From risk to opportunity Lecture 10 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Introduction à la théorie de la décision
Advertisements

Copyright © 2008 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin Managerial Economics, 9e Managerial Economics Thomas Maurice.
Choices Involving Risk
Economics of Information (ECON3016)
From risk to opportunity Lecture 11 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.
From risk to opportunity Lecture 12 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.
Chapter 7 Hypothesis Testing
Utility theory U: O-> R (utility maps from outcomes to a real number) represents preferences over outcomes ~ means indifference We need a way to talk about.
Choice under Uncertainty. Introduction Many choices made by consumers take place under conditions of uncertainty Therefore involves an element of risk.
Risk Aversion and Capital Allocation to Risky Assets
Paradoxes in Decision Making With a Solution. Lottery 1 $3000 S1 $4000 $0 80% 20% R1 80%20%
JOHN HEY THE CHALLENGES OF EXPERIMENTALLY INVESTIGATING DYNAMIC ECONOMIC BEHAVIOUR DEMADYN’15, Heidelberg, 2 nd – 4 th March 2015.
Utility Theory.
States of the World In this section we introduce the notion that in the future the outcome in the world is not certain. Plus we introduce some related.
Decisions under Uncertainty
Social Choice Session 6 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
PROPERTIES OF UTILITY  One way to begin an analysis of individuals choices that we say are characterized in a utility function is to state a basic set.
Choices Involving Risk
Decision Theory Lecture 8. 1/3 1 1/4 3/8 1/4 3/8 A A B C A B C 1/2 A B A C Reduction of compound lotteries 1/2 1/4 A B C.
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2011 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2013 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 8 1.
1 st lecture Probabilities and Prospect Theory. Probabilities In a text over 10 standard novel-pages, how many 7-letter words are of the form: 1._ _ _.
Utility Axioms Axiom: something obvious, cannot be proven Utility axioms (rules for clear thinking)
CHAPTER 14 Utility Axioms Paradoxes & Implications.
1 Utility Theory. 2 Option 1: bet that pays $5,000,000 if a coin flipped comes up tails you get $0 if the coin comes up heads. Option 2: get $2,000,000.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior
1 CHAPTER 3 Certainty Equivalents from Utility Theory.
Notes – Theory of Choice
Decision Trees and Utility Theory
September 5, 2009Section 3 Midterm Review1 Section 3: Midterm Review EWMBA 201A Eva Vivalt.
VNM utility and Risk Aversion  The desire of investors to avoid risk, that is variations in the value of their portfolio of holdings or to smooth their.
LECTURE 2 : UTILITY AND RISK AVERSION (Asset Pricing and Portfolio Theory)
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Probability, Utility, and Game Theory Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Investment Analysis and Portfolio Management
Frank Cowell : Risk RISK MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Consumption and Uncertainty Almost essential Consumption.
Copyright © 2005 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin Managerial Economics Thomas Maurice eighth edition Chapter 15.
Expected Utility Theory
STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE APPROACH TO PORTFOLIO OPTIMIZATION Nesrin Alptekin Anadolu University, TURKEY.
1 The Shape of Incomplete Preferences Robert Nau Duke University Presented at ISIPTA ‘03.
Markets, Firms and Consumers Lecture 4- Capital and the Firm.
A Heuristic Solution To The Allais Paradox And Its Implications Seán Muller, University of Cape Town.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Chapters 23, 24 and 25 CHOICE UNDER RISK Chapter 23: The Budget Constraint. Chapter 24: The Expected Utility Model. Chapter.
John Hey LUISS, Italy and University of York, UK Gianna Lotito, University of Piemonte Orientale IAREP/SABE 2008 World Meeting at LUISS in Rome Naïve,
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Ellsberg’s paradoxes: Problems for rank- dependent utility explanations Cherng-Horng Lan & Nigel Harvey Department of Psychology University College London.
Lecture 3 on Individual Optimization Uncertainty Up until now we have been treating bidders as expected wealth maximizers, and in that way treating their.
Decision theory under uncertainty
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
Axiomatic Theory of Probabilistic Decision Making under Risk Pavlo R. Blavatskyy University of Zurich April 21st, 2007.
Expected Value, Expected Utility & the Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes
Allais Paradox, Ellsberg Paradox, and the Common Consequence Principle Then: Introduction to Prospect Theory Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making.
Microeconomics Course E John Hey. Chapter 26 Because we are all enjoying risk so much, I have decided not to cover Chapter 26 (on the labour market)
Nash Bargaining Solution and Alternating Offer Games MIT Game Theory.
Money and Banking Lecture 11. Review of the Previous Lecture Application of Present Value Concept Internal Rate of Return Bond Pricing Real Vs Nominal.
Statistics for Business and Economics Module 1:Probability Theory and Statistical Inference Spring 2010 Lecture 4: Estimating parameters with confidence.
DADSS Lecture 11: Decision Analysis with Utility Elicitation and Use.
Von Neumann-Morgenstern Lecture II. Utility and different views of risk Knightian – Frank Knight Risk – known probabilities of events Uncertainty – unknown.
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
CHAPTER 1 FOUNDATIONS OF FINANCE I: EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY
Decisions under risk Sri Hermawati.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey.
Risk Chapter 11.
Choices Involving Risk
Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty
Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Presentation transcript:

From risk to opportunity Lecture 10 John Hey and Carmen Pasca

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Overview First we have some definitions. Then we look at static problems under risk. We generalise briefly to dynamic problems and those under ambiguity (where probabilities do not exist). We discuss the axioms underlying (S)EUT. We discuss some of the implications. We briefly mention the circumstances under which (S)EUT reduces to Mean/Variance theory – which is much used in Finance.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Expected Values Suppose some variable X is risky and takes possible values x 1, …, x N with associated probabilities p 1, …, p N, where, of course, p 1 + … +p N = 1, then the Expected Value of the variable X, denoted by EX, is given by EX = p 1 x 1 + … +p N x N It can be interpreted as the average value of X in many repetitions, or the value we expect X to take on average. Also the Expected Value of some function f(.) of the variable X, denoted by Ef(X), is given by Ef(X) = p 1 f(x 1 )+ … +p N f(x N )

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Static & Risk We start by considering static (one-off) decision problems under risk. By static we mean that there is one decision, and that the outcome for the decision-maker depends upon the “state of the world”, which is risky in the sense that the possible states can be listed and probabilities attached to them. Suppose that there are N mutually exclusive states of the world, n = 1,…,N and suppose that state n has associated probability p n. (p 1 +…+p N = 1)

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Notation Let us denote a generic risky choice R by [X,Y;p,(1-p)] signifying a choice that leads to outcome X or Y with associated probabilities p and (1-p). Note that the DM gets either X or Y, not both. X and Y could themselves be risky choices, though the decision-maker only gets to ‘consume’ a certain outcome. EUT is an axiomatic theory. The individual is assumed to have preferences over all risky choices R. We use ≽ to indicate ‘preferred or indifferent to’, and ∼ to indicate ‘indifferent to’.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Axioms on preferences over lotteries (note that there are different possible sets of axioms) Completeness: for all R and S either R ≽ S or S ≽ R or both. Transitivity: if R ≽ S and S ≽ T then R ≽ T. Continuity: if R ≽ S ≽ T then ∃ p such that S ∼ [R,T;p,(1-p)]. Independence: if R ≽ S then, for all T, [R,T;p,(1-p)] ≽ [S,T;p,(1-p)] Existence of Best and Worst: There exist a best (B) and a worst (W) lottery. Monotonicity: [B,W;p,(1-p)] ≽ [B,W;q,(1-q)] if and only if p ≥ q If these hold then preferences are represented by u(R) = pu(X) +(1-p)u(Y) That is, by the Expected Utility of the lottery.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: The Key axiom (independence) R T 1-p Does the above appear reasonable/compelling? p is preferred to T 1-p S if and only if R is preferred to S… p … whatever T is represents a chance node

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: ‘Derivation of utility function’ Suppose that there are N possible outcomes x 1,…,x N. Suppose that, in the preferences of the decision-maker x 1 is the least preferred and x N the most. (using Best and Worst axiom) Let us put u(x 1 )=0 and u(x N )=1. Now consider any intermediate outcome x n. From continuity, since x N ≽ x n ≽ x 1 then ∃ u n such that x n ∼ [x N, x 1 ;u n,(1-u n )] Put u(x n )= u n (note u n is a probability but we interpret it as a utility.) xNxN x1x1 unun 1-u n x n ∼

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Why it is natural to put u(x n ) = u n The u n for which the individual is indifferent between x n and the gamble on the right is a probability. Why is it ‘natural’ to call it the utility of x n ? Because the individual says that he or she is indifferent between it and the gamble... and hence u(x n ) must be equal to the expected utility of the gamble; this is given by u n u(x N ) + (1-u n )u(x 1 ) which is equal to u n since u(x N ) = 1 and u(x 1 ) = 0. xNxN x1x1 unun 1-u n x n ∼

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: ‘Proof of EU result 1’ This can be re-expressed (replacing each intermediate outcome by a gamble between the best and the worst – using independence.) xNxN x1x1 pNpN p1p1 … xnxn … pnpn Consider the generic lottery: xNxN xNxN x1x1 pNpN p1p1 … … pnpn x1x1 unun 1-u n xNxN x1x1 p N u N +…+p n u n +…+p 1 u 1 1 minus the above expression or: Hence the generic lottery has value (see next slide) p N u N +…+p n u n +…+p 1 u 1 – its expected utility!

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: ‘Proof of EU result 2’ xNxN x1x1 1-p Just a footnote: it follows from monotonicity that: q P is preferred to x1x1 1-q Q xNxN if and only if p is greater than q… … and hence that p is an indicator of the value of a lottery involving just the best and the worst. p

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: the EU result xNxN x1x1 pNpN p1p1 … xnxn … pnpn Consider the generic lottery: We have shown that the generic lottery is equivalent (for our individual obeying the axioms) to a lottery between the best and the worst outcomes, in which the probability of getting the best outcome is p N u N +…+p n u n +…+p 1 u 1 that is, the Expected Utility of the lottery. It follows from monotonicity that the individual evaluates the generic lottery by its Expected Utility. Note that since we put u(x 1 )=0 and u(x N )=1 it follows that the utility representation is unique only up to a linear transformation (two points fixed – like temperature).

Problems? Remember the Common Ratio Effect? (1) Do you prefer (1A) €30 for sure, or (1B) a lottery which yields €40 with probability 0.8 and €0 with probability 0.2? (2) Do you prefer (2A) a lottery which yields €30 with probability 0.25 and €0 with probability 0.75, or (2B) a lottery which yields €40 with probability 0.2 and €0 with probability 0.8? A preference for 1A in problem 1 and for 2B in Problem 2 is a violation of Expected Utility.

Let us look at this using trees: Note: green squares are decision nodes and red squares are chance nodes. firstsecond €30 € €0€0 €0€ Now consider this €30 €40 £ A 1B €30 €50 €0€ €0€ A 2B Such an individual would plan to play Down but actually choose Up.

Now recall the Original Allais Paradox (using the notation of Machina) Problem 1: Choose between (a1) 1 million for sure and (a2) a lottery which gives 5 million with probability 0.1, 1 million with probability 0.89 and 0 with probability Problem 2: Choose between (a4) a lottery which gives 1 million with probability 0.11 and 0 with probability 0.89 and (a3) a lottery which gives 5 million with probability 0.1 and 0 with probability 0.9. Choosing a1 in Problem 1 and a3 in Problem 2 is a violation of EU.

Lecture 10: Expected Utility theory This is closely related to Machina’s arguments for dynamic consistency with EU preferences (taken from Machina JEL 1989). Here squares denote choice nodes and circles chance nodes. To be consistent with EU if you prefer a 1 to a 2 you should prefer a 4 to a 3 since u(1) >.1u(5) +.89u(1) +.01u(0) if and only if.11u(1)+.89u(0)>.1u(5) +.9u(0) Now note that as viewed from the start these are the same as the problems above. But if you get to the square box, the choice problems are the same as each other! Which reinforces the idea that if you prefer a 1 to a 2 you should prefer a 4 to a 3. Someone who does not can be dynamically inconsistent.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Risk Attitude If someone has a linear utility function u(x) = x then they are risk-neutral since the maximisation of Expected Utility is the same as maximisation of Expected Value. If someone has a concave utility function u’’(x)<0 then they are risk-averse; the more concave the more risk-averse. If someone has a convex utility function u’’(x)>0 then they are risk-loving; the more convex the more risk-loving.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Certainty Equivalents We define the Certainty Equivalent of a gamble for some individual by CE given by U(CE) = EU(X) so the individual is indifferent between the Certainty Equivalent and the gamble. For a risk-neutral person CE = EX For a risk-averse person CE < EX For a risk-loving person CE > EX. Are risk-lovers mad?

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Measuring Risk Attitude The concavity of the utility function tells us the risk- aversion; the more concave the more risk-averse. One measure is the Absolute Risk Attitude (ARA) -u’’(x)/u’(x) Another is the Relative Risk Attitude (RRA) -xu’’(x)/u’(x) CARA utility function: u(x) = - e -rx ARA = r always. CRRA utility function: u(x) = x 1-r RRA = r always.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: CE in a particular case Suppose an individual has a CARA utility function u(x) = - e -rx and that X is normally distributed with mean μ and variance σ 2 then the CE is given by U(CE) = E[- e -rx ] Using the properties of moment generating functions we can show that this implies -e -CE = - exp(-rμ + r 2 σ 2 /2) and hence CE = μ – r σ 2 /2 Which is a rather nice result.

Lecture 10 Subjective Expected Utility Theory Now suppose that states of the world 1,…,N but not their probabilities exist. Suppose the decision-maker receives x n if state n occurs (n=1,..,N). Savage showed in 1954 that, if a decision-makers preferences agreed with certain ‘reasonable’ axioms of behaviour, then the decision-maker would choose among lotteries as if he or she were maximising a function p 1 u(x 1 ) + … + p N u(x N ) where the p n and u(x n ) exist and are unique (n=1,..,N). The axioms can be found, for example, in Leonard Savage’sThe Foundations of Statistics, This is an absolutely breathtaking result!!

Lecture 10 Subjective Expected Utility Theory Axioms For those who are interested: 1.the preference relation is transitive and all acts are comparable. 2.the preference between acts depend solely on the consequences in states in which the payoffs of the two acts being compared are distinct. 3.the ordinal ranking of consequences is independent of the event and the act that yields them. 4.the betting preferences are independent of the specific consequences that define the bets. 5.it is not the case that the decision maker is indifferent among all acts. 6.no consequence is either infinitely better or infinitely worse than any other consequence. 7.if the decision maker considers an act strictly better (worse) than each of the payoffs of another act on a given non-null event, then the former act is conditionally strictly preferred (less preferred) than the latter. Taken from Edi Karni’s Savages’ Subjective Expected Utility Model, 2005.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Dynamics We do not have the time to study this in depth, but one immensely satisfying property of EU preferences is that someone with such preferences is necessarily dynamically consistent in dynamic decision problems. What do we mean by this? That they do not want to change their minds part way through a dynamic decision problem. Or, whichever way they analyse a dynamic decision problem they come up with the same solution. In contrast a non-EU person could be dynamically inconsistent.

Two Problems: what would you choose – Up or Down – in each? Consider a person who does not violate EU, choosing Up in both problems (you could also examine the implications of Down in both). Note: green squares are decision nodes and red squares are chance nodes. £30 £50 £ first second £30 £50 £ £

What does such a person do in this dynamic problem? Suppose that he/she prefers £30 to the 80% chance of £50 and that he/she strictly prefers the 25% chance of £30 to the 20% chance of £50. Plays Down – irrespective of the way that he/she looks at the problem. Note: green squares are decision nodes and red squares are chance nodes.

Suppose that he/she prefers £30 to the 80% chance of £50 and that he/she strictly prefers the 25% chance of £30 to the 20% chance of £50. Plays Down – irrespective of the way that he/she looks at the problem. Let us look at the strategy method (rather than backward induction) There are three possible strategies: Up-Up; Up- Down; Down. Up-Up leads to £50 with probability 0.2 and £0 with probability 0.8. Up-Down leads to £30 with probability 0.25 and £0 with probability Down leads to £31 with probability 0.25 and £1 with probability With these preferences Down is best – the same as found by backward induction.

Now consider a non-EU person Consider a person who violates EU, choosing Up in the first problem and and Down in the second. Note: green squares are decision nodes and red squares are chance nodes. £30 £50 £ first second £30 £50 £ £

What does such a person do in this dynamic problem? Suppose that he/she prefers £30 to the 80% chance of £50 and that he/she strictly prefers the 20% chance of £50 to the 25% chance of £30. Note: green squares are decision nodes and red squares are chance nodes.

What does such a person do in this dynamic problem? Suppose that he/she prefers £30 to the 80% chance of £50 and that he/she strictly prefers the 20% chance of £50 to the 25% chance of £30. Now look at the strategy method (rather than backward induction) There are three possible strategies: Up-Up; Up-Down; Down. Up-Up leads to £50 with probability 0.2 and £0 with probability 0.8. Up-Down leads to £30 with probability 0.25 and £0 with probability Down leads to £31 with probability 0.25 and £1 with probability With these preferences Up-Up initially appears to be the best (though Down at the second node, if reached, looks tempting).

What they do depends on their type Resolute: Choose Up at the first and Up at the second (even though they want to choose Down when they get there). Naive: Choose Up at the first and Down at the second. Sophisticated: Choose Down at the first (because they anticipate moving Down at the second if they choose Up at the first). The latter is what is assumed when backward induction is used.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory=Mean/Variance? In finance, preferences are often assumed to be mean/variance; the higher (lower) the former (latter) the better. This could arise from a quadratic utility function or from normally distributed outcomes. But a quadratic utility function is rather odd (utility decreasing with wealth). And normal distributions have tails going to both plus and minus infinity.

Lecture 10 Expected Utility Theory: Conclusion (Subjective) Expected Utility Theory is based on very plausible and reasonable axioms. It leads to a very elegant solution for problems under risk. It leads to an even more elegant solution for problems under ambiguity/uncertainty. In dynamic problems it avoids the difficulty of dynamically inconsistent preferences. So it is normatively very strong. But positively?

Lecture 10 Goodbye!