Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 5-6 26-7/9/2007 Text: Critique of the Aesthtical Power of Judgment (6-9)

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 5-6 26-7/9/2007 Text: Critique of the Aesthtical Power of Judgment (6-9)"— Presentation transcript:

1 Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 5-6 26-7/9/2007 Text: Critique of the Aesthtical Power of Judgment (6-9) Claus Beisbart The analysis of the Beautiful (II) References third Critique: Guyer/Matthews

2 The second moment Table of Judgment (Critique of Pure Reason) I. Quantity of Judgments Universal Particular Singular

3 Universality in which sense? 1. Universality of form (or logical quantity, in Kant's terms, 100): For all x: x has property P. This is not the universality that Kant has in mind. He even says that every judgment of taste is singular (100). Why does he say so?

4 Logical universality Kant's picture: you have to check whether a particular thing actually gives you pleasure. It doesn't make sense to check a class of things. You can check them one after the other, and then summarize your experience. But this summarizing doesn't interest Kant any more. He is interested in your experience, and thus, for him, a judgment of taste is only about particular objects – is singular only.

5 A variety of logical universality? Cf. Richard M. Hare: Moral judgments are universalizable Whenever you say that some particular action is morally right, then you are committed to a general principle that entails that this particular action is right. Idea: Moral judgments are often singular, but there is always a moral principle in the backing. This is again not what Kant wants to say, as we shall see.

6 Another kind of universality Kant: “That is beautiful which pleases universally without a concept.” (104) Idea: A certain presupposition is associated with judgments of taste, and the presupposition says that everybody would react to beautiful things in some specific way. Let us first briefly talk about presuppositions.

7 Mackie's distinction Given: Judgments or a domain of discourse Conceptual question: What is presupposed in these judgments? Substantive question: Are the presuppositions true? (or, maybe, are we justified in presupposing what we presuppose?) Conceptual and substantive questions are in principle independent.

8 An example Domain of discourse: physicists in the lab talk about atoms. Conceptual claim: They assume that there are tiny balls called atoms and that one can know about these atoms. Substantive thesis: There are (no) atoms; we can (not) know about atoms (as they are unobservable). (Scientific realism debate)

9 Agenda 1. What exactly is presupposed in judgments of taste according to Kant? (What is Kant's conceptual claim?) 2. How does Kant argue for his conceptual claim? 3. Is Kant's conceptual thesis true? 4. Is the thing that Kant thinks we presuppose in judgments of taste true?

10 What is Kant's conceptual claim? Suggestions for the presupposition of the judgment that X is beautiful: 1. Every person who knows X can understand that I take pleasure in X. 2. Every person who is in appropriate contact with X would judge X beautiful, particularly, he would take pleasure from X.

11 Suggestion 2 put into perspective 2 has a similarity with presuppositions connected to other judgments “All ravens are black.” Presupposition: “Every person that commands appropriate cognitive capacities and that is in appropriate contact with ravens would also judge that all ravens are black.”

12 NB on suggestion 2 Suggestion 2 can be weakened by requiring more conditions: Every person who is in appropriate contact with X and who is well educated and who takes the appropriate stance... would judge X beautiful, particularly, he would take pleasure from X. Still, the idea is that the pleasure is shared among everybody who fulfills certain conditions.

13 Kant himself “The beautiful is that which, without concepts, is repre- sented as the object of a universal satisfaction.“ (par. 6, p. 96) “Similarly, he must believe himself to have grounds for expecting a similar pleasure for everyone.” (par. 6, p. 97) So suggestion 2 has direct textual support. In the following, we are taking suggestion 2 for granted.

14 Kant's conceptual thesis Whenever I judge some object X beautiful, I presuppose that everybody who is in appropriate contact with X (and maybe fulfills some other conditions), judges X beautiful as well. Call this the presupposition of intersubjective validity

15 Kant's arguments for the conceptual claim par. 6: idea: it follows from the disinterested character of the pleasure we take in the beautiful. If I judge something beautiful, then I take pleasure in it independently from my interests. So I think that no personal matters enter this judgment. So I think that the grounds for my judgment are impersonal. So I think that everybody would join me in my judgment.

16 Criticisms (1) 1. Although I'm not aware of any interests, I might be aware of other personal factors (emotions, maybe) such that I wouldn't think the grounds for the judgment are impersonal. I wouldn't then expect universal validity for my judgment. Kant would probably answer, that judgments of taste are really about pleasure only, so the question can only be whether my pleasure is in a way personal. Kant then thinks that his distinction pleasure in the beautiful/good/agreeable is exhaustive. So there cannot be other personal matters that enter judgments about the beautiful.

17 Criticisms (2) 2. Even if I conceive of the grounds of my judgment as disinterested and impersonal, I need not conclude that everybody would join me in the pleasure. To be sure, such a conclusion would be justified given what I think, but it might be that I don't draw the conclusion. (Comment: very often we think something true, but we don't believe what follows from our beliefs. For instance, from what I believe about numbers, very difficult mathematical theorems follow. But I don't believe that these theorems are true – I haven't just thought about them) Kant might answer that the presupposition of intersubjective validity is such an obvious consequence of my conceptions of the grounds that I take the presupposition to be true as well.

18 More arguments hinted at in par. 7 (1) 1. The agreeable provides the paradigm for judgments without the presupposition of intersubjective validity. In this case, we talk differently. We say that something is agreeable for me. One cannot say that something is beautiful for me. So the paradigm doesn't work for judgments about the beautiful So judgments about the beautiful do carry the presupposition of intersubjective validity. thanks to Jane here for a useful clarification....

19 Criticism of this argument Criticism: We do say that something is beautiful for me. Or we say “It's beautiful, isn't it” and “I think it's beautiful” So we do somehow relativize to the speaker, and the agreeable is a model for the beautiful. Rejoinder: We do talk this way, but if we talk this way, we mean something else, for instance, we really talk about the agreeable or we want to say: “It might be beautiful, but I'm not sure” or “It is beautiful, but I wouldn't be able to prove it.”

20 More arguments hinted at in par. 7 (2) 2. the surface structures of sentences with which we express judgments of taste: “This rose is beautiful.” resembles “This rose is red.” The second sentence reflects a judgment for which intersubjective validity is assumed. So does the first one. (This argument would impress ordinary language philosophers)

21 More arguments hinted at in par. 7 (3) 3. If A judges X to be beautiful, and B disagrees, A would criticize B. That makes only sense, if A thinks that everybody would agree with him – at least under ideal circumstances.

22 More arguments hinted at in par. 7 (4) 4. Some persons have taste regarding the beautiful. This only makes sense, if some judgments of taste are better than others. So there is something to be got right here. At least the experts would converge in their judgments. Attention: people can also have more taste in that they know better what people find agreeable. But this is a matter of empirical research (par. 10, 98).

23 More arguments hinted at in par. 7 (5) 5. There is something like progress in matters of taste. First, I don't take pleasure in Mahler's music, say. Later somebody gives me a few hints, I study a bit on Mahler, and I find his music beautiful. The idea of progress implies that certain judgments of taste are better than others. Go on as in argument 4.

24 Criticism against 1 – 5 Criticism: These arguments are too soft or weak, they only talk about what people think. We would need an argument that is about the real world. Rejoinder: We are only talking about the conceptual question here. But the conceptual point is really about what people think. A real world story would be pointless at this point.

25 The fourth moment Kant elaborates on the presupposition in his fourth moment. main result: “That is beautiful which is cognized without a concept as the object of a necessary satisfaction.” (124) “Of every representation I can say that it is at least possible that it [...] be combined with a pleasure. Of that which I call agreeable I say that it actually produces pleasure in me. Of the beautiful, however, one thinks that it has a necessary relation to satisfaction.” (par. 18, 121)

26 The fourth moment (interpreted) Question: what exactly is the presupposition of “X is beautiful”? Suggestion: “For every person P: whenever she is in appropriate contact with X, she should judge it beautiful.” (cf. par 19) NB. “should” like obligation is a modal notion: If you should do something, then this in a way necessary, it is required that you act this way. But Kant doesn't have in mind moral obligations here. He emphasizes that the necessity is conditioned and weak.

27 The fourth moment (continued) Nevertheless, necessity, however weak, is a characteristic of a priori judgments. Kant: there is something a prioristic about judgments of taste. This came as a surprise to Kant himself, earlier he didn't think like this. Kant: a priori judgments are in need of justification: deduction.

28 The fourth moment (continued) Kant expresses the presupposition in yet different words: What is really presupposed is a common sense: “Thus only under the presupposition that there is a common sense [...] can the judgment of taste be made.” (par. 20, 122) Common sense: entirely about the feeling.

29 Kant's problem with the conceptual claim Kant himself finds the conceptual claim worrisome. par. 1: Judgments of taste are aesthetic. The representation is only related to the subject. Judgments of taste do not represent objective knowledge. So how can there be intersubjectivity without objectivity? This is already about the substantial question: Is the presupposition true? So the worry is: From a certain perspective, the presupposition seems implausible. But if this is so, then our ordinary talk about the beautiful might rest on a mistake.

30 A model for objectivity Kant: objectivity implies intersubjectivity a tree Alice Bob representation object via concepts the same judgment

31 The problem for aesthetic judgments a tree Alice Bob representation object no concepts the same judgment??? feeling of pleasure

32 The problem put differently When we judge something agreeable, it is about our feelings, and we don't presume intersubjective validity. When we judge something beautiful, it is about our feelings, and we do presume intersubjective validity. What grounds the difference? par 8, p. 99

33 The role of concepts In his summary of the second moment, Kant says that the “beautiful pleases universally without concept.” (my emphasis) For Kant, there is only objectivity, when concepts are applied. a. the categories of the understanding b. specific concepts. So the puzzle can also be put like this: How can there be intersubjective validity without concepts?

34 Beauty and concepts Kant claims that judgments of taste involve no concepts. What does this mean? Moment 1: For judging something beautiful, one need not to know what kind of thing that is. Moment 2: There are no rules for judging something beautiful (remember, that concepts are rules according to Kant) You cannot demonstrate to someone else that something is beautiful (cf. mathematical proofs) (par. 8, p. 101)

35 The substantive question Are we justified in presupposing universal validity of judgments of taste? This justification is probably the most important task that Kant sets himself. It reappears again and again. 1. Par. 21 2. The deduction (for Kant, deductions are always about justifications. Henrich: distinguish the questions: quid facti – what are the facts? quid juris – are the facts justifiably as they are?) 3. The dialectic (the antinomy of taste)

36 par. 9 (I) Official question: So far, we have two aspects of judgments of taste 1. pleasure 2. the presupposition Problem: What comes first? NB. “first” is probably not meant in a temporal sense, rather the question is: Which aspect grounds the other?

37 par. 9 (II) Model no. 1 pleasure → presupposition problem: pleasure alone gives no grounds for the presupposition. Model no. 2 presupposition → pleasure how can this be?

38 par. 9 (III) Kant's theory of the free play. We have, inter alia, the following cognitive capacities: imagination (task: “composition of the manifold of intuition”) understanding (task: unity by application of a concept) If we judge something beautiful, hey play without a definite result (which would be a cognition).

39 par. 9 (IV) How does Kant argue for the theory of the free play? Kant assumes that the presupposition is true. From this he derives the theory of the free play. The argument in nuce: The presupposition can only be true, if the understanding and the imagination engage in free play, whenever we judge something beautiful. Of course, the argument doesn't help, if the presupposition is false.

40 par. 9 (V) NB. Kant's methodology in the “Groundwork” is similar. In Section 2, he derives the content of the Categorical Imperative from the assumption that there is an imperative that commands categorically. In Section 3, he shows that there is such an imperative.

41 par. 9 (VI) NB. A problem in interpreting Kant: What is the “judging of the object” (“Beurteilung”, 102)? Interpretation here: it is to claim that the presupposition is true (note that taking the presupposition to be true is to say something about the object: this object would arouse pleasure in everybody)


Download ppt "Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 5-6 26-7/9/2007 Text: Critique of the Aesthtical Power of Judgment (6-9)"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google