Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Economics of Information (ECON3016)
Advertisements

From risk to opportunity Lecture 11 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.
(Single-item) auctions Vincent Conitzer v() = $5 v() = $3.
Choice under Uncertainty. Introduction Many choices made by consumers take place under conditions of uncertainty Therefore involves an element of risk.
Auction Theory Class 5 – single-parameter implementation and risk aversion 1.
CPS Bayesian games and their use in auctions Vincent Conitzer
ECON 100 Tutorial: Week 9 office: LUMS C85.
Seminar in Auctions and Mechanism Design Based on J. Hartline’s book: Approximation in Economic Design Presented by: Miki Dimenshtein & Noga Levy.
Chapter 12 Uncertainty Consider two lotteries L 1 : 500,000 (1) L 1 ’: 2,500,000 (0.1), 500,000 (0.89), 0 (0.01) Which one would you choose? Another two.
Utility Theory.
Decisions under Uncertainty
Auctions. Strategic Situation You are bidding for an object in an auction. The object has a value to you of $20. How much should you bid? Depends on auction.
Michael R. Baye, Managerial Economics and Business Strategy, 3e. ©The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc., 1999 Managerial Economics & Business Strategy Chapter.
Private-value auctions: theory and experimental evidence (Part I) Nikos Nikiforakis The University of Melbourne.
1 1 Slide © 2009 South-Western, a part of Cengage Learning Slides by John Loucks St. Edward’s University.
1 Decision Making and Utility Introduction –The expected value criterion may not be appropriate if the decision is a one-time opportunity with substantial.
Decision Theory Lecture 8. 1/3 1 1/4 3/8 1/4 3/8 A A B C A B C 1/2 A B A C Reduction of compound lotteries 1/2 1/4 A B C.
1 Decisions under uncertainty A Different look at Utility Theory.
Risk Attitude Dr. Yan Liu
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2008 Lecture 4 – Sept
Rational Expectations and the Aggregation of Diverse Information in Laboratory Security Markets Charles R. Plott, Shyam Sunder.
Decision-Making under Uncertainty – Part I Topic 4.
An Introduction to Game Theory Part I: Strategic Games
1 Utility Theory. 2 Option 1: bet that pays $5,000,000 if a coin flipped comes up tails you get $0 if the coin comes up heads. Option 2: get $2,000,000.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
L1: Risk and Risk Measurement1 Lecture 1: Risk and Risk Measurement We cover the following topics in this part –Risk –Risk Aversion Absolute risk aversion.
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior
Last Day Utility Analysis. Today Utility Analysis (cont’d) International Diversification.
Notes – Theory of Choice
Extensions to Consumer theory Inter-temporal choice Uncertainty Revealed preferences.
LECTURE 2 : UTILITY AND RISK AVERSION (Asset Pricing and Portfolio Theory)
Games in the normal form- An application: “An Economic Theory of Democracy” Carl Henrik Knutsen 5/
Basic Tools of Finance Finance is the field that studies how people make decisions regarding the allocation of resources over time and the handling of.
Lecture 3: Arrow-Debreu Economy
Investment Analysis and Portfolio Management
GAMES AGAINST NATURE Topic #3. Games Against Nature In game theory, for reasons that will be explained later, the alternatives (e.g., LEFT and RIGHT)
Decision Analysis (cont)
STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE APPROACH TO PORTFOLIO OPTIMIZATION Nesrin Alptekin Anadolu University, TURKEY.
Auction Seminar Optimal Mechanism Presentation by: Alon Resler Supervised by: Amos Fiat.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Chapters 23, 24 and 25 CHOICE UNDER RISK Chapter 23: The Budget Constraint. Chapter 24: The Expected Utility Model. Chapter.
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 4.
1 Chapter 7 Applying Simulation to Decision Problems.
Chapter 5 Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior. ©2005 Pearson Education, Inc.Chapter 52 Q: Value of Stock Investment in offshore drilling exploration: Two.
Topic 2: Designing the “optimal auction” Reminder of previous classes: Discussed 1st price and 2nd price auctions. Found equilibrium strategies. Saw that.
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Diversification of Parameter Uncertainty Eric R. Ulm Georgia State University.
Lecture 3 on Individual Optimization Uncertainty Up until now we have been treating bidders as expected wealth maximizers, and in that way treating their.
Decision theory under uncertainty
The Economics of Information and Choice Under Uncertainty.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
6.853: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Fall 2011 Constantinos Daskalakis Lecture 22.
Allais Paradox, Ellsberg Paradox, and the Common Consequence Principle Then: Introduction to Prospect Theory Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making.
Utility An economic term referring to the total satisfaction received from consuming a good or service. A consumer's utility is hard to measure. However,
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Increasing Risk Lecture IX. Fall 2004Increasing Risk2 Literature Required u Over the next several lectures, I would like to develop the notion of stochastic.
Microeconomics Course E John Hey. Chapter 26 Because we are all enjoying risk so much, I have decided not to cover Chapter 26 (on the labour market)
On Investor Behavior Objective Define and discuss the concept of rational behavior.
1 Systems Analysis Methods Dr. Jerrell T. Stracener, SAE Fellow SMU EMIS 5300/7300 NTU SY-521-N NTU SY-521-N SMU EMIS 5300/7300 Utility Theory Applications.
Money and Banking Lecture 11. Review of the Previous Lecture Application of Present Value Concept Internal Rate of Return Bond Pricing Real Vs Nominal.
Risk Efficiency Criteria Lecture XV. Expected Utility Versus Risk Efficiency In this course, we started with the precept that individual’s choose between.
Advanced Subjects in GT Prepared by Rina Talisman Introduction Revenue Equivalence The Optimal Auction (Myerson 1981) Auctions.
1 Civil Systems Planning Benefit/Cost Analysis Scott Matthews Courses: / / Lecture 16.
L6: Risk Sharing and Asset Pricing1 Lecture 6: Risk Sharing and Asset Pricing The following topics will be covered: Pareto Efficient Risk Allocation –Defining.
Portfolio Theory & Related Topics
Tools for Decision Analysis: Analysis of Risky Decisions
Rate of Return and Risk.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey.
Risk Chapter 11.
Presentation transcript:

Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion Last lecture we investigated the independence axiom and the expected utility hypothesis. A more direct approach is to design experiments that reveal a person’s attitudes towards risk and uncertainty, the topic of today’s lecture.

Certainty Equivalence Instead of pursuing an axiomatic approach to modeling human behavior under uncertainty, we could more directly determine their attitude towards risk. An important concept is how much a person is willing to pay to avoid a risk, or equivalently, how much they are willing to pay to gamble. (Parenthetically we note that gambling is one of the biggest recreational activities in the U.S.)

Measuring certainty equivalence How much a person is willing to pay for a lottery depends both on the person and also on the lottery. Experimental methods have been used to determine a person’s certainty equivalent to well specified lotteries. In this class we shall consider lotteries which have up to 11 outcomes. They offer the chance to pay $100 with probability p10, $90 with probability p9, . . . , and $0 with probability p0.

An experiment In this experiment you are asked to how much you are willing to pay for a lottery called L when you know its probabilities. Call that number b for bid. We then draw a random number n from a probability distribution which lies between (that has support on) 0 and 100. If n  b, then you pay n in exchange for the lottery L, and receive the payoff from playing the lottery. If b < n, then you neither pay nor receive anything.

The lotteries Each of these lotteries can be defined by 10 numbers (lying the 10 dimensional simplex), where the first element is p10, the second is p9, and so on. We only have to write down 10 elements even though there are 11 outcomes because: p0 = 1 - p10 - p9 - . . . - p1. The lotteries you will bid on are listed below: (0.5, 0, 0, . . . ,0) (0.0909’, 0.0909’, . . . ., 0.0909’) (0.1, 0.1, . . . ., 0.1, 0.1)

Verbal explanation The first lottery pays $100 half the time and $0 half the time. The second lottery pays $100 one eleventh of the time, $90 one eleventh of the time, . . ., and $0 eleventh tenth of the time. The third lottery pays $100 one tenth of the time, $90 one tenth of the time, . . ., and $10 one tenth of the time, so always pays out something.

Bidding below your certainty equivalent Suppose your certainty equivalent lottery for L is the value v. How should you choose b? If you bid b < v you gain v – n whenever n  b, and zero otherwise. This bidding strategy guarantees that you never lose. However if b < n < v, you miss the gain from buying the lottery at a price less than your valuation. If you had bid between n and v instead, you would have gained v – n.

Bidding above your certainty equivalent If you bid b > v, you gain v – n whenever n  v and you lose n – v if v < n  b. Otherwise b < n and you neither gain nor lose. The potential for loss from this strategy can be mitigated by reducing your bid. If you bid some number b1 between v and b, then you still gain v – n whenever n  v and you don’t lose anything if v  b1 < n  b.

Optimal bidding strategy The two previous slides have probably convinced you that the optimal choice is to bid b = v. In this case you gain v – n whenever n  v and zero otherwise. Therefore experimental subjects who know how to make an optimal bid will truthfully reveal their certainty equivalent v for the lottery L.

Expected utility and certainty equivalence Suppose the outcomes called x are ordered by your own preferences from the worst to the best, and let u(x) denote the utility from the random variable x. (For example money outcomes are always ordered that way, since more is preferred to less!) Assume your preferences obey the expected utility hypothesis. Then your expected utility from playing a lottery F is EF[u(x)], where E denotes the expectations operator. It follows that your certainty equivalent for F is the value vF which solves u(vF) = EF[u(x)]

Expected utility and attitudes towards risk In this case we can characterize you attitude towards risk quite simply. If you are risk neutral, then vF = EF[x] for all F, and hence we can write u(x) = x. If you are a risk lover, meaning vF > EF[x] for all F, then u(x) is convex. If you are a risk avoider, meaning vF < EF[x] for all F, then u(x) is concave.

First-order stochastic dominance Consider two different probability distributions F(x) and G(x). That is F(x)  G(x) for some real number x. We say that F first-order stochastically dominates G if and only F(x)  G(x) for all x. This is formally equivalent to saying that if x is a random variable drawn from G(x), if y is a random variable that only takes on positive values, and F(z) is the probability distribution function for z = x + y, then F first-order stochastically dominates G.

An example Notice that the the third lottery first-order stochastically dominates the second.

First Order Stochastic Dominance illustrated

First-order stochastic dominance and expected utility Now consider those people who obey the expected utility hypothesis, and order the outcomes x, a random variable from the lowest (least preferred) to the highest (most preferred). They obtain expected utility EF[u(x)] from playing lottery F, but the function u(x) differs from person to person. Can we rank EF[u(x)] and EG[u(x)] when F first order stochastically dominates G?

Theorem If F first-order stochastically dominates G, then every expected utility maximizer with u(x) increasing in x, prefers F to G.

Second-order stochastic dominance Consider two different probability distributions F(x) and G(y) with the same mean. That is EF[x]= EG[x]. We say that F second-order stochastically dominates G if and only for all t: This is saying that if x is a random variable drawn from G(x), if y is a random variable with mean 0, and that probability distribution function for z = x + y is F(z) , then F second-order stochastically dominates G.

Example X

Second-order stochastic dominance and expected utility Assume a person follows the expected utility hypothesis, and thus obtains expected utility EF[u(x)] from playing a lottery F. We now assume u(x) is concave increasing in x, implying that the person is risk averse, but we impose no other restrictions on u(x). Suppose EF[x]= EG[x]. Then a risk averse person prefers F to G, that is vG  vF if and only if F second-order stochastically dominates G.

Another theorem Suppose F and G have the same mean. Then a risk averse person prefers F to G if and only if F second-order stochastically dominates G.

Investing in a risky asset We now modify the lottery experiment. Instead of bidding on a lottery, you are asked to choose how many units of each independently distributed lottery you would like to buy A unit of each lottery costs $50, and you can spend up to $50,000. Your total payoff are your lottery winnings plus unspent cash. The payoff from the lotteries you are listed below: - Firm A : [$10 with probability 0.5 and $100 with probability 0.5] - Firm B : [$10 with probability 0.1, $20 with probability 0.10, . . ., $100 with probability 0.1] - Firm C : [$20 with probability 0.2, $30 with 0.1, $40 with probability 0.1,. . ., $100 with probability 0.1]

Optimal Insurance A risk averse person fully insures himself against a calamity if actuarially fair insurance is available. This follows from the fact that for risk averters the certainty equivalent of a gamble is greater than its expected value. By the same argument we have used on portfolio choices, a risk averter will not fully insure himself if the rates are not actuarially fair. He will retain ownership over a portion of the lottery.