The Euthyphro dilemma.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Higher RMPS Lesson 3 The Euthyphro dilemma. Learning intentions After todays lesson you will be able to: explain the background to the Euthyphro dilemma.
Advertisements

The idea of morality as a social contract offers an explanation of why its reasonable to act in accordance with the dictates of morality As such it provides.
Anselm On the Existence of God. “Nor do I seek to understand so that I can believe, but rather I believe so that I can understand. For I believe this.
Michael Lacewing The Idea of God Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Euthyphro – initial questions Characters? Setting? Reasons for location? Question? Who asks and why?
Locke v. Leibniz on innate knowledge
The ontological argument. I had the persuasion that there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor.
Support For Morality As A Social Contract
Empiricism on a priori knowledge
God and Morality: why the Euthyphro dilemma matters
Divine command theory the euthyphro argument. conventionalism In some cases, there is no objective moral fact. In some cases, there is an objective moral.
The Ontological Argument. Anselm’s Argument So the fool has to agree that the concept of something than which nothing greater can be thought exists in.
The ontological argument
Religion and Morality Many people believe that morality ultimately depends upon an appeal to the dictates of a higher being. Many people believe that morality.
Timed Writing: An Example
Descartes’ rationalism
Descartes’ cosmological argument
Two puzzles about omnipotence
René Descartes ( ) Father of modern rationalism. Reason is the source of knowledge, not experience. All our ideas are innate. God fashioned us.
Descartes’ trademark argument Michael Lacewing
Socrates and Plato Euthyphro, Apology, and Phaedo Unit 2: Greece Honors 2101, Fall 2006 Bryan Benham.
Knowledge innatism Michael Lacewing
Plato's Euthyphro Question authority “Says who?!”.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 8 Moore’s Non-naturalism
Malcolm’s ontological argument Michael Lacewing
Summer 2011 Thursday, 07/21. Appeals to Intuition Intuitively, it may not seem that the Chinese room has understanding or that the Blockhead or China-brain.
The search for a proper definition of Piety or Holiness
Divine Might Makes Right? Divine Command Theory. As a Metaethical theory, DCT states that … ‘Good’ =df ‘approved of by God. ‘Right’ =df ‘commanded by.
Divine command theory the euthyphro argument. the divine command theory The Divine Command Theory (DCT): There are some objective moral truths. “X is.
Socrates and the Socratic Turn
Euthyphro Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
Euthyphro Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey. Socrates Born 469 BC Lived in Athens Married to Xanthippi Clashed with the Sophists Convicted of impiety.
The Euthyphro dilemma Michael Lacewing
Divine attributes Michael Lacewing
Results from Meditation 2
If God created everything, he is responsible for everything? Today’s lesson will be successful if: You can evaluate the above statement You can begin to.
Is goodness without God good enough?
‘The unexamined life is not worth living.’ Socrates
Discussion Questions 1. Do you know the Ten Commandments? Can you follow all of them? Why or why not? 1. Do you know the Ten Commandments? Can you follow.
Socrates (d. 399 BCE) Plato ( BCE)
Phil 360 Chapter 2. Kohlberg’s Stages of Moral Development Pre-conventional – Punishment and reward Conventional – Community, family, peer, etc. role.
Socrates and Plato The Origin of Philosophy Origin of Western Philosophy Religion and Mythology Greek City-States Athenian Democracy Thales (
Does morality depend on God?
Socrates – The Euthyphro Summary. Background  Socrates due to appear before the court  Encounters Euthyphro who has gained reputation as religious expert.
Euthyphro. The Setting Time: 399 BCE. Place: The porch of the King Archon's Court in Athens. Note: King Archon not the head of the state but one of the.
LO: I will justify my response to the view that Morality can exist without God. CHRISTMAS HOMEWORK: Revise for end of unit assessment on Kantian Ethics.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
The Euthyphro Dilemma Introduction.
Objectives: SWBAT  Debate the role of religion in morality  Identify the strong and weak forms of Divine Command Theory  Critique DCT.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Worries about Ethics Norms & Descriptions. Hume’s gap In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark'd, that the author.
Ontological Argument. Teleological argument depends upon evidence about the nature of the world and the organisms and objects in it. Cosmological argument.
A Mickey Mouse Guide to the Ontological Argument
Morality in the Modern World. Where does morality come from?
Anti-Realism A philosophy which claims statements are true because they cohere with other statements that are accepted as true within a given form of life/society.
Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.
Absolutism and the Euthyphro dilemma LO: I will know what is meant by absolutism I will attempt to resolve the Euthyphro dilemma Hmk: Come up with some.
Inter-relationships Religion and Morality. Relationships Is it true that morality depends on religion, even that it cannot be understood in the context.
Ethics Review Via the Euthyphro. What does Euthyphro think? What position would this be? Suppose Socrates asks only because he thinks piety is whatever.
The Nature of God Nancy Parsons. Attributes- Nature of God Candidates should be able to demonstrate knowledge and understanding of: 1.God as eternal,
Plato’s Euthyphro. Questions to answer 1. Socrates asks Euthyphro to define piety. What is Euthyphro’s first answer? How does Socrates criticize it? 2.
WEEK 4: EPISTEMOLOGY Introduction to Rationalism.
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
Euthyphro.
The Problem of Evil.
Remember these terms? Analytic/ synthetic A priori/ a posteriori
What can you remember? Outline at least one problem with the definition of Omnipotence simply being “Can do anything”. Summarise the Paradox of the.
Euthyphro.
Morality and Religion.
Presentation transcript:

The Euthyphro dilemma

If God is the most perfect possible being, then each of the perfections attributed to God must be possible, and the combination of the perfections must also be possible. Here is a puzzle about God’s omnipotence and perfect goodness. Can God make right be wrong, or good be bad? Is morality whatever God wills it to be or is morality something independent of God? 1. If morality is whatever God wills, then if God wills what is (now) morally wrong, then what is wrong will become right – if God commands us to murder babies, then murdering babies would be morally right. What is morally right is right because God wills it. 2. If morality is independent of what God wills, then God cannot make what is wrong be right – murdering babies is wrong whatever God commands. But then, to be good, God must conform his will to something independent of him. God wills what is morally right because it is right. The answer must be one or the other, but both alternatives can seem unsatisfactory, which creates a dilemma, known as the ‘Euthyphro dilemma’.

This argument leads us back to (1). But as we will see below, To (2), we can object that this places a constraint on God. For instance, if God is supremely good, but morality is independent of God, then God cannot will anything, only what is right. This would mean that God is not omnipotent. Or again, God cannot change what is morally right – so God is not omnipotent. Since God is omnipotent, morality is not a restriction on God’s will, but dependent on it. Or again, if God exists and is good, then everything that is morally good must relate back to God as the ultimate reality. Given the nature of God, morality must depend on God. This argument leads us back to (1). But as we will see below, this also faces strong objections.

In his dialogue Euthyphro, Plato considered the question ‘what is piety?’. Is piety doing whatever the gods want or do the gods want what is pious? Plato argued that both answers seem unsatisfactory, creating a dilemma. (Our version is substitutes ‘morality’ for ‘piety’.) PLATO, EUTHYPHRO In response to Socrates’ questioning, Euthyphro’s first formal definition of piety is ‘that which is dear to the gods’ or again ‘what the gods love’. Socrates then asks whether what is pious is pious because it is loved by the gods, or whether the gods love what is pious because it is pious. Euthyphro answers that the gods love it because it is pious. This makes piety independent of the gods’ love – it would count as piety whether or not the gods love it.

Socrates objects that this can’t be right Socrates objects that this can’t be right. What ‘is dear to the gods is dear to them because it is loved by them, not loved by them because it is dear to them’. Piety, Euthyphro has said, is what is dear to the gods. So piety must be dear to them because they love it. Curiously, Plato doesn’t support this objection with any arguments. The thought is that what the gods value, they value because they love that thing. To accept this means accepting that there aren’t any further reasons for the gods loving what they do. But suppose we agree that piety is independent of what the gods love. So what is it? Euthyphro suggests it is justice in relation to the gods. This requires that we learn how to please them in prayers and sacrifices. This doesn’t bring them any benefit; it simply pleases them. But then, objects Socrates, piety once more becomes whatever pleases the gods – what is pious is pious because the gods love it. Euthyphro has found it impossible to say what piety is, independent of what the gods love.

IS ‘GOD IS GOOD’ A TAUTOLOGY? The discussion so far supports the view that morality is whatever God wills. However, this faces two powerful objections. IS ‘GOD IS GOOD’ A TAUTOLOGY? The first is this: If good is whatever God wills, then ‘God is good’ doesn’t say anything substantial about God. Whatever God wills is by definition good. ‘God is good’ means no more than ‘God wills whatever God wills’. It states a tautology.

Here are two possible replies: Reply: ‘God is good’ means ‘God is good to us’, i.e. God loves us and wants what is best for us. And what is best for us can be understood in a way that is not dependent on whatever God wills. Objection: But then, there is some standard of what is good, viz. what is best for us, which is independent of what God wills. Reply: ‘God is good’ should be understood metaphysically, not morally: ‘God is good’ just means that God has all perfections. Objection: But then what is the connection between the metaphysical sense of ‘good’ and the moral sense of ‘good’? Does God being perfect entail that God is morally good? If so, then ‘God is (morally) good’ is still a tautology. If not, then is morality independent of metaphysical perfection?

MORALITY IS ARBITRARY

The second objection to saying that what is good is whatever God wills is that it makes morality arbitrary. Why does God will what he wills? On this view, there is no moral reason guiding what God will because God invents morality. But if God has no reasons to will what he does, this means that there is no rational structure to morality. The view also entails that it would be right to murder babies if God willed it. This doesn’t seem right! For both these reasons, there must be some independent standard we are implicitly relying on to say that what God wills is, in fact, morally good. We may reply that although God’s will does not respond to anything independent of it, it is not arbitrary. For example, we can appeal to God’s other attributes, such as love. But then aren’t we judging God’s will by the standard of love? If so, morality is still independent of God. But this is a misunderstanding: the claim is not that the basis of morality is love, but that the basis of morality is God’s love. Does this answer make morality arbitrary? Not obviously. God’s will is structured by God’s love, and it is this that creates morality. God wills what he does because he loves. Yet we may still ask: why does God love what he does? Is this arbitrary? If God loved something else, then morality would be different.

GOOD IS THE SAME PROPERTY AS WHAT GOD WILLS A third solution to the Euthyphro dilemma is to say that morality is the same thing as what God wills, but ‘God is good’ is not a tautology. How is this possible? GOOD IS THE SAME PROPERTY AS WHAT GOD WILLS The answer depends on a distinction between concepts and properties. ‘God’ and ‘morally good’ are different concepts. It is not an analytic truth that God is good. However, goodness is the same property as what God wills.

A different example will help A different example will help. ‘Water’ and ‘H2O’ are different concepts, and before the discovery of hydrogen and oxygen, people knew about water. They had the concept of water, but not the concept of H2O. And they didn’t know that water is H2O. So ‘water is H2O’ is not analytically true. However, water and H2O are one and the same thing – the two concepts refer to just one thing in the world. Water is identical to H2O. The same account can be given of ‘good’ and ‘what God wills’ – they are different concepts, and people can have and understand one concept without the other. So ‘God is good’ is not an analytic truth. However, what is good is the same thing as what God wills. It is not something separate which provides a standard for God’s will. Morality is dependent on God. This is a metaphysical truth (about what exists) but not a conceptual truth.

We can object that unless we have an independent standard of goodness, we cannot claim that God’s will and what is good are the same thing. This is true, but it only applies to how we know what is good, not what goodness turns out to be. We can only judge that water is H2O if we have some independent idea of what water is. But that doesn’t mean water is not H2O. Likewise, to judge that what is good is what God wills, we need, at least initially, independent concepts of what is good and of what God wills. Which is fine, since we do form these concepts in distinct ways. But once we think that water is H2O, we will say that whatever is H2O is water. Likewise, once we come to believe that what is good is what God wills, we may use what we believe God’s will to be to start judging what is good. God’s will, we may argue, is our best source of knowledge about what is good.