Week 5. A Paradox of Material Constitution

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Immanuel Kant ( ) Theory of Aesthetics
Advertisements

Equality vs. Entitlement
Meditation IV God is not a Deceiver, Truth Criterion & Problem of Error.
On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time
The ontological argument. I had the persuasion that there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor.
Dualism. Substance Dualism : Human beings have both a material body and an immaterial mind.
Basic Concepts of Democracy
PH251 Metaphysics Week 8. The Special Composition Question.
Summer 2011 Tuesday, 8/ No supposition seems to me more natural than that there is no process in the brain correlated with associating or with.
CAN I KILL MY YOUNGER SELF? Time Travel and the Retro-Suicide Paradox Peter B. M. Vranas The University of Michigan 15 September 2000.
Personal Identity. CAUSAL EFFICACY OF CONTENT Breaking Glass o.
Ambiguous contents? Arvid Båve, Higher seminar in Theoretical Philosophy, FLoV, Gothenburg University, 8 May 2013.
Two puzzles about omnipotence
LECTURE 24 THE NATURE OF PERSONS PHYSICALISM AND DUALISM (“WHAT AM I?)
Gibbard, “Contingent Identity” Against Kripke, for whom identity statements involving names (rigid designators) are necessary. Gibbard wants to argue that.
David Lewis, “Counterparts and Double Lives” Modal Realism: “When I profess realism about possible worlds, I mean to be taken literally. Possible worlds.
PH251 Metaphysics Week 7. Persistence and Temporal Parts.
PH251 Metaphysics Week 4. Particulars. Some preliminaries Particulars = commonsense material particulars are the Aristotelian primary substances. (You,
Phil 160 Kant.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 8 Moore’s Non-naturalism
PH251 Metaphysics Week 3. Properties. Introduction We seem to distinguish between particular things and their properties. We distinguish between me and.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 6 Ayer and Emotivism By David Kelsey.
Persons, Persistence & Tuvix: What Makes Me “Me” From One Moment to the Next? Jim Fahey Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute Philosophy Group – Department.
PH251 Metaphysics Week 9. Neo-Aristotelian theories of Substance.
PHL 201 March 18, 2004  Quiz #3 Answers  Next Quiz – Mar. 26 (new format)  Essay Assignments  Chapter Four – The Self  Faculty Course Surveys.
Substance dualism: do Descartes’ arguments work? Michael Lacewing
The Modal Argument. Review: The “Hard Problem”  Remember that there are three arguments that make consciousness a ‘hard’ problem. 1. Knowledge Argument.
Persistence of Simple Substances University of Durham, November 19, 2009 Dr Jani Hakkarainen (University of Tampere) Dr Markku Keinänen (University of.
History of Philosophy Lecture 12 Thomas Aquinas
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
Descartes argument for dualism
The Mind-Brain Type Identity Theory
BERKELEY’S CASE FOR IDEALISM (Part 2 of 2)
David Lewis Counterfactuals and Possible Worlds. David Lewis American philosopher, lived between UCLA and Princeton Modal realism.
Cartwright, “Scattered Objects” Following Hobbes, “a body is that, which having no dependence on our thought, is coincident or coextended with some part.
KNOWLEDGE What is it? How does it differ from belief? What is the relationship between knowledge and truth? These are the concerns of epistemology How.
Questioning Natural Rights: Utilitarianism ER 11, Spring 2012.
Thomson, “Parthood and Identity Across Time” Thomson’s aim is to argue against the thesis of temporal parts. I Make a Tinkertoy house, H, and place it.
John Locke ( ) Influential both as a philosopher (Essay Concerning Human Understanding) and as a political thinker (Two Treatises on Government)
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
Equations, Inequalities, and Mathematical Models 1.2 Linear Equations
Philosophy 2803 – Health Ethics Andrew Latus. Introduction Ethics Study of right and wrong/good and bad A Branch of Philosophy Central Question = “How.
02 Truth and Rationality Philosophy. 2 Part I: Sentences and Propositions.
Arguments for God’s existence.  What are we arguing for?
Substance dualism Michael Lacewing
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 13 Minds and Bodies #2 (Physicalism) By David Kelsey.
The Four Causes Aristotle. Aristotle was the first philosopher to understand that not all “why”, questions can be answered the same way, because their.
Proof of God? Inquiries into the Philosophy of Religion A Concise Introduction Chapter 12 Faith and Reason By Glenn Rogers, Ph.D. Copyright © 2012 Glenn.
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE Some topics and historical issues of the 20 th century.
FOUNDATIONS OF DEMOCRACY. BASIC NOTIONS OF DEMOCRACY  1. Recognition of the fundamental worth and dignity of every person  2. Respect for the equality.
Instructor: Todd Ganson.  Φιλοσοφία (philo-sophia)
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
The objective of this 10 slide presentation is to:  Identify “roadblocks” to moral discourse.  Give your “roadblock” in class  Evaluate the content.
Particulars and Properties Lecture two: The concrete and the abstract.
Lecture 8 Time: McTaggart’s argument
Lecture 1 What is metaphysics?
Lecture 7 Modality: Metaphysics of possible worlds
Cosmological arguments from contingency
Lecture 5 Particulars: substratum and substance theories
Lecture 11 Persistence: arguments for perdurance
Lecture 10 Persistence: endurance and perdurance
Lecture 4 Particulars: bundle theory
Time and Change Parmenides vs. Heraclitus:
Descartes’ proof of the external world
The zombie argument: responses
The Problem of Evil.
Puzzles of Material Constitution
Get Yourself Thinking…
Animalism.
The ship of Theseus Theodor Sider, «Four-dimentionalism. An ontology of persistence and time», Clarendon Press, 2001.
Presentation transcript:

Week 5. A Paradox of Material Constitution PH251 Metaphysics Week 5. A Paradox of Material Constitution

A Paradox of Material Constitution: The Statue and the Lump x = Statue y = Lump (1) x goes out of existence at t5 (2) y does not go out of existence at t5 (3) If x is F but y is not F then x ≠ y (4) x ≠ y (5) x and y occupy the same place (and have all of the same parts) at t4 But: (6) No two distinct concrete material particulars can occupy the same place (and can have all of the same parts) at the same time. Assuming that x and y are concrete material particulars, (5) and (6) are inconsistent.

The Standard Story Statue and Lump are distinct Statue constitutes Lump Constitution is not identity

The Standard Story (Where ‘T’ is a tree and ‘W’ is the aggregate of cellulose molecules which occupies the volume of space occupied by the tree) ‘The ‘is’ of constitution is not the ‘is’ of identity. The tree is made of (or constituted of or consists of) W, but is not identical with W. And ‘A is something over and above B\ denies ‘A s (wholly composed of) B’ of ‘A is merely (or merely consists of) B. If A is something over and above B, then of course A ≠ B, but the proper point of saying “over and above” is to make the further denial that B fully exhausts the matter of A. But W does fully exhaust T and so T is not something over and above W.” (Wiggins, 1968: 4 (in Rea (1997) reprint)

The Standard Story: Problems Too many objects The Grounding Problem (a) A difference between x and y with respect to what they can do or the changes that they can undergo requires a difference between the parts of x and y. (b) There is no difference between the parts of x and y (c) Therefore x and y cannot differ with respect to what they can do or the changes that they can undergo.

Alternative Accounts Eliminativism (at least, the version in Ayers (1974) Dominant Kinds Relative Identity Temporal Parts (alternative?)

Ayers (1974) In so far as we take Lump to be a mass of clay that can persist through various kinds of deformation, and in so far as Statue is something that exists, Statue is identical with the piece of clay that is Lump. Insofar as it is identical with that piece of clay, though, Statue existed prior to t3 and exists after t5. So, (2) in the argument above is false.

Ayers (1974) “What does happen to a statue when a vandal beats it out of shape, if it is not destroyed? And what is a sculptor bringing about if he is not creating a statue? In so far as these questions do not answer themselves, a suitable reply to the first is that a piece of metal (TC: or clay) is ceasing to be a statue, and to the second, that a piece of metal is coming to be a statue. We can talk of destruction and creation if we like, for such talk can be fairly unserious, or at least detachable from considerations of substantial continuity.  

Ayers (1974) “..I can create an eyesore by cutting down a tree or destroy an aesthetic whole by painting my house red, white and blue. We could say that what the vandal is destroying is a shape or form. None of this gives any grounds for arguing that one thing the statue, ceases to exist, while another thing, the piece of metal (TC: or clay), continues existing…”

Ayers (1974) “..Paperweights are physical objects, and it is possible to make paperweights by scratching patterns on pebbles, but this is not a way of making physical objects. It is a way of making certain physical objects into paperweights. A pebble can become a saleable paperweight without changing at all, to revive a point made by Robert Boyle against teleology.” (1974: 128)

Problems and Difficulties 1. Statues are not substantial and enduring things that come into existence after shaping. Is that coherent with our commonsense view? 2. Worries about the ambiguity of “That statue cannot be crushed into a ball” on Ayers (1974) account, though seems straightforwardly true.

Burke (1994): Dominant Kinds Piece 1= The lump of clay which exists prior to the shaping into a statue Piece 2= The lump of clay which exists once the shaping has been completed Statue = The entity that comes into existence when the shaping has been completed. (iv) The argument for the distinctness claim at the core of the standard story is that: (a) Piece 1 and Piece 2 are identical; (b) Piece 1 and Statue are distinct; so: (c) Statue and Piece 2 must be distinct.

Burke (1994): Dominant Kinds (v) Burke (1994) maintains that the correct response to the argument is to deny (a). It is not the case that Piece 1 and Piece 2 are identical. The particular object which was the lump of clay prior to its being shaped into a statue is a different particular object than that lump of clay that exists after the shaping has been performed. Why?

Dominant Sortals “I agree that every sortal has an associated set of persistence conditions, but I hold that every composite object that is not a mere aggregate satisfies at least two sortals, one being ‘aggregate’. For example Piece 2 (=Statue) is (predicatively) a piece of copper (clay), a statue, and an aggregate (…of clay particles…) I hold that among the sortals satisfied by an object, one is the object’s “dominant” sortal.

Dominant Sortals Let’s say that sortal F is object o’s dominant sortal just in case o has the persistence conditions it has in consequence of satisfying F. And let’s say that sortal F dominates sortal G, with respect to o, just in case (1) o satisfies both F and G, and (2) F, not G, is o’s dominant sortal. With respect to Piece 2, for example, ‘statue’ dominates both ‘piece of (clay)’ and ‘aggregate (of clay particles)’. (Burke (1994) (in Rea (1997): 247).

Dominant Sortals When one sortal comes to ‘dominate’ another, an object goes out of existence. “On my account, an object that has the persistence conditions it has in consequence of satisfying F can persist only so long as it does not undergo changes that would cause it to satisfy a sortal that dominates F. Thus a mere piece of copper (clay) could not survive the changes that would make it a statue.

Dominant Sortals On my account, therefore, but not on the standard account, a mere piece of copper (clay) would be destroyed by changes that would cause it to be co-extensive with a statue. (On the standard account, of course, such changes would cause the piece of copper to be coincident with a statue, not to be a statue.) ((1994) (in Rea(ed.) (1997): 251).

Difficulties Could manipulating the clay destroy an object?! How to answer the “Which One?” question ‘Of the sortals satisfied by an object, the one that tells the object’s sort is the one whose satisfaction entails possession of the widest range of properties.” ((1994)(1997 reprint p.252)

Relative Identity (i) The argument for the distinctness of the statue and the piece of clay relies on the indiscernibility of identicals, a principle that also goes by the name ‘Leibniz’s Law’. (LL) For any x and y, if x = y then x and y share all their properties. This principle dictates that if x has one property F that y lacks then x is not the same as y. Relative identity theorists deny this

Relative Identity Geach (1962) argues for the view that identity is relative, in the sense that it is never the case that A = B simpliciter, but that A is always, for example, the same F (say, the same cat) as B or the same G (say, the same collection of material particles) as B. (iv) Identity is not a two-place relation ‘___ = ____’ or ‘____is the same as _____’ but the three-place ‘___is the same____ as _____’ Any other notion of identity as absolute is unintelligible.

Relative Identity (iii) Geach (1962) maintains that it is possible for A to be the same F as B but not the same G as B. X may be same man but not same office-holder as Y T1 may be same tree but not same mass of cellulose particles as T2 Suggestion: x and y are the same lump, the same piece of clay, but not the same statue. What the difference in behavior shows is that they are not identical under one sortal. But this does not show that they are not identical under another such sortal, as they are, (nor that they fail to be absolutely distinct).

Problems Denying Leibniz’s Law is a very high price to pay. It is not clear that the move to ‘relative identity’ solves the initial problem. The problem reappears when identity is relativized to a sortal.

Sider (2001): Temporal Parts (i) Start with ‘four-dimensionalism’ about time and about objects in time. We can think of time as a dimension analogous to space. Both time and things in time exist also in the fourth dimension. (ii) Things do not exist all at once, or whole, at a time, and then persist in their entirety. They are spread out in time. The only way that the are ‘wholly present’ is across the period of time they exist.

Sider (2001): Temporal Parts (iii) You and I are not beings that exist whole all at once, but across time, as ‘space-time worms’. At any particular time, we have spatial parts. But we also, considered as an entity that has an existence spread out in time, have temporal parts. (iv) Temporal parts are either momentary or extended temporal stages of the being you are. There is a temporal part of me which is ‘TC on 5-3-2015’ say. This stage is a part of me in broadly the same way that my finger is a spatial part of me.

Sider (2001): Temporal Parts (v) Set aside questions about foundations of the view (vi) Sider (2001) argues that four-dimensionalism offers an attractive solution to the paradoxes of material constitution. (a) Statue is distinct from Lump (b) The distinctness of Statue and Lump does not violate the principle that if things have all of their parts in common they are identical (Lump has temporal parts that Statue lacks). (c) Statue is distinct from Lump in being a part of the lump, in the way that my hand is distinct from me in the sense that it is a part of me.