What really happens upon quantum measurement?[n eeds revision] References are more fully listed in my Phys Rev A paperPhys Rev A paper Art Hobson Prof.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
1 Taoufik AMRI. Overview 3 Chapter II Quantum Protocols Chapter III Quantum States and Propositions Chapter VI Detector of « Schrödingers Cat » States.
Advertisements

Quantum Computing MAS 725 Hartmut Klauck NTU
Experiments in “Quantum Erasure” and “Delayed Choice” Preventing the simultaneous acquisition of probabilistic and deterministic results for the same result.
Quantum Information Stephen M. Barnett University of Strathclyde The Wolfson Foundation.
1 quantum teleportation David Riethmiller 28 May 2007.
Quantum Control of Wave- Particle Duality Robert Mann D. Terno, R. Ionicioiu, T. Jennewein.
Cove: A Practical Quantum Computer Programming Framework Matt Purkeypile Fall 2008.
Durham University – Atomic & Molecular Physics group
Quantum One: Lecture 3. Implications of Schrödinger's Wave Mechanics for Conservative Systems.
郭劼 Schrodinger’s cat 1, It is a paradox Paradox is a statement that when you assume it wrong, you can launch it right ; on the contrary, assume.
Gaitskell PH0008 Quantum Mechanics and Special Relativity Lecture ?? (Quantum Mechanics) TEST FILE Prof Rick Gaitskell Department of Physics Brown.
Bell inequality & entanglement
The GSI oscillation mystery Alexander Merle Max-Planck-Institute for Nuclear Physics Heidelberg, Germany Based on: AM: Why a splitting in the final state.
6/9/2015Bell's Theorem1 Spooky Action at a Distance Bell’s Theorem and the Demise of Local Reality Natalia Parshina Peter Johnson Josh Robertson Denise.
Backward Evolving Quantum State Lev Vaidman 2 March 2006.
Quantum Mechanics 101 Waves? or Particles? Interference of Waves and the Double Slit Experiment  Waves spreading out from two points, such as waves.
Advanced Computer Architecture Lab University of Michigan Quantum Noise and Distance Patrick Cassleman More Quantum Noise and Distance Measures for Quantum.
Almost all detection of visible light is by the “photoelectric effect” (broadly defined.) There is always a threshold photon energy for detection, even.
Quantum Mechanics from Classical Statistics. what is an atom ? quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum field theory.
Quantum Physics Mach-Zehnder
Quantum Computing Marek Perkowski Part of Computational Intelligence Course 2007.
Quantum Computing Lecture 1 Michele Mosca. l Course Outline
Quantum correlations. Adam W. Majewski. Quantum entanglement. Ghhjhjj Quantum entanglement is a phenomenon that occurs when particles (subsystems) are.
Quantum theory and Consciousness This is an interactive discussion. Please feel free to interrupt at any time with your questions and comments.
School of something FACULTY OF OTHER School of Physics and Astronomy FACULTY OF MATHEMATICAL AND PHYSICAL SCIENCES Introduction to entanglement Jacob Dunningham.
SCHRODINGER’S CAT Group 1: Sudheer, Venkatesh, Hrudil, Praveen.
In 1887,when Photoelectric Effect was first introduced by Heinrich Hertz, the experiment was not able to be explained using classical principles.
Quantum, classical & coarse-grained measurements Johannes Kofler and Časlav Brukner Faculty of Physics University of Vienna, Austria Institute for Quantum.
School of something FACULTY OF OTHER School of Physics and Astronomy FACULTY OF MATHEMATICAL AND PHYSICAL SCIENCES Nonlocality of a single particle Jacob.
From the previous discussion on the double slit experiment on electron we found that unlike a particle in classical mechanics we cannot describe the trajectory.
Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy Significant content from: “Quantum Mechanics and Experience” by David Z. Albert, Harvard University Press.
University of Gdańsk, Poland
The Quantum Measurement Problem Art Hobson Professor Emeritus of Physics University of Arkansas, Fayetteville Handout: Phys Rev A paperPhys Rev A paper.
School of something FACULTY OF OTHER School of Physics and Astronomy FACULTY OF MATHEMATICAL AND PHYSICAL SCIENCES “Classical entanglement” and cat states.
Steering witnesses and criteria for the (non-)existence of local hidden state (LHS) models Eric Cavalcanti, Steve Jones, Howard Wiseman Centre for Quantum.
A comparison between Bell's local realism and Leggett-Garg's macrorealism Group Workshop Friedrichshafen, Germany, Sept 13 th 2012 Johannes Kofler.
The Road to Quantum Computing: Boson Sampling Nate Kinsey ECE 695 Quantum Photonics Spring 2014.
Lecture 2. Postulates in Quantum Mechanics
Atomic Particles  Atoms are made of protons, neutrons and electrons  % of the atom is empty space  Electrons have locations described.
Interference in BEC Interference of 2 BEC’s - experiments Do Bose-Einstein condensates have a macroscopic phase? How can it be measured? Castin & Dalibard.
Quantum Physics II.
Decoherence Demo (with 2-slit interference demo) Scott Johnson Intel Press Play to begin.
A condition for macroscopic realism beyond the Leggett-Garg inequalities APS March Meeting Boston, USA, March 1 st 2012 Johannes Kofler 1 and Časlav Brukner.
Quantum Computing by Mathew Ross Jared Davis - Group L -
DUALITY PARTICLE WAVE PARTICLE DUALITY WAVE © John Parkinson.
Quantum Mechanics1 Schrodinger’s Cat. Quantum Mechanics2 A particular quantum state, completely described by enough quantum numbers, is called a state.
Gerard ’t Hooft, quant-ph/ Erice, September 6, 2006 Utrecht University 1.
1 entanglement-quantum teleportation entanglement-quantum teleportation entanglement (what is it?) quantum teleportation (intuitive & mathematical) ‘ quantum.
Physics 2170 – Spring Some interesting aspects of quantum mechanics The last homework is due at 12:50pm.
MS310 Quantum Physical Chemistry
Indefinite causal order in quantum mechanics Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna & Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information, Vienna Mateus.
The EPR Paradox, Bell’s inequalities, and its significance By: Miles H. Taylor.
Quantum Imaging MURI Kick-Off Meeting Rochester, June 9-10, Entangled state and thermal light - Foundamental and applications.
The Transactional Interpretation: an introduction ©2012 R. E. Kastner.
A1 “BASIC QUANTUM MECHANICS, AND SOME SURPRISING CONSEQUENCES” Anthony J. Leggett Department of Physics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Basic Concepts Absolute Size The Superposition Principle Copyright – Michael D. Fayer, 2007 Size Classical MechanicsQuantum Mechanics RelativeAbsolute.
Chapter 3 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics. Questions QM answers 1) How is the state of a system described mathematically? (In CM – via generalized coordinates.
Quantum Measurements: some technical background “Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments,
Quantum optics Eyal Freiberg.
Quantum Information Promises new insights Anthony J
Quantum mechanics from classical statistics
Quantum One.
Quantum One.
Double Slit Experiment
Heisenberg Uncertainty
Review and suggested resolution of the problem of Schrodinger’s cat
Quantum Mechanics Postulate 4 Describes expansion
Quantum computation with classical bits
Massive non-classical states and the observation of quantum gravity
Time and Quantum from Correlations
Presentation transcript:

What really happens upon quantum measurement?[n eeds revision] References are more fully listed in my Phys Rev A paperPhys Rev A paper Art Hobson Prof Emeritus of Physics University of Arkansas

ABSTRACT Measurement causes the measured quantum system to entangle non-locally with the measurement apparatus. Quantum theory, and non-local two-photon interferometry experiments, show that the locally observed states of both subsystems are mixtures of their eigenstates, while the unitarily-evolving composite global state, which can be accessed only by comparing after-the-fact records from the two local subsystems, evolves as a coherent superposition of correlations rather than of subsystem eigenstates. Thus, nature violates the eigenvalue-eigenstate link: Entanglement causes the subsystems to exhibit mixed state outcomes (such as a dead-or-alive Schroedinger’s cat, rather than dead-and-alive), but the subsystems do not actually collapse into the corresponding eigenstates. Instead, the subsystems remain entangled.

OUTLINE I.What’s the problem? II.An enlightening experiment. III.A proposed solution

I. WHAT’S THE PROBLEM? Consider a 2-state (qubit) system S, Hilbert space H S spanned by |s1>, |s2>. Superposition |> S = α|s1> + β|s2>. Ex: 2-slit exp, observed at the slits. |s1> & |s2> represent an electron passing through slit 1 or 2. Apparatus A “measures” S, obtaining a “definite outcome” (eigenvalue) s1 or s2. Measurement postulate: Upon measurement, S instantly “collapses” into either |s1> or |s2>. The problem: If the world obeys Q physics, we should be able to derive this collapse from the Schrodinger eq. for A & S. How to do this?

Let’s set up the problem: (See e.g. Schlosshauer 2007) Assume A has states |ready>, |a1>, |a2> ∊ H A such that: |ready>|s1> → |a1>|s1> and |ready>|s2> → |a2>|s2> --“ideal non-disturbing meas.” Linearity of the Schrodinger evolution implies |ready>|> S → α|a1>|s1> + β|a2>|s2> Note that the meas process entangles S and A. Thus the correlations between S and A are non-local (Gisin 1991). This turns out to be crucial.

Apparent contradictions: |> = α|a1>|s1> + β|a2>|s2> (measurement state, MS) appears to describe a macro superposition of SA with superposed states |a1>|s1> & |a2>|s2>. Ex: If A is Schrodinger’s cat, and S is a radioactive nucleus that kills the cat if it decays, then MS appears to be a superposition of dead & alive. But that’s absurd. Where’s the collapse, to |a1>|s1> or |a2>|s2>? Such a collapse would be non-linear, contradicting the linear Sch. eq. Most experts think the problem is solvable only by altering the quantum fundamentals.

When SA is in the MS, neither S nor A is superposed. E.g. S cannot be described by a state of the form γ|s1>+δ|s2>. Proof: see Phys Rev A paper.Phys Rev A paper So cat is not predicted to be dead & alive. This mistake results from neglect of the non-local connection between S and A. Entangled states are nonlocal (Gisin 1991). Exactly what is superposed in the MS? What interferes? One thing immediately wrong with these conclusions:

II. AN ENLIGHTENING EXPERIMENT The Rarity-Tapster & Ou (RTO, 1990) exp. As we’ll see, there is a problem in the foundations. RTO demonstrates that non-locality is the key to understanding the meas prob. We must distinguish between two kinds of states of entangled systems: local states and the global state. RTO exp shows precisely what is superposed in the MS --It’s not your ordinary superposition!

Exp of Rarity/Tapster, & Ou et al (RTO) Two entangled photons, A & S. The exp, which used beam splitters, variable phase shifters, and photon detectors, is equivalent to the following 2-photon double slit exp: A source sends entangled photon pairs through two Mach-Zehnder interferometers:

Source of two entangled photons photon A path a1 path a2 x mirror y photon S path s2 path s1 With no entanglement, this would be two 2-slit exps: states (|a1>+|a2>)/√2 and (|s1>+|s2>)/√2. Interference fringes at both screens. With entanglement, the photons are in the MS |> = (|a1>|s1> + |a2>|s2> )/√2. Each photon “measures” the other! The RTO exp is a probe of the MS …with variable phases!

Results: In a series of trials, neither screen shows any sign of interference or phase dependence: x & y are distributed randomly; no sign of coherence or superposition. The reason: Each photon acts as a “which path” detector, decohering both, causing each to come through only 1 slit. Locally (i.e. at S’s screen & A’s screen), each photon is described by an incoherent mixture with density operators ρ S = (|s1> <s2|) / 2 ρ A = (|a1> <a2|) / 2. These are not coherent superpositions. But globally S and A are in the MS!

Where does the coherence go? --It can’t vanish, because the Schrodinger evolution is “unitary.” Ans: the correlations become coherent. When coincidences of entangled pairs are detected at A’s and S’s screens: coincidence rate ∝ cos( A - S ) = cos(y-x). Photon A strikes it’s screen randomly at x, and photon S then strikes its screen in an interference pattern around x! And vice- versa. This certainly seems non-local, and in fact the results violate Bell’s inequality. y-x is proportional to the difference of the two phases A - S.

What are “coherent correlations”? If the phase difference is A - S = 0, 2π, …, A and S are correlated: ai occurs iff si occurs. When A - S =π, 3π, 5π,..., A and S are anti- corr: ai occurs iff si does not occur. When A - S =π/2, 3π/2, 5π/2, …, A and S are not at all correlated. This is an interference of correlations between states, rather than the usual single-photon interference of states. A - S =0, 2π, 4π M-Z interferometer:

Bell’s theorem implies…. …that the results are truly non-local: Cannot be explained by “prior causes” or by “causal communication.” If S’s phase shifter changes, the outcomes on A’s (and S’s) screen are instantly (i.e. faster than light) altered. Aspect (1982) tested these predictions (but with photon polarizations): The results confirmed violation of Bell’s ≠ and the observed changes showed up at the distant station sooner than a lightbeam could have gotten there.

III. PROPOSED RESOLUTION The RTO exp shows that, when A & S are in the MS, the local results for A alone and for S alone are correctly described by the incoherent mixtures ρ S = (|s1> <s2|) / 2, ρ A = (|a1> <a2|) / 2. But the non-local, or global, correlations between A and S must be described by the coherent MS |> = α|a1>|s1> + β|a2>|s2>. ρ S and ρ A are local states observed separately at S or A. |> is the global state, observable only by gathering info from both S and A.

In fact, all local observations at S and A must show no sign of S-A correlations. Here’s why: S and A are non-locally connected. Thus all info about S-A correlations must be “camouflaged from” local observers of S & A. The reason: If an observer could, by observing S alone, detect any change when A is changed, A could send an instant signal to S across an arbitrary distance. Special relativity (Einstein causality) does not allow this.

In fact Ballentine 1987 and Eberhard 1989 show that quantum probabilities do just what’s needed: When A alters φ A, only the correlations change—the statistics of the outcomes at S don’t change. RTO exp confirms this. This protection of Einstein causality is a remarkable and delicate feature of quantum entanglement. It is key to the measurement problem. Thus, to a local observer of S, all correlations with A must be “invisible.” Such correlations can be made known to S only by comparing outcomes at S and A— i.e. only via the global state. Thus all physical facts at S or at A must be fully described by the local states.

In other words … ρ S = (|s1> <s2|) / 2 and ρ A = (|a1> <a2|) / 2 describe what is observed at S and at A. Schrodinger’s cat will be either dead or alive, not both. Nevertheless, S & A are actually “in” the global state. They retain a “coherent correlation” not described by ρ S & ρ A. This sounds like a contradiction, but it is not. Instead, the eigenfunction-eigenvalue rule is broken: S exhibits the value s1 or s2, but it’s not in the state |s1> or |s2>. Similarly for A. This resolves the problem (while disproving the standard eigenfunction-eigenvalue connection).

Solution to “problem of outcomes:” The standard quantum axioms imply that, when 2 systems are entangled in the MS, they exhibit definite values s1 or s2 and a1 or a2. However, S and A are not actually in the corresponding eigenstates. They are in the MS. That is, S and A appear to be in the corresponding eigenstates, but they retain non-local (and thus unobservable locally) correlations between them. Thus the postulated collapse, into the corresponding eigenstates, doesn’t occur at the time when S and A become entangled in the MS.

Returning to the RTO exp: RTO separates the problem of outcomes from the problem of irreversibiity. The MS describes S & A after they are emitted from the source but before either photon impacts its screen. The MS is still reversible, in principle. Upon impact, the coherence of the MS transfers to the environment (the screens) as described by Zurek This leaves S & A in mixtures ρ S & ρ A --definite outcomes that are now irreversible i.e. macroscopic & permanent. This locks in specific outcomes. A x y S

THANK YOU!