Cognitive Biases 3. HW2 Problem #1 Here are two sequences of coin-flips. X is one side of the coin, O is the other. XXO, for example, means that the coin.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Reconstruction of Automobile destruction
Advertisements

TEST-TAKING STRATEGIES FOR THE OHIO ACHIEVEMENT READING ASSESSMENT
So You Think You Can Argue? RELA 8 Howelll/Larson All About Writing Persuasively.
CHAPTER 15: Tests of Significance: The Basics Lecture PowerPoint Slides The Basic Practice of Statistics 6 th Edition Moore / Notz / Fligner.
Testing Hypotheses About Proportions
Copyright © 2010, 2007, 2004 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 14 From Randomness to Probability.
Ms. Maxwell Stage 2: Describe.  You have each taken a test to determine how well you keep your minds active while you are reading and remember what you.
Decision Rules. Decision Theory In the final part of the course we’ve been studying decision theory, the science of how to make rational decisions. So.
Order of Operations And Real Number Operations
Probability and Induction
Statistical Hypothesis Testing Popcorn, soda & statistics Null Hypothesis Significance Testing (NHST) Statistical Decisions, Decision Errors & Statistical.
Gl: Students will be expected to conduct simple experiments to determine probabilities G2 Students will be expected to determine simple theoretical probabilities.
Authority 2. HW 8: AGAIN HW 8 I wanted to bring up a couple of issues from grading HW 8. Even people who got problem #1 exactly right didn’t think about.
Cognitive Biases 3. SEEING WHAT WE EXPECT TO SEE.
5.1 day 2 Simulations! .
Probability.
Probability Abney Elementary.
6-1 Stats Unit 6 Sampling Distributions and Statistical Inference - 1 FPP Chapters 16-18, 20-21, 23 The Law of Averages (Ch 16) Box Models (Ch 16) Sampling.
Probability, Part III.
Cognitive Biases I. Optional Reading Today’s lecture is based primarily on: “How We Know What Isn’t So,” Chapter 1. By Thomas Gilovich, a psychologist.
Mathematics in Today's World
Statistical Issues in Research Planning and Evaluation
MM207 Statistics Welcome to the Unit 7 Seminar Prof. Charles Whiffen.
When Intuition Differs from Relative Frequency
Cognitive Biases 2 Incomplete and Unrepresentative Data.
Testing Hypotheses About Proportions Chapter 20. Hypotheses Hypotheses are working models that we adopt temporarily. Our starting hypothesis is called.
Cognitive Biases I. Optional Reading Today’s lecture is based primarily on: “How We Know What Isn’t So,” Chapter 1. By Thomas Gilovich, a psychologist.
Chapter 5 Understanding Randomness
Section 9.1 ~ Fundamentals of Hypothesis Testing Introduction to Probability and Statistics Ms. Young.
Confidence Intervals for Proportions
Readings 25 & 26. Reading 25: Classic Memory and the eye-witness Experiment 1 Experiment 2 Conclusion Reading 26: Contemporary Misinformation Effect Memory.
1 Psych 5500/6500 The t Test for a Single Group Mean (Part 5): Outliers Fall, 2008.
Copyright © 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 19 Confidence Intervals for Proportions.
Cognitive Biases I. Optional Reading Today’s lecture is based primarily on: “How We Know What Isn’t So,” Chapter 1. By Thomas Gilovich, a psychologist.
Memory and the power of suggestion
Chapter 8 Hypothesis testing 1. ▪Along with estimation, hypothesis testing is one of the major fields of statistical inference ▪In estimation, we: –don’t.
Confirmation Bias. Critical Thinking Among our critical thinking questions were: Does the evidence really support the claim? Is there other evidence that.
Bell Work. Have you ever watched someone win a game again and again? Do you think that person just has good luck? In many cases, winners have strategies.
Probability True or False? Answers.
Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc LEARNING GOAL Interpret and carry out hypothesis tests for independence of variables with data organized.
AP STATS: Take 10 minutes or so to complete your 7.1C quiz.
Understanding Randomness
Hypothesis Testing. The 2 nd type of formal statistical inference Our goal is to assess the evidence provided by data from a sample about some claim concerning.
Copyright © 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 19 Confidence Intervals for Proportions.
© 2011 MARS University of NottinghamBeta Version Projector resources: Evaluating Statements About Probability Projector Resources.
Copyright © 2006 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley Slide
Rejecting Chance – Testing Hypotheses in Research Thought Questions 1. Want to test a claim about the proportion of a population who have a certain trait.
Introduction to Psychology What IS Psychology? Why should I care about it?
Reliability of one cognitive process
Factors affecting eyewitness testimony. Eyewitness testimony Eye witnesses who have ‘seen with their own eyes’ tend to be believed more by juries than.
Welcome to MM570 Psychological Statistics
Probability.
1 Binomial Random Variables Lecture 5  Many experiments are like tossing a coin a fixed number of times and recording the up-face.  The two possible.
Copyright © 2010, 2007, 2004 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 19 Confidence Intervals for Proportions.
MATH 256 Probability and Random Processes Yrd. Doç. Dr. Didem Kivanc Tureli 14/10/2011Lecture 3 OKAN UNIVERSITY.
Copyright © 2010, 2007, 2004 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 19 Confidence Intervals for Proportions.
The Chi Square Equation Statistics in Biology. Background The chi square (χ 2 ) test is a statistical test to compare observed results with theoretical.
 What do you think it means for an event to have a probability of ½ ?  What do you think it means for an event to have a probability of 1/4 ?
Loftus & Palmer Cognitive Psychology The Core Studies.
Statistics 11 Understanding Randomness. Example If you had a coin from someone, that they said ended up heads more often than tails, how would you test.
Extension: How could researchers use a more powerful measure of analysis? Why do you think that researchers do not just rely on descriptive statistics.
Statistics 19 Confidence Intervals for Proportions.
The Law of Averages. What does the law of average say? We know that, from the definition of probability, in the long run the frequency of some event will.
Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc LEARNING GOAL Interpret and carry out hypothesis tests for independence of variables with data organized.
Statistics 200 Lecture #12 Thursday, September 29, 2016
Multiple choice questions
PROBABILITY RULES. PROBABILITY RULES CHANCE IS ALL AROUND YOU…. YOU AND YOUR FRIEND PLAY ROCK-PAPER-SCISSORS TO DETERMINE WHO GETS THE LAST SLICE.
Probability True or False? Answers.
Statistics and Probability-Part 5
Presentation transcript:

Cognitive Biases 3

HW2 Problem #1 Here are two sequences of coin-flips. X is one side of the coin, O is the other. XXO, for example, means that the coin landed on side X, then side X again, then side O. 1. XXOXXXOXOXOOOXXOOXOO 2. XOXXOXOXOOXXOXOOXOXO Which of the two was generated randomly by me flipping a coin, and which is a non-random sequence that I made up? Make sure to tell me how you know the answer.

HW2 Problem #1 Remember that if the sequence is truly random (how the coin lands the second time is independent of how it lands the first time), then the number of times where it lands the same as it did before should be about equal to the number of times where it lands different to what it landed before.

HW2 Problem #1 Let’s color-code “landing the same as the previous toss as blue, and landing different as red. Then sequence #1 is: XXOXXXOXOXOOOXXOOXOO Here we have 8 same tosses and 11 different ones.

HW2 Problem #1 For the second sequence we have: XOXXOXOXOOXXOXOOXOXO This is very different. Here there are only four same tosses and 15 different ones.

HW2 Problem #1 I made up the second sequence. Because I wanted it to look random, I tended to put X’s after O’s and O’s after X’s. This made most of the tosses turn out different– but that’s not what we should expect to happen.

HW2 Problem #2 If I flip a fair coin and ten times in a row it lands heads, which of the following should I most likely expect for the next ten flips? Circle one: A. It will “regress to the mean” and land tails more than heads to balance things out. B. Since it’s a fair coin, it is most likely to land heads half the times and tails the other half.

HW2 Problem #2 The correct answer is B: B. Since it’s a fair coin, it is most likely to land heads half the times and tails the other half. Future tosses of a coin are independent of past ones. Fair coins land, on average, 50% heads and 50% tails.

HW2 Problem #2 Answer A is a trick answer, for several reasons: A. It will “regress to the mean” and land tails more than heads to balance things out.

HW2 Problem #2 Regression to the mean happens when we have two imperfectly correlated variables X and Y, and X takes on a very extreme value. Then we expect Y to take on a less extreme value. But coin flips are not imperfectly correlated. They are not correlated at all. Past coin flips do not influence future coin flips.

HW2 Problem #2 Answer A also contains a misunderstanding about regression. It suggests that if the variable “past coin flips” takes on one extreme value (“lots of heads”) we should expect “future coin flips” to take on an extreme value in the opposite direction (“lots of tails”).

HW2 Problem #2 But this is not how regression works. Even if past and future coin flips are correlated, what we expect is that extreme values of one variable are paired with more average, normal, or “mean” values of the other variable. It’s regression to the mean, not regression to the opposite extreme!

HW2 Problem #3 Suppose that the government conducts a survey of traffic intersections to find out which had the most accidents in the past month. At every intersection where there was a large number of accidents, the government installs cameras. Next month they do a survey again and notice than on average there are fewer accidents at the locations where cameras are installed.

HW2 Problem #3 The government claims: Claim: Installing the cameras reduced the number of accidents. Suppose that this claim is false. Which cognitive bias/ fallacy (that we learned about in class) might be responsible for the government falsely believing the claim, in light of the evidence they have about the reduced number of accidents?

HW2 Problem #3 The answer I am looking for is the regression fallacy. The variables “traffic accidents this month” and “traffic accidents next month” are imperfectly correlated. Intersections with lots of accidents this month will likely have lots next month; intersections with few this month will likely have few next month.

HW2 Problem #3 If you have two imperfectly correlated variables, and one of them (“traffic accidents this month”) takes on an extreme value, the other will have a more moderate value. So the intersections that were the worst this month will be, on average, bad-but-less-bad next month. The will, on average, improve– simply through regression to the mean.

HW2 Problem #3 The regression fallacy is attributing a cause (the cameras the government installed) to an effect (the decrease in accidents at the intersections that had the most accidents last month) that is really just regression to the mean.

HW2 Problem #3 None of this means the cameras didn’t work! To truly test whether cameras work, you must install them at a random sampling of intersections– good and bad ones. If accidents then go down on average, you can be confident the cameras worked. We’ll talk more about random samples later in the course.

HW2 Problem #4 Suppose that I present you with four cards. On each card there is a number on one side and a letter on the other. I claim: Claim: If a card has a vowel on one side then it has an even number on the other side. Which of the four cards do you need to turn over to tell whether this claim is true?

HW2 Problem #4 Card #1: 6 Card #2: 7 Card #3: E Card #4: F

HW2 Problem #4 Card #1, 6, doesn’t matter. If you turn it over and it has a vowel, then the claim could be true. But it could also be false– maybe some other card has a vowel and an odd number on it. If you turn it over and it does not have a vowel, then the claim again can be either true or false. Card #1 gives you no information.

HW2 Problem #4 Card #4, F, also gives you no information. The claim is about what cards with vowels on one side have on the other side. F is not a vowel, so the claim is not about cards with F’s on one side.

HW2 Problem #4 Card #2, 7, is important. 7 is an odd number. If there is a vowel on the other side of card #2, then the claim is false, because #2 is a card with a vowel on one side but no even number on the other side. You must turn over #2 and make sure there is not a vowel on the other side.

HW2 Problem #4 Card #3, E, is also important. E is a vowel. If the claim is true, this card must have an even number on the other side. If it has an odd number on the other side, then the claim is false. You must turn over #3 and make sure there is not an odd number on the other side.

HW2 Problem #5 Consider the following contingency table. I claim that I can predict which students will get an A in my course (Prediction = Yes = student will get an A) and which will not get an A (Prediction = No = student will not get an A).

HW2 Problem #5 Observation = YesObservation = No Prediction = Yes3712 Prediction = No5224

HW2 Problem #5 So I got 37 out of 49 ( ) of my “yes” predictions correct, for a rate of 75.5%. Additionally, I got 24 out of 76 ( ) of my “no” predictions correct, for a rate of 31.6% Altogether, I got 61 out of 125 guesses correct, for a total of 48.8%.

HW2 Problem #5 Am I good predictor of which students will get an A or not? This is a hard question. Notice that I don’t do all that much better on guessing who gets an A than if I predicted that everyone would get an A. Then the chart would look like this:

89/125 = 71.2% Observation = YesObservation = No Prediction = Yes8936 Prediction = No00

HW2 Problem #5 I’ll accept any answer for this question, if you gave me some reasons for your answer, and those reasons aren’t crazy.

SEEING WHAT WE EXPECT TO SEE

Bias Our expectations often influence how we evaluate claims and evidence. We easily accept as true those things that we expect to be true, but are much more skeptical about things that are unexpected.

Bias Bias can be a good thing. If someone tells you they saw a construction worker, it makes sense to believe them– construction workers are numerous, and we expect there to be numerous sightings of them. But if someone tells you they saw an extraterrestrial, things are different. You’ll be right to be skeptical: that is very unexpected.

Bias Bias can also be a bad thing. If you’re biased against black people (“blacks tend toward criminal behavior,” you think), then you might be more likely to accept a negative statement about someone who is black, and more skeptical of believing positive things about them– even if they’re totally innocent, wonderful human beings.

Loftus & Palmer 1974 How things are described to us can affect how we see them. In one study, subjects were shown pictures of a car accident involving multiple cars. They were asked: “About how fast were the cars going when they (hit/smashed/collided/bumped/contacted ) each other?”

Loftus & Palmer 1974

Additionally, the subjects were asked one week later whether they remembered seeing broken glass (from the cars) in the photographs. There was no glass, but subjects who had been asked “smash” or “collided” questions were more likely to remember some than subjects asked “contacted” or “hit” questions.

Context Affects Expectation This study shows that context (how a picture is described to us) can affect how we see a thing (the picture itself), and what we remember about it.

Studies have shown that people in many cultures have negative associations with the color black. They are biased against black- colored things.

Frank & Gilovich 1988 One study asked professional referees (for American football) to watch a video clip of a play and decide whether the players deserved a penalty. In one version of the clip, the players wore white; in another, their uniforms were changed to black.

Frank & Gilovich 1988 The referees were more likely to say that the players deserved a penalty if they were wearing black. Frank & Gilovich also found that teams with black uniforms actually did get penalized more often than teams with other colored uniforms!

Disconfirmation Bias Our biases can lead us to accept evidence that agrees with our views and reject evidence against our views, even when the “for” and “against” evidence is of the same quality.

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 One study looked at how people who were in favor of the death penalty evaluated arguments for and against it, and how people who were against the death penalty evaluated those same arguments. There were four types of arguments:

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 AGAINST-SAME. A study that showed that murder rates in a state increased after that state instituted the death penalty. AGAINST-DIFF. A study that showed that murder rates were higher in states that had the death penalty than in states that didn’t.

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 FOR-SAME. A study that showed that murder rates in a state decreased after that state instituted the death penalty. FOR-DIFF. A study that showed that murder rates were lower in states that had the death penalty than in states that didn’t.

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 All the subjects got one study AGAINST the death penalty and one study FOR it. If the study they got AGAINST it was the SAME condition, then they got FOR-DIFF; if the study they got AGAINST it was DIFF, then they got FOR-SAME.

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 People who liked the death penalty and received AGAINST-SAME and FOR-DIFF argued that SAME studies were bad, and DIFF ones were good. They liked the study that supported them. If they got AGAINST-DIFF and FOR-SAME, they argued the opposite: that DIFF studies were bad, and that SAME studies were good.

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 The same was true for people who opposed the death penalty: they liked SAME studies when they got AGAINST-SAME, but not when they got FOR-SAME; they liked DIFF studies when they got AGAINST-DIFF, but not when they got FOR- DIFF. Everyone liked the studies that agreed with them!

Lord, Ross & Lepper 1979 What’s interesting is that the arguments given by the subjects about why DIFF studies are bad (or why SAME studies are bad) were good arguments. No one was arguing in bad faith. But their biases made them see the flaws in studies that disagreed with them, and made them ignore the flaws in the studies that agreed with them.

Disconfirmation Bias This is sometimes called disconfirmation bias. It is the tendency to subject evidence against your views to a greater degree of scrutiny than evidence in favor of your views. It is a double-standard for evidence evaluation.

Gamblers A similar study was seen in a study of gamblers (in particular, ones who bet on sports matches). Why do gamblers keep gambling when they lose money so often? Don’t they ever learn from their mistakes? Are they just forgetting about all those times they lost?

Gamblers The study showed that gamblers didn’t forget their losses– they were more likely to remember them. What they did was explain away the times they lost. Losses were counted as accidents, bad luck, “near wins”, etc. They weren’t counted as bad gambles or mistakes.

Gamblers Wins however were never attributed to accident or luck. They were the result of skill. So wins and losses were treated differently. A win was taken as evidence that the gambler was good at choosing bets. But losses were not taken as evidence that the gambler was bad at choosing bets, just that he was “unlucky”.

Multiple Endpoints One way that our expectations can influence our beliefs is called “the problem of multiple endpoints.”

Multiple Endpoints For example, suppose someone claims that spending time on Facebook is bad for your social life. Well what does that mean? There are lots of effects of Facebook that might be counted as bad for your social life (spending less time face- to-face with friends) and lots of ways that might be counted as good (talking more often with a larger range of friends).

Multiple Endpoints Here, if I’m biased because I dislike Facebook, I can interpret “bad for your social life” in a way that Facebook is bad; if I like Facebook, I can interpret it in a way that is good. There are multiple different events (“endpoints”) that I can focus on when evaluating the claim.

Multiple Endpoints People often say to parents, “your child looks so much like you!” even if (unknown to them) the child is adopted. There are lots of ways that any two people can look alike (hair, eyes, mouth, nose…). Most people will be similar in some ways. If you expect that two people will look similar (you think they’re biologically related), you will focus on those “endpoints”.

Two-Sided Events Some events are “one-sided” and some events are “two-sided”. A “two-sided” event is an event that can turn out one of two ways. For example, if I bet on a football match, I can either win or I can lose. Winning is one “side” of the event and losing is the other “side”.

One-Sided Events “One-sided” events are different. They can either (i) turn out in exactly one way or (ii) not exist.

One-Sided Events For example, suppose I believe that the phone always rings when I’m in the shower. If I’m in the shower and the phone rings, that seems like an event– something happened: I was in the shower, and the phone rang.

One-Sided Events For example, suppose I believe that the phone always rings when I’m in the shower. But if I’m in the shower and the phone doesn’t ring, it seems like nothing happened. I don’t say “look what happened when I was in the shower– the phone didn’t ring!”

Two-Sided Events & Memory For two-sided events, we notice both outcomes equally. So when evaluating claims about them, like “I always win when I bet on a match,” we will be confronted with the negative evidence (all those times I bet on a match and lost).

For one-sided events, we only notice when they happen, not when they don’t happen. So it may seem to me that my phone rings frequently when I’m in the shower, because I never notice the many, many times it does not ring when I’m in the shower.

Confirmations and Non-confirmations Sometimes events are “one-sided” because we are never inclined to notice the other side. Only when the event confirms a certain belief do we notice its relevance to the belief; if it doesn’t confirm the belief, then we’re uninclined to notice its relevance.

Confirmations and Non-confirmations Suppose a fortune teller predicts that I will have twins. If many years later, I have twins, I may remember the prediction. I have evidence that fortune tellers are accurate. If instead I have only one child, I’m less likely to remember the prophecy. One child doesn’t remind me of a prophecy about two children.

Open-Ended Claims Sometimes events are “one-sided” because the claims they are relevant to are open-ended. For example, suppose I predict that you will someday break a bone. If you break a bone tomorrow, next week, next month, next year, 30 years from now, etc. then the relevant event happened. I was right.

But if you don’t break a bone tomorrow, nothing happened. If you don’t break it next week, nothing happened. If you don’t break it next month, nothing happened. None of this shows that I’m wrong. Only if you died without breaking a bone would I be wrong. And you wouldn’t be around to notice that.