophy
Philosophy of Religion Michael Lacewing
Mathematics and TOK Exploring the Areas of Knowlege.
ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF
Positivism -v- Pragmatism. MMUBS Mres Epistemology, session 4, slide-1 Positivism -v- Pragmatism Is knowledge composed of a correct.
Research Methods and Design
Epistemology Revision
David Lewis Counterfactuals and Possible Worlds. David Lewis American philosopher, lived between UCLA and Princeton Modal realism.
TaK “This was one of the great events of my life, as dazzling as first love. I had not imagined that there was anything so delicious in the world” Bertrand.
DEDUCTIVE DATABASE.
 According to philosophical skepticism, we can’t have knowledge of the external world.
The answer really annoys me for 3 reasons: 1.I think the statement is arrogant. It doesn’t take into account any definitions of God but solely focuses.
The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)
Rationality Through Reasoning John Broome. When someone believes she ought to F, often her belief causes her to intend to F. How does that happen? Call.
Math 3121 Abstract Algebra I Section 0: Sets. The axiomatic approach to Mathematics The notion of definition - from the text: "It is impossible to define.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 4 ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF.
Basics of Probability. A Bit Math A Probability Space is a triple, where  is the sample space: a non-empty set of possible outcomes; F is an algebra.
On Denoting and its history Harm Boukema. Everyone agrees that “the golden mountain does not exist” is a true proposition. But it has, apparently, a subject,
MIDTERM EXAMINATION THE MIDTERM EXAMINATION WILL BE ON FRIDAY, MAY 2, IN THIS CLASSROOM, STARTING AT 1:00 P.M. BRING A BLUE BOOK. THE EXAM WILL COVER:
Mathematics. We tend to think of math as an island of certainty in a vast sea of subjectivity, interpretability and chaos. What is it?
LEVEL 3 I can identify differences and similarities or changes in different scientific ideas. I can suggest solutions to problems and build models to.
Epistemology, Part I Introduction to Philosophy Jason M. Chang.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
0 What logic is or should be Propositions Boolean operations The language of classical propositional logic Interpretation and truth Validity (tautologicity)
Bayesian vs. frequentist inference frequentist: 1) Deductive hypothesis testing of Popper--ruling out alternative explanations Falsification: can prove.
Lecture 3: The nature of epistemic justification.
Key Concepts Representation Inference Semantics Discourse Pragmatics Computation.
Uncertainty Management in Rule-based Expert Systems
Acknowledgements This project would not have been possible without the gracious help of the McNair Scholars Program. The authors of this project thank.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
LECTURE 17 THE MODAL ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT (A VARIANT OF HARTSHORNE’S VERSION)
Lecture №1 Role of science in modern society. Role of science in modern society.
Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. Line and Angle Relationships 1 1 Chapter.
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
Epistemology (How do you know something?)  How do you know your science textbook is true?  How about your history textbook?  How about what your parents.
What are the strengths and weaknesses of Descartes’ Trademark Argument? StrengthsWeaknesses p , You have 3 minutes to read through the chart you.
Mathematics and TOK Exploring the Areas of Knowlege.
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE Some topics and historical issues of the 20 th century.
Chapter 1: The cosmological argument AQA Religious Studies: Philosophy of Religion AS Level © Nelson Thornes Ltd 2008 Revision.
Philosophy of Science Lars-Göran Johansson Department of philosophy, Uppsala University
WHAT MODELS DO THAT THEORIES CAN’T Lilia Gurova Department of Cognitive Science and Psychology New Bulgarian University.
Intuition and deduction thesis (rationalism)
Knowledge Empiricism 2.
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
A new perspective on philosophical debates
Unit 4 Introducing the Study.
On your whiteboard (1): 1. What is innate knowledge? 2. What were Plato’s arguments for innate knowledge? 3. Was he right? Explain your answer.
Logical Entailment Computational Logic Lecture 3
Philosophy of Mathematics: a sneak peek
Presentation transcript:

Existence by Definition Tom Donaldson

2 Section 1. Introduction

3 Existence by Definition: Some Examples (Some versions of) the ontological argument Analytic phenomenalism Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’. Wherever there are some particles arranged table-wise, there is a table.

4 Existence by Definition: Some Examples (Some versions of) the ontological argument Analytic phenomenalism Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’ Schiffer on properties and propositions If Palo Alto is a town, then Palo Alto has the property of being a town.

5 Existence by Definition: Some Examples (Some versions of) the ontological argument Analytic phenomenalism Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’ Schiffer on properties and propositions Neofregeanism Postulationism

6 Existence by Definition: Some Examples (Some versions of) the ontological argument Analytic phenomenalism Thomasson on ‘ordinary objects’ Schiffer on properties and propositions Neofregeanism Postulationism

7 Reactionaries David Lewis mocks those who deny the existence of classes: I’m moved to laughter at the thought of how presumptuous it would be to reject mathematics for philosophical reasons. How would you like the job of telling the mathematicians that they must change their ways … now that philosophy has discovered that there are no classes?...

8 Reactionaries …If they challenge your credentials, will you boast of philosophy’s other great discoveries: that motion is impossible,... that it is unthinkable that anything exists outside the mind, that time is unreal,... ad nauseam? Not me! David Lewis

9 Reactionaries Reactionaries are (typically) platonists, in the sense that (1) they believe that abstract mathematical objects exist, and (2) they believe that these objects are (setting aside the odd mistake) accurately described by current mathematical theories.

10 Section 2. Postulationism

11 Reichenbach’s Postulationism The axiomatic method has most frequently been applied in mathematics. It has become customary to reduce a controversy about the logical status of mathematics to a controversy about the logical status of the axioms. Nowadays one can hardly speak of a controversy any longer. The problem of the logical status of the axioms of mathematics was solved by the discovery that they are definitions, that is, arbitrary stipulations … Reichenbach (1924)

12 Postulationism: The Basic Idea One can learn mathematical truths by deducing them from stipulative definitions: both explicit definitions, and implicit definitions (which are more usually called ‘axioms’). For example, one might learn number theory by stipulating that the Peano axioms are implicit definitions of ‘number’, ‘plus’, ‘times’, ‘successor’ and ‘zero’, and then deducing theorems from these axioms, introducing additional terms by explicit definition as necessary. This is the ‘definitions and deductions method’.

13 Some Points of Clarification Most postulationists think that mathematical knowledge is a priori.

14 Some Points of Clarification Most postulationists think that mathematical knowledge is a priori.

15 Some Points of Clarification Most postulationists think that mathematical knowledge is a priori. The postulationists’ view is that the definitions and deductions method can be used to acquire mathematical knowledge ab initio. Postulationism is an answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, not the ‘How actually?’ question. I’ll focus on the definitions of words rather than concepts.

16 Objections to postulationism The historical objection

17 Objections to postulationism The historical objection [Postponed] The infinity objection The coherence objection

18 Goals for the talk I want to… …solve the infinity problem, on behalf of the postulationist. …convince you that the coherence objection is fatal to traditional postulationism. …suggest a new answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, which incorporates postulationist insights while escaping the coherence problem.

19 Section 3. The Infinity Problem

20 A simple example Clare sets out to learn some number theory… …having no previous mathematical knowledge. Her axioms might be the Peano axioms, or something similar. She uses a ‘many-sorted’ language. She works in isolation. Her language (initially) is free from ambiguity and vagueness/open-texture.

21 Success conditions A definition. D: Goliath is a horse at least 10cm taller than any other horse. Its success condition. There exists a horse at least 10cm taller than any other horse.

22 Clare, again The function of a definition is to assign referents to the newly introduced words. A definition will succeed just in case suitable referents exist. Clare’s terms include: 0, 0′, 0′′, 0′′′, 0′′′′, … Plausible conclusion: the success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things.

23 How could Clare show that there exist infinitely many things? Empirical arguments? Appeal to existing mathematical theories? A priori, but non-mathematical arguments?

24 The infinity objection (P1) In order to learn a priori that her definitions are true, Clare must establish independently and a priori that their success condition is met. (P2) The success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things. (P3) Clare cannot establish independently and a priori that there exist infinitely many things. (C) Clare cannot learn a priori that her definitions are true.

25 Section 4. Solving The Infinity Problem

26 Another way of thinking about success conditions The function of a definition is to assign referents to the newly introduced words. A definition will succeed just in case suitable referents exist.

27 Another way of thinking about success conditions The function of a definition is to assign referents to the newly introduced words. A definition will succeed just in case suitable referents exist. The function of a definition is to assign truth conditions to sentences in the agent’s newly extended language. A definition will succeed just in case a suitable assignment of truth conditions exists.

28 Some notation L is the agent’s ‘old’ language. L + is the agent’s newly extended language. The definitions are δ 1, …, δ n. J is a function which assigns truth conditions to the sentences in L. We are looking for conditions on the suitability of a function J + which assigns truth conditions to the sentences in the agent’s newly extended language.

29 Conditions on suitability (C1) For each definition δ i, J + (δ i ) is the set of all possible worlds. (C2) For any ‘old’ sentence φ, J(φ)=J + (φ). (C3) J + should ‘respect logical necessitation’ in the following sense. If Γ is a set of sentences, and possible world w  J + (γ) for each γ  Γ, and if Γ logically necessitates φ, then w  J + (φ).

30 Conditions on suitability (C1) For each definition δ i, J + (δ i ) is the set of all possible worlds. (C2) For any ‘old’ sentence φ, J(φ)=J + (φ). (C3) J + should ‘respect logical necessitation’ in the following sense. If Γ is a set of sentences, and possible world w  J + (γ) for each γ  Γ, and if Γ logically necessitates φ, then w  J + (φ).

31 The application to Clare’s definitions An assignment function that meets conditions (C1)-(C3) will exist provided that the following condition is met: The Modal Conservativeness Condition For any possible world w, {δ 1, …, δ n }∪{α∊L:w∊J(α)} is coherent.

32 The application to Clare’s definitions An assignment function that meets conditions (C1)-(C3) will exist provided that the following condition is met: The Modal Conservativeness Condition For any possible world w, {δ 1, …, δ n }∪{α∊L:w∊J(α)} is coherent.

33 The application to Clare’s definitions [I]f the arbitrarily given axioms do not contradict one another with all their consequences, then they are true and the things defined by the axioms exist. This is for me the criterion of truth and existence. Hilbert

34 The infinity objection (P1) In order to learn a priori that her definitions are true, Clare must establish independently and a priori that their success condition is met. (P2) The success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things. (P3) Clare cannot establish independently and a priori that there exist infinitely many things. (C) Clare cannot learn a priori that her definitions are true.

35 Aside for metaphysicians: Do numbers exist in the perfectly natural sense? “There exists a hole in every bagel.”

36 Goals for the talk I want to… …solve the infinity problem, on behalf of the postulationist. …convince you that the coherence problem is fatal to traditional postulationism. …suggest a new answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, which incorporates postulationist insights while escaping the coherence problem.

37 Section 5. The coherence problem

38 The infinity objection (P1) In order to learn a priori that her definitions are true, Clare must establish independently and a priori that their success condition is met. (P2) The success condition of Clare’s definition is at least that there exist infinitely many things. (P3) Clare cannot establish independently and a priori that there exist infinitely many things. (C) Clare cannot learn a priori that her definitions are true.

39 Externalism Goliath is a horse at least 10cm taller than any other horse. (Strong Externalism) If an agent uses a definition , and if the success condition of  is met, then the agent is in a position to know a priori that  is true, in the absence of a defeater.

40 Externalism (Weak Externalism) If an agent uses a definition , and if the success condition of  is met, and if the definition meets constraint C, then the agent is in a position to know a priori that  is true, in the absence of a defeater. Case (i) Clare uses as her definitions the Peano axioms. Case (ii) Clare uses as her definitions the Peano axioms, together with some difficult number- theoretic result, such as Fermat’s Last Theorem.

41 What is coherence? First thesis: It is possible for Clare, who has no pre-existing mathematical knowledge, to establish a priori that (say) the Peano axioms are coherent. Second thesis: Whenever Clare’s definitions are coherent, there will exist a ‘suitable’ assignment of truth conditions to the sentences in her newly extended language.

42 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability First thesis: It is possible for Clare, who has no pre-existing mathematical knowledge, to establish a priori that (say) the Peano axioms are coherent.

43 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency Second thesis: Whenever Clare’s definitions are coherent, there will exist a ‘suitable’ assignment of truth conditions to the sentences in her newly extended language.

44 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency α 1, …, α n ⊢ T β

45 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency (i)PA 2 ⊢ T φ(n) (for each numeral n). (ii)PA 2 ⊬ T ∀x φ(x).

46 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency (i)PA 2 ⊢ T φ(n) (for each numeral n). (ii)PA 2 ⊬ T ∀x φ(x). PA* = PA 2 ∪{⌜¬∀xφ(x)⌝}

47 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency J + (⌜¬∀xφ(x)⌝) = the set of possible worlds

48 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency J + (⌜∀xφ(x)⌝) =∅ J + (φ(n))= the set of possible worlds The Generalization Constraint: J + (⌜∀x α(x)⌝) = J + ( α(o)) ∩ J + ( α(1)) ∩ J + (α(2)) ∩ …

49 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency 3.Coherence as informal deductive consistency First thesis: It is possible for Clare, who has no pre-existing mathematical knowledge, to establish a priori that (say) the Peano axioms are coherent.

50 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency 3.Coherence as informal deductive consistency Second thesis: Whenever Clare’s definitions are coherent, there will exist a ‘suitable’ assignment of truth conditions to the sentences in her newly extended language.

51 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency 3.Coherence as informal deductive consistency 4.Coherence as informal satisfiability ∀x Rxx∀x∀y∀z[(Rxy  Ryz)  Rxz]

52 What is coherence? 1.Coherence as model-theoretic satisfiability 2.Coherence as proof-theoretic consistency 3.Coherence as informal deductive consistency 4.Coherence as informal satisfiability 5.Field’s primitivism

53 The vicious circle Mathematical Knowledge Knowledge of Coherence

54 Goals for the talk I want to… …solve the infinity problem, on behalf of the postulationist. …convince you that the coherence problem is fatal to traditional postulationism. …suggest a new answer to the ‘How possibly?’ question, which incorporates postulationist insights while escaping the coherence problem.

55 Section 6. A solution (?)

56 The vicious circle: A Solution? Method 1: Suppose that some set of mathematical terms are entirely defined by definitions δ 1,…, δ n, and that no other non-logical terms occur in δ 1,…, δ n. Then if you can show that δ 1,…, δ n are coherent, you may infer that they are all true. Method 2: Suppose that S is a set of sentences, and that T is a mathematical theory you know to be true. Then if you can interpret S in T, you may infer that S is coherent.

57 The vicious circle: A Solution? Method 3: Suppose that S is a set of sentences, and T is an empirically well-confirmed scientific theory. Then if you can interpret S in T, you have good reason to believe that S is coherent. Method 4: If a mathematical theory T plays an indispensable role in an empirically well- confirmed scientific theory, one has good reason for believing that T is true. (See: Quine)

58 The vicious circle: A Solution? Method 4: Suppose that S is a set of sentences. Then if you can deduce ⊥ from S, you may conclude that S is incoherent. Method 5: Changes to one’s overall system of logico-mathematical beliefs can be justified on grounds of simplicity, elegance etc.. (See: Penelope Maddy)

59 Section 7. Postscript: Is there a ‘reliability problem’ for logic?

60 Field’s Challenge Platonists believe that ‘we’ are ‘reliable’ in what we believe about mathematics. How can this ‘reliability’ be explained? A parallel (?) challenge: How can we explain the reliability of our beliefs about which collections of sentences are coherent?

61 Field’s Argument (1) Were the mathematical facts different, the our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise) (2) It could only be a huge coincidence if our mathematical beliefs are true. (From 1) (3) “Our belief in a theory should be undermined if the theory requires that it would be a huge coincidence if what we believed about its subject matter were correct.” (Premise) (4) Our belief in current mathematical theories is undermined. (From 2, 3)

62 Field’s Argument (1) Were the mathematical facts different, our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise) (1*) Were the mathematical logical facts different, our mathematical logical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise)

63 Response to Field (1) Were the mathematical facts different, our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise) (2) It could only be a huge coincidence if our mathematical beliefs are right. (From 1)

64 A lottery case The people in Dave’s department organize a lottery syndicate. They buy 100 tickets from the national lottery. Dave understands that each ticket has only a tiny chance of winning the jackpot, and he is a pessimist. So he forms the belief that the first ticket will not win, and the belief that the second ticket will not win, and the belief that the third ticket will not win, … and so on. As it happens, Dave is right: none of the tickets will win. There is thus a perfect correlation between his beliefs of the form [ticket n will not win] and the facts.

65 Response to Field (1) Were the mathematical facts different, our mathematical beliefs would be exactly the same. (Premise) (2) It could only be a huge coincidence if our mathematical beliefs are right. (From 1)

66 Section 8. Closing thoughts

67 Conclusion: My take on postulationism The postulationist is right that mathematical knowledge can be achieved using the definitions and deductions method. However, this is of limited value, in the absence of some account of how one might establish the coherence of systems of mathematical definitions. In order to obtain a satisfactory answer to the ‘How possibly?” question, we must add further methods of obtaining logico-mathematical knowledge.

68 Some other possible applications Compound objects Social objects Propositions (etc.)

69 The End!