TOPIC4: INTER-TEMPORAL CONSUMPTION CHOICE Saving for tomorrow is a fact of life. Equally, we often spend more than what we currently earn or have by borrowing.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Choices Involving Risk
Advertisements

Optimal Contracts under Adverse Selection
Choice under Uncertainty. Introduction Many choices made by consumers take place under conditions of uncertainty Therefore involves an element of risk.
The Intertemporal Approach to the Current Account Professor Roberto Chang Rutgers University January 2007.
Budget Today or Tomorrow
Chapter 12 Uncertainty Consider two lotteries L 1 : 500,000 (1) L 1 ’: 2,500,000 (0.1), 500,000 (0.89), 0 (0.01) Which one would you choose? Another two.
Chapter 37 Asymmetric Information In reality, it is often the case that one of the transacting party has less information than the other. Consider a market.
Utility Theory.
States of the World In this section we introduce the notion that in the future the outcome in the world is not certain. Plus we introduce some related.
Understanding the Concept of Present Value
1 Demand for Health Insurance. 2 Which Investment will you pick Expected Value $2600 Choice 2 $5000 -$ Choice 1 $5000 $
Choices Involving Risk
Decision-Making under Uncertainty – Part I Topic 4.
Chapter 3: Demand, Supply and Equilibrium
The Economics of Information. Risk a situation in which there is a probability that an event will occur. People tend to prefer greater certainty and less.
Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion
Intermediate Microeconomic Theory
317_L13, Feb 5, 2008, J. Schaafsma 1 Review of the Last Lecture finished our discussion of the demand for healthcare today begin our discussion of market.
Uncertainty and Information CHAPTER 19. After studying this chapter you will be able to Explain how people make decisions when they are uncertain about.
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior
Chapter 9 THE ECONOMICS OF INFORMATION Copyright ©2002 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved. MICROECONOMIC THEORY BASIC.
More Insurance How much insurance We started talking about insurance. Question now is “how much?” Recall that John’s expected utility involves his wealth.
Notes – Theory of Choice
Chapter Twelve Uncertainty. Uncertainty is Pervasive u What is uncertain in economic systems? –tomorrow’s prices –future wealth –future availability of.
Wrapping UP Insurance Let’s Review Moral Hazard With health insurance, the amount of expenditures may depend on whether you have insurance. Suppose that.
Extensions to Consumer theory Inter-temporal choice Uncertainty Revealed preferences.
In this chapter, look for the answers to these questions:
The Capital Asset Pricing Model P.V. Viswanath Based on Damodaran’s Corporate Finance.
Chapter Twelve Uncertainty. Uncertainty is Pervasive u What is uncertain in economic systems? –tomorrow’s prices –future wealth –future availability of.
Equilibrium and Efficiency
1 Chapter 6 From Demand to Welfare. Main Topics Dissecting the effects of a price change Measuring changes in consumer welfare using demand curves 2.
Basic Tools of Finance Finance is the field that studies how people make decisions regarding the allocation of resources over time and the handling of.
© 2008 Pearson Addison Wesley. All rights reserved Chapter Five Consumer Welfare and Policy Analysis.
Lecture 3: Arrow-Debreu Economy
MONOPOLISTIC COMPETITION
THE HEALTH CARE MARKET Chapter 9.
mankiw's macroeconomics modules
Industrial Economics Fall INFORMATION Basic economic theories: Full (perfect) information In reality, information is limited. Consumers do not know.
Decision-making under uncertainty. Introduction Definition of risk Attitudes toward risk Avoiding risk: Diversification Insurance.
Chapter 16 Uncertainty We must believe in luck. For how else can we explain the success of those we don’t like? Jean Cocteau.
Modelling the labour market Labour supply decisions The effect of a minimum wage.
ECON 6012 Cost Benefit Analysis Memorial University of Newfoundland
Chapter 37 Asymmetric Information. Information in Competitive Markets In purely competitive markets all agents are fully informed about traded commodities.
Interest ratesslide 1 INTEREST RATE DETERMINATION The rate of interest is the price of money to borrow and lend. Rates of interest are expressed as decimals.
5.1 Household Behavior and Consumer Choice We have studied the basics of markets: how demand and supply determine prices and how changes in demand and.
Copyright © 2004 South-Western 27 The Basic Tools of Finance.
Chapter 3 Arbitrage and Financial Decision Making
Chapter 5 Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior. ©2005 Pearson Education, Inc.Chapter 52 Q: Value of Stock Investment in offshore drilling exploration: Two.
Asymmetric Information
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Chapter 14 Equilibrium and Efficiency. What Makes a Market Competitive? Buyers and sellers have absolutely no effect on price Three characteristics: Absence.
Decision theory under uncertainty
© 2010 W. W. Norton & Company, Inc. 12 Uncertainty.
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior Chapter 5. Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior 1.In order to compare the riskiness of alternative choices, we need to.
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
CHAPTER 12 Risk and information ©McGraw-Hill Education, 2014.
How Prices are Determined In a free market economy, supply and demand are coordinate through the price system. Everyone who participates in the economy.
3.1 Chapter 3: Demand, Supply and Equilibrium From Chapter 2: All societies must decide: What will be produced? How will it be produced? Who will get what.
Intertemporal Choice Lecture 13.
20 UNCERTAINTY AND INFORMATION © 2012 Pearson Education.
S PP 2 T OPIC 1 I SSUE 2: C HANGE IN PRICES AFFECT CONSUMER ’ S CHOICES T HE THEORY OF CONSUMER CHOICE Xiaozhen Chen Hai Tran.
Section 5. What You Will Learn in this Module Illustrate the relationship between the demand for money and the interest rate with a graph Explain why.
Microeconomics Course E John Hey. Chapter 26 Because we are all enjoying risk so much, I have decided not to cover Chapter 26 (on the labour market)
Intermediate Microeconomic Theory Intertemporal Choice.
The Intertemporal Approach to the Current Account Professor Roberto Chang Rutgers University March 2013.
Extensions to Consumer theory Inter-temporal choice Uncertainty Revealed preferences.
Lectures 7-8 (Chap. 26) Saving, Investment, and the Financial System.
1 Indifference Curves and Utility Maximization CHAPTER 6 Appendix © 2003 South-Western/Thomson Learning.
L11 Uncertainty.
Choices Involving Risk
Presentation transcript:

TOPIC4: INTER-TEMPORAL CONSUMPTION CHOICE Saving for tomorrow is a fact of life. Equally, we often spend more than what we currently earn or have by borrowing.

We shall consider a two-period model of consumer choice. The consumer receives a given amount of money in period 0 (M0), and in period 1 (M1). The numbers M0 and M1 thus define the consumer’s budget. The consumer derives utility from today’s consumption(C0) and tomorrow’s consumption C1 according to some utility function U(C0,C1) which generates an indifference map as shown in below.

C0 o C1 Relate this diagram to the explanation in the next slide

An individual who borrows has a stronger preference for C0 (steeper indifference curves). The slope of the indifference curve is the MRS between C0 and C1. The MRS is also called the discount factor.

People with stronger preference for C0 have a smaller discount factor. They discount future happiness more. The discount factor is unique to an individual consumer, just like his/her indifference curves.

The budget constraint of the consumer must recognise the fact that the consumer is free to borrow and/or lend at the market interest rate r. For a given value of r, the budget constraint is drawn below (We assume for simplicity that the unit price of both C0 and C1 is 1)

c0 c1 OA B M0 M1 OA  M0 + M1/(1+r); OB  M0(1+r) + M1 The slope of the budget line = (-OB/OA)= -(1+r). The negative sign represents the trade-off; the magnitude (1+r) is the relative price of C0 in terms of C1.

c0 c1 O A b M0 M1 C*1C*1 C*0C*0 Consumer choice: The individual is a saver

A c0 c1 O b M0 M1 A drop in the rate of interest Shifts AB down and to the right

M0 A A’ C0 A fall in the rate of interest is a gain for the borrower but a loss to the lender B’

c0 c1 O A’ A b M0 M1 b’ 2 1 An increase in the interest rate reduces the welfare of the borrower

c0 c1 O A’ A b M0 M1 b’ 1 2 An increase in the interest rate increases the welfare of the lender In this case, as the interest rate goes up, C0 falls The law of demand holds

c0 c1 O A’ A b M0 M1 b’ 1 2 In this case, as the interest rate goes up, so does C0. The law of demand does not hold

Inter-temporal Choice with Production The analysis above assumes that the individual can reallocate consumption across time by borrowing/lending in a perfect capital market.

 However, instead of having just the freedom to lend current resources, it may be more realistic to include the possibility of using the current resources to produce some goods that are consumable in the future, or INVESTMENT.  We shall therefore broaden our analysis by incorporating a production opportunity that allows current saving to be invested, leading to a greater level of output in the future.

To start with a simple model, suppose that the individual has no access to a capital market., that is, she is unable to borrow/lend. Also, for simplicity, we assume that the individual is endowed with productive resources only for today (she does not receive any resources tomorrow).

C0 C1 O X A B Individual consumes OX units of C0. 1 Individual has no access to an organized capital market Saves and invests AX units Produces/consumes OY units of C1. Y

C0 C1 O C I A B 2 Individual has access to an organized capital market 1 1’ Investment = IA Saving = CI

C0 C1 O I A C B 2 Individual has access to an organized capital market 1 1’ Investment = IA Saving =-IC

TOPIC5: CONSUMER CHOICE UNDER RISK We have so far analysed consumer behaviour under certainty. The typical consumer has been assumed to have perfect information on every single economic variable. We shall now introduce the notion of RISK.

 Consider the following choice problem.  Choice A: Buy lottery ticket for £1 that wins £2 with probability 0.5 or nothing with probability 0.5  Choice B: Don’t buy the ticket.

Consumer preferences may be one of the following three types: 1. Risk Lovers or Gamblers would prefer choice A to B. 2. A Risk Neutral person would be indifferent between choice A and B. 3. A Risk Averse person would prefer choice B over A.

Wealth Utility O £1 £2 The utility function of a gambler The utility from a £ gained is greater than the disutility from a £ lost

Wealth Utility O £1 £2 The utility function of a risk- averse person The utility from a £ gained is less than the disutility from a £ lost

Wealth Utility O £1 £2 The utility function of a risk-neutral person The utility from a £ gained is the same as the disutility from a £ lost

Consider this possibility. Individual says that  U(A) < U(B) = U (£1). That is,  although both A and B offers the same amount of money (£1) on average, the individual would rather have B.  But what is U(A)?  It is certainly not as high as U(£2).  Neither is it as low as U(£0).

 The value of U(A) is in between these extreme values.  To capture this idea, we introduce the notion of EXPECTED UTILITY..

We shall say that Expected utility of lottery A, or EU (A)  0.5 U(£2) U(£0). Clearly, EU(A) is a weighted average of the two extreme values U(£2) and U(£0), using the probabilities as the ‘weights’. It then follows that U(2) > EU(A) > U(£0)

For a gambler, EU(A) > U(B). Oppositely, for a risk-averse person EU(A) < U(B) and for a risk neutral person EU(A) = U(B)

Risk Preference and the market for insurance  In this section we shall argue that  there is no demand for insurance from an individual who is a gambler or risk-neutral.  Risk-averse people will want to be insured against the risk,

 but this alone does not guarantee the existence of a market as we shall shortly see.  We start with the case of a risk- averse person.  In order to generalise the argument above,  let the individual face a risky situation A described as follows:

 With a small probability  the individual gets W0 unit s of money  and with probability (1-  ) he gets W1 > W0.  Let OB   W0 + (1-  )W1.  OB is then the EXPECTED VALUE of the monetary gain.

Wealth Utility O W0 C B W1 EUA U(OB)

EUA =  U  W0) +  U(W1) W1-B is the minimum insurance premium W1-C is the maximum insurance premium C is the certainty equivalent of lottery A OB = EVA =  W0 +  W1 U(EVA) > EUA for a risk-averse person BC is the consumer surplus

It therefore seems that potentials of a market exist because the buyer could pay more than what the seller would charge. But what about administrative costs? If these exceed distance BC in the diagram above, there is no market! As long as these costs are less than BC, potentials of a market exist.

The nature of admin costs is such that they do not change proportionately with the size of the policy or that of the premium. On the other hand, notice that the consumer surplus BC is larger the greater the difference between W1 and W0. Hence it follows that the consumer will not bother to buy insurance if the extent of the loss is ‘small’.

You should now be able to argue that a risk –neutral person will not buy insurance if there are positive administrative costs. What exactly are these ‘administrative’ costs? The insuring party typically ‘pools’ the risk faced by several of its customers.

Suppose that 100 individuals each wants to purchase an insurance against unemployment. Assume that they each earn £40000 p.a. and nothing if s/he loses job. Let the job loss probability for each be 0.1. Here, the ‘fair bet’ premium is £4000.

 How much extra the seller charges depends how the job losses are correlated.  Essentially, the seller hopes to pay out a claim (by a customer who lost his job) from the money paid in by those who do not lose their jobs.  This can be ideally achieved if the event that one customer loses his job is negatively correlated with the one in which some other customer loses his.

 The worst scenario for the insurer is when these events are perfectly and positively correlated.  For example, if all the workers work in the same factory, there can be no single insurer who can sell unemployment insurance to all of them.

 This is why you cannot purchase insurance against earthquakes or floods.  A social risk is non-insurable.

Wealth Utility O £1 £2 The utility from a £ gained is greater than the disutility from a £ lost 1 4 Examine his attitude to risk An agent has the utility function U = W 2 defined over wealth (W)

W0 EVA W1 Utility O EUA U(W1) U(W0) U =W 2 Wealth U(EVA) Relate this diagram to the explanation in the next slide

25000 > Then EVA = 0.5* *100= 150 Suppose probability of getting W1 is 0.5 Then U(W0) = and U(W1) = EUA = 0.5* *40000 = Let W0 = 100 and W1 = 200 EU(A) > U(EVA) The agent is a gambler

Utility O U =W 2 Wealth (£) Maximum Premium =£41.89 Minimum Premium =£50 No market for insurance

Asymmetric Information and the Market for Insurance Are we more likely to leave the house/car door unlocked after purchasing insurance against burglary? Does the probability of a risky event occurring increase as we insure ourselves against it? Moral Hazard Adverse Selection

Some economists answer in the affirmative. If this is the case, then the profitability of the insurance seller may well be lower, thus reducing the willingness of the seller to sell insurance and the probability of market existence. This is the problem of ‘moral hazard’ due to asymmetric information.

A second problem, and due to asymmetric information as well, is that of ‘adverse selection’. Suppose that individual A is a low-risk case who wishes to purchase insurance. Mr. A expects the premium to be low.

Indeed, the seller would offer him a low premium rates if he knew that A was low-risk. Unfortunately, he cannot distinguish Mr. A from Ms. B, a high-risk customer. The presence of the latter kind of customers drives the cost of insurance higher than what the likes of Mr. A ought to pay.

On the other hand, such premiums are well below the rate that the high- risk customer ought to pay. Result- low-risk customers such as Mr. A pull out of the market; high- risk customers are the ones that remain. The seller has managed to attract the worse type of customers to his business.