From optimism to surrender

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
NOVEL PREDICTION AND THE UNDERDETERMINATION OF SCIENTIFIC THEORY BUILDING Richard Dawid Univ. of Vienna.
Advertisements

What is Social Theory?. Theory Harrington 2005: 1-3 Greek word theōria, opp. of praxis contemplation / reflection Reflection on the value and meaning.
Meaning Skepticism. Quine Willard Van Orman Quine Willard Van Orman Quine Word and Object (1960) Word and Object (1960) Two Dogmas of Empiricism (1951)
Today’s Outline Hume’s Problem of Induction Two Kinds of Skepticism
The Scientific Method.
Can you point to science?  Philosophy, even from it’s most ancient beginnings, has been keenly interested in the constituents and organization of our.
Quine, “Natural Kinds” Some Problems of Induction: (1) The New Riddle of Induction (Goodman) Goodman proposes a new predicate: grue. X is grue if and only.
NOTE: CORRECTION TO SYLLABUS FOR ‘HUME ON CAUSATION’ WEEK 6 Mon May 2: Hume on inductive reasoning --Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, section.
Popper On Science Economics Lawlor. What is and inductive inference? Example: “All Swans are white” Needs an observation to confirm it’s truth.
Chapter 1 What is Science
1 From metaphysics to logical positivism The metaphysician tells us that empirical truth-conditions [for metaphysical terms] cannot be specified; if he.
Naturalism The world we live in. Supplementary Reading A Field Guide to Recent Species of Naturalism Alex Rosenberg The British Journal for the Philosophy.
PHILOSOPHY 107 (STOLZE) Notes on Geoffrey Gorham, Philosophy of Science, Chapter 3.
The Problem of Induction Reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’ by W. Salmon.
Hume’s Problem of Induction. Most of our beliefs about the world have been formed from inductive inference. (e.g., all of science, folk physics/psych)
Introduction/Hume’s Problem of Induction Seminar 1: Philosophy of the Sciences 6 September
Philosophy 120 Symbolic Logic I H. Hamner Hill CSTL-CLA.SEMO.EDU/HHILL/PL120.
Saving the Date vs. Coherence Reflections on fossils and scientific method.
Limitations to Underdetermination of Theory Building and their Role in Fundamental Physics Richard Dawid.
The Language of Theories Linking science directly to ‘meanings’
The Problem of the Criterion Chisholm: Particularists and Methodists.
Science and induction  Science and we assume causation (cause and effect relationships)  For empiricists, all the evidence there is for empirical knowledge,
The “Explanatory Gap” Where it is said that identity theory is not necessary false, but merely unknowable.
Chapter Two SCIENTIFIC METHODS IN BUSINESS
Lecture 6 1. Mental gymnastics to prepare to tackle Hume 2. The Problem of Induction as Hume argues for it 1. His question 2. His possible solutions 3.
Developing Ideas for Research and Evaluating Theories of Behavior
The Problem of Induction Reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’ by W. Salmon.
Nursing Knowledge Chapter 8 Logical positivism and mid-century philosophy of science Presented by Justin Fallin October 25, 2014 Professor: Dr. Tomlinson.
Qualitative research in psychology. A distinct research process Inquiries of knowledge that are outside the framework prescribed by the scientific method,
Can you point to science?  Philosophy, even from it’s most ancient beginnings, has been keenly interested in the constituents and organization of our.
Positivism -v- Pragmatism. MMUBS Mres Epistemology, session 4, slide-1 Positivism -v- Pragmatism Is knowledge composed of a correct.
Philosophy of science II
Research Methods and Design
Lecture 7: Ways of Knowing - Reason. Part 1: What is reasoning? And, how does it lead to knowledge?
Ways of Arguing with Intelligent Design: Philosophers on Demarcation Creationist criticism of evolutionary theory takes many forms, but one of the more.
 According to philosophical skepticism, we can’t have knowledge of the external world.
Positivism -v- Pragmatism. MMUBS Mres Epistemology, session 4, slide-1 Positivism -v- Pragmatism Is knowledge composed of a correct.
Chapter 13 Science and Hypothesis.  Modern science has had a profound impact on our lives— mostly for the better.  The laws and principles of science.
Ann Kemper Raivydas Simenas
Lesson Overview Lesson Overview Science in Context Lesson Overview 1.2 Science in Context.
Lesson Overview Lesson Overview Science in Context Lesson Overview 1.2 Science in Context.
David Hume’s Skepticism The nature of ideas and reasoning concerning ‘matters of fact’
Lesson Overview 1.2 Science in Context.
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
Invitation to Critical Thinking Chapter 9 Lecture Notes Chapter 9.
11/8/2015 Nature of Science. 11/8/2015 Nature of Science 1. What is science? 2. What is an observation? 3. What is a fact? 4. Define theory. 5. Define.
Chapter Two: Explaining Winston Jackson and Norine Verberg Methods: Doing Social Research, 4e.
Contrasting views of science: Popper vs. Kuhn. Sir Karl Popper Sir Karl Popper was a member of the Vienna Circle in the earlier part of the 20th century.
Scientific Methods and Terminology. Scientific methods are The most reliable means to ensure that experiments produce reliable information in response.
Rachel Petrik Based on writing by A.J. Ayer
Critical Social Theory “[O]ur age is … the age of enlightenment, and to criticism everything must submit” Kant, Critique of Pure Reason.
Confirmation, Falsification, Underdetermination. Empiricism is the winning view Empiricist: Accept that we can acquire knowledge about the future and.
About Math and related topics About Math 1. The Unreasonable Effectiveness The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences by Eugene.
Miracles: Hume and Howard-Snyder. * For purposes of initial clarity, let's define a miracle as a worldly event that is not explicable by natural causes.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. Line and Angle Relationships 1 1 Chapter.
邏輯經驗論 2010 春台大哲學系科學哲學第三講. Central Ideas of Logical Positivism Logical positivism was a revolutionary, uncompromising version of empiricism, based largely.
Epistemology (How do you know something?)  How do you know your science textbook is true?  How about your history textbook?  How about what your parents.
Chapter 1 Introduction to Research in Psychology.
TOK: Ways of Knowing Sense Perception. ‘ He who has been bitten by a snake fears a piece of string’ Persian proverb.
Instructor: Todd Ganson.  Φιλοσοφία (philo-sophia)
Philosophy of science What is a scientific theory? – Is a universal statement Applies to all events in all places and time – Explains the behaviour/happening.
Lesson Overview Lesson Overview Science in Context Lesson Overview 1.2 Science in Context Scientific methodology is the heart of science. But that vital.
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
W.V.O. Quine ( ) On the Nature of Moral Values
IS Psychology A Science?
Did King Harold die at the battle of Hastings?
The Postgridiot’s Guide to…
Verification and meaning
Presentation transcript:

From optimism to surrender Logical Empiricism From optimism to surrender

The logical part: First order logic First order (quantified) logic combines the resources of truth functional propositional connectives, a simple subject-predicate analysis of sentences and (individual) variables and quantifiers. The result is a formal language with quite a lot of expressive power– enough for us to formalize mathematical theories, for instance. With a language this clear and this powerful, the logical empiricists hoped they could do what Hume and other early empiricists could not: give a full account of all (meaningful) ideas and concepts in terms of experience and logic.

Experience Experience clearly plays a role in observation– in ‘pure’ observation, many philosophers have thought that we simply report what we experience. Because such reports are often regarded as incorrigible and infallible, this sort of pure report of experience is often part of a foundationalist picture of the epistemology of ‘facts about the world’.

Skepticism There are two characteristic forms of skepticism that arise here. The first is about the links between an account of what we experience and the external world: How can the course of our private experience tell us about the public, external world that (we believe) causes most such experiences? The second is about induction and regularities: How can reports about patterns of experience we’ve had provide a basis for projecting those patterns into future experiences?

Patterns of actual and possible sensations One traditional response to the first sort of skepticism is to re-define what an ‘external object’ is, in terms of ‘patterns of actual and possible sensations’. This view is called phenomenalism. But it is widely accepted to be untenable. The problem is, we cannot describe these patterns independently of our understanding of the (familiar) world of physical objects. Kant’s account of our knowledge as combining fixed conceptual structures (including space and time) with ‘raw material’ from sensation solves this problem, if a bit crudely. Other accounts focus on language and language acquisition, which can be more flexible about concepts.

Science By this time, science is a standard example of epistemic success. Einstein’s theory of relativity was a recent example, undermining the ‘fixity’ of fundamental concepts that Kant had assumed. The logical positivists proposed to apply their logical tools together with empiricist ideas about experience as the key to scientific knowledge, to arrive at a new account of science that would fit with Einstein’s work.

Philosophy of Language Analytic-synthetic distinction & knowledge of mathematics. Einstein’s use of non-Euclidean geometry in physics illustrates the view that all mathematical knowledge is analytic (and all synthetic knowledge is empirical). The difference between applied and pure mathematics is central here. The verifiability theory of meaning. The meaning of a sentence is reduced to methods of deciding whether the sentence is true or false. This turns out to be untenable right away, since dispositions are meaningful, but we often aren’t able to say whether an object has a certain disposition or not. So weaker conditions were developed, always maintaining a link between empirical testability and meaningfulness.

Observational vs. Theoretical Language The positivists recognized the importance of theoretical language, even though it seems impossible to directly test theoretical claims against experience. They proposed that theoretical language always depended on a basic observational language for its meaningfulness. The observational language would remain fixed over time, ensuring that we always have an agreed starting point we can apply to evaluating and comparing different scientific theories.

Responding to Hume This requires an account of the logic of induction– somehow, regularities in our observations have to provide evidence that certain observed patterns will persist. The positivists expected that logical work on the relations between observations and the theoretical claims those observations confirm (or disconfirm) would reveal the structure of inductive reasoning.

Limits of philosophy Context of justification: here logic is the key, and we should be able to give an account of our commitments and why we hold them. Context of discovery: here psychology is the key; philosophy does not have to give an account of how (rationally) we should go about developing new hypotheses and theories to test against our observations.

Positivists as bad guys? In some circles today ‘positivist’ is a term of abuse– it implies a narrow, authoritarian commitment to science, and a dismissal of everything that science does not account for. Otto von Neurath’s ship metaphor is a good starting point for appreciating how open-minded and modest the positivists actually were. Better yet, this is an intellectual movement that, in the end, realized that its goals could not be achieved. How many such movements are clear (and honest) enough to achieve such closure?

Holism W.V.O. Quine famously challenged the analytic-synthetic distinction in his classic article, “Two dogmas of empiricism”. Quine’s response (in a move that some other philosophers, including Sellars, also favoured) was a kind of holism: our commitments face the ‘tribunal of experience’ together, rather than individually. Further, the ‘analytic’ truths can also be changed, if that’s the best way to accommodate experience.

Late Logical Empiricism Theories are logically closed sets of sentences. They are connected to observation by ‘bridge rules’ that link observations to the theoretical vocabulary. A successful theory will be confirmed by the combination of observations and bridge rules. If there is trouble (a contradiction between the observations made and the theory’s commitments) then how to respond is decided holistically, by a kind of cost-benefit calculus—any sentence in the theory can be given up, if doing so accommodates experience better. Explanation is a matter of deriving some pattern in our observations from other observations and theoretical principles. (Deductive-nomological explanation)

The theoretician’s dilemma This paper by Hempel proposed (as Carnap also maintained) that the contribution theoretical language makes to our understanding of the world is exhausted by the theory’s implications for patterns expressed in the observation language. Thus, even though we have words like ‘electron’ in our theory that seem to refer to strange, unobservable objects which play a role in explaining what we observe, the meaning of these words lies only in what the theory (which uses them) implies about our observations: science is about the ‘surface’ of things only, not what lies beneath it. (See also Carnap, “The methodological character of theoretical concepts”.)

What is hidden? Are electrons really hidden? Van Fraassen’s example: high energy electrons can be directly detected as flashes of ‘light’ produced when they strike our retinas. Shapere: Observation in science and (traditional) philosophy seem rather different: Consider neutrinos and the interior of the sun.

Puzzled by induction Ampliative reasoning: Induction (from particular cases to generalizations) Projection (from past cases to new cases) Explanatory inference (inference from data to conclusions that explain the data– e.g. the Alvarez hypothesis).

Hypothetical deductivism A theoretical claim is confirmed when consequences of the claim are observed to be true. In a simple version this is clearly wrong. But it fits so many familiar examples of good science that it’s hard to give up altogether.s

A puzzle about some simple rules for induction Nicod’s criterion: An instance of an A that is B confirms all A’s are B’s. Equivalence rule: If some evidence confirms a sentence P, it confirms any logically equivalent sentence. ‘All Ravens are Black’ is equivalent to ‘All non-black things are non-Ravens’. It follows that white sneakers confirm ‘All Ravens are black’.

Goodman’s riddle Grue: Observed before or at t and green or observed after t and blue. Bleen: Observed before or at t and blue or observed after t and green. Let t be midnight, Decmber 31 2009. Then all observed emeralds are grue. Should we infer by simple induction that all emeralds are grue?

Curve-fitting Given just some points on a graph indicating observed relations between some quantities, how do we ‘project’ to arrive at a general pattern or rule relating them? These problems were never satisfactorily solved, although there are many ideas about how we might make some progress with them.