Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Notes: Prospect Theory in the Wild Paper by Colin F. Camerer.

Similar presentations

Presentation on theme: "Notes: Prospect Theory in the Wild Paper by Colin F. Camerer."— Presentation transcript:

1 Notes: Prospect Theory in the Wild Paper by Colin F. Camerer

2 Review and finish up of Prospect Theory

3 The Man Himself Kahneman Nobel Lecture: 9:00-22:15 and 31:50-end Changes are salient and maintained states are mostly ignored. What does this mean? What does he mean when he says that framing outcomes in terms of wealth is psychologically unrealistic but normatively appropriate (19:30)? Why would indifference curves have kinks? What is the point of the colonoscopy experiment?

4 What does PT add? K and T introduce the value function. Carriers of value are changes in wealth or welfare, rather than final states. When we respond to attributes such as brightness, loudness, or temperature, the past and present context of experience defines an adaptation level, or reference point, and stimuli are perceived in relation to this reference point. Value should be treated as a function in two arguments: 1. The asset position that serves as a reference point 2. The magnitude of the change (positive or negative) from that reference point.

5 Property that the Value Function proposes: Many sensory and perceptual dimensions share the property that the psychological response is a concave function of the magnitude of physical change. Ex: Temperature change from 3 degrees to 6 degrees VERSUS a temperature change of 13 degrees to 16 degrees EX: value of a gain of 100 to 200 VERSUS a change of 1,100 to 1,200 Ex: value of a loss of 100 to 200 VERSUS a loss of 1,100 to 1,200

6 Concave and Convex The value function for changes in wealth: Concave above the reference point Convex below it And that the marginal value of both gains and losses generally decreases with their magnitude

7 The Value Function Gains Losses Value

8 Summary of the Value Function 1. it is defined on deviations from the reference point – that reference point may be: The status quo An individuals endowment 2. It is generally concave for gains and commonly convex for losses 3. It is steeper for losses than for gains (this is the idea of loss aversion)

9 Add: The Weighting Function In Prospect Theory, the value of each outcome is multiplied by a decision weight. Decision weights are inferred from choices between prospects much as subjective probabilities are inferred from preferences K and T propose that very low probabilities are generally over- weighted Because people are limited in their ability to comprehend and evaluate extreme probabilities, highly unlikely events are either ignored or overweighted, and the difference between high probability and certainty is either neglected or exaggerated The following is a hypothetical weighting function

10 The Probability Weighting Function Actual Probability Perceived Probability Weighting function

11 Misperceiving Probability


13 Ten Anomalies in Naturally- Occurring Data: Colin Camerer Anomalies for EUT but can be explained by three simple elements of prospect theory: Loss aversion Reflection effects Nonlinear weighting of probability Along with the assumption that people isolate decisions (or edit them) from others they may be grouped with

14 1. Finance: The Equity Premium Stocks or equities tend to have more variable annual price changes (or returns) than do bonds. Result: the average return to stocks is higher, as a way of compensating investors for the additional risk they bear. Avg: 8% higher per year return This was accepted a as a reasonable return premium for equities until Mehra and Prescott (1985) asked how large a degree of risk-aversion is implied by this premium?

15 Why is the equity premium strange? The assumption is that the equity premium is the excess return one would get from investing in a stock (a risky bet) versus a bond (a risk free bet). Imagine that the RoR on a three-month U.S. Treasury Bill (T Bill – the risk-free rate) is 0.17 percent. Imagine a RoR on a stock, say 3 percent. Subtracting the risk-free rate from the RoR on the risky investment should determine the equity risk premium. Heres the math for this example: 3% % = 2.83%

16 But stocks perform on average 8% better than bonds... So, now assuming Risky – Risk Free = 8 percent What kind of attitude toward risk does this imply? A person with enough risk-aversion to explain the equity premium would be indifferent between a coin flip paying either $50,000 or $100,000 and a sure amount of $51,329 (See The Equity Premium: A Puzzle by Rajnish Mehra and Edward C. Prescott, 1985)The Equity Premium: A Puzzle

17 Benartzi and Thaler (1997) Investors are not averse to the variability of returns, they are averse to a loss (the chance that their returns are negative). The high return is compensation for the much higher chance of losing money in a year To calculate, B&T assumed investors take a short horizon over which stocks are more likely to lose than bonds. Find the expected prospect values of stock and bond returns over various horizons using estimates of investor utility functions Include a loss-aversion coefficient of 2.25 (i.e. The disutility of a small loss is 2.25 times as large as the utility of an equal gain) Over a one-year horizon, the prospect values of stock and bond returns are about the same if stocks return 8% more than bonds

18 2. Finance: The disposition effect Investors tend to hold on to stocks that have lost value (relative to their purchase price) too long and will be eager to sell stocks that have risen in value. Anomalous because the purchase price of a stock should not matter much for whether you decide to sell it If you think it will rise, you should keep it. If you think it will fall, you should sell it.

19 Evidence from Odean Found investors held losing stocks a median of 124 days Held winners 104 days Losers returned 5% in the subsequent year Winners returned 11.6% in the subsequent year

20 Labor Supply Camerer, Babcock, Loewenstein and Thaler talked to cab drivers in NYC about when they decide to quit driving each day. Drivers lease cabs for a fixed fee for up to 12 hours. Many set an income target for the day and quit when they reach that target. Implication? Drivers work long hours on bad days when per- hour wage is low and quit earlier on good, high-wage days. Standard theory predicts the opposite.

21 4. Asymmetric price elasticities of consumer goods Price elasticity: percentage change in the quantity demanded divided by the percentage change in price Tons of studies estimate elasticities – effects of how much quantity demanded responds to own prices, cross prices etc. Elasticities of labor supply... Etc. If we take PT into consideration we can expect that loss aversion might affect elasticities: loss-averse consumers might dislike price increases more than they like the windfall gain from price cuts We might see larger elasticities after a price increase than a price decrease

22 Hardie, Johnson, and Fader (1993) on price elasticities Looked at the possibility that consumers compare a goods current price to some reference price (the price they last paid) Found that consumers get more disutility from buying when prices have risen than the extra utility they get when prices have fallen For OJ, estimate the coefficient of loss aversion to be 2.4

23 5. Savings and Consumption Economic models of lifetime savings and consumption: people have different utility functions over each period of life, and discount factors which weight future consumption less than current consumption. Implication: because workers expect to earn larger and larger incomes throughout their lives, people will spend more than they earn when they are young (perhaps borrowing) and then earn more than they spend when they are older. What people really do? They spend a fixed fraction of their current income, and it doesnt vary across the life cycle. Consumption drops steeply after retirement because people didnt save enough.

24 PT can help explain Bowman, Minehart and Rabin (1994) explain with a stylized tow-period consumption-savings model in which workers have reference-dependent utility. Bowman, Minehart and Rabin (1994) The utility they get from consumption in each period exhibits loss aversion and a reflection effect Our main conclusion is that, when there is sufficient income uncertainty, a person resists lowering consumption in response to bad news about future income, and this resistance is greater than the resistance to increase consumption in response to good news.

25 6. Status Quo Bias, Endowment Effects and buying-selling gaps Samuelson and Zeckhauser (1988) coined the term status quo bias to refer to an exaggerated preference for the status quo. Samuelson and Zeckhauser (1988) Example: Harvard U added new health-care plan options. Previously hired faculty members could switch to new options. Assume: old and new faculty members have same preferences for health care plans Implication: the distribution of plans elected by new and old faculty should be the same S and Z found that older faculty tended to stick to previous plans

26 Default Choices When there is no status quo, people may have an exaggerated preference for whichever option is the default choice. Johnson, Hershey, Meszaros and Kunreuther (1993) showed this in decisions involving insurance purchases. Johnson, Hershey, Meszaros and Kunreuther (1993) Pennsylvania and New Jersey passed similar forms of limited insurance policies but chose different default options. Penn: limited-rights insurance was the default NJ: unlimited-rights insurance was the default Result: people stuck with the default

27 Endowment Effect In Class Experiment

28 The Endowment Effect Buying and Selling Prices are often quite different. Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler (1990): some subjects are endowed (randomly) with coffee mugs and others are not. Those who are given the mugs demand a price about 2-3 times as large as the price that those without mugs are willing to pay But the prices should be extremely close together... Why?

29 More papers on the Endowment Effect for your Perusal Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch, Richard H. Thaler Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion and Status Quo Bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 5 (1): Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch, Richard H. Thaler Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion and Status Quo Bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 5 (1): Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch and Richard H. Thaler Experimental Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem. Journal of Political Economy. Vol. 98(6): Kahneman, Daniel, Jack L. Knetsch and Richard H. Thaler Experimental Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem. Journal of Political Economy. Vol. 98(6):

30 7. Racetrack Betting: The favorite-longshot bias In parimutuel betting on horse races, there is a pronounced bias toward betting on longshots, horses with a relatively small chance of winning. Horses with 2% of the total money bet on them win only about 1% of the time. Implication is that favorites are underbet. The problem is that the return for a dollar bet is low on favorites and people dislike those types of bets.

31 Explanations for favorite- longshot bias Gamblers fallacy: longshots are due Overweighting of low probabilities of winning Losing on a heavy favorite is particularly dissapointing (as opposed to losing on a long-shot or winning on a long-shot)

32 The End-of-the-day effect McGlothlin (1956) and Ali (1977) a racetrack anomaly which points to the central role of reference points. Betters tend to shift their bets toward longshots later in the racing day. Because the track takes a big bite out of each dollar, most bettors are behind by the last race of the day. These bettors prefer longshots because a small longshot bet can generate a large enough profit to cover earlier losses, enabling them to break even. PT: assume people open a mental account a the beginning of the day, close it at the end, and hate closing an account in red.

33 9. State Lotteries Lotto: players choose six different numbers from a set of numbers. They win a jackpot if their six choice match six numbers which are randomly drawn in public. If no one wins, the jackpot is rolled over and added to the next weeks jackpot. Cook and Clotfelter (1993): people are more sensitive to the large jackpot than to the correspondingly low probability of winning Ticket sales are correlated with the size of a states population which is correlated with jackpot size PT explanatino: overweighting of and insensitivity to very low probabilities

34 Conclusion.... Is this stuff in our brain???

35 10 Ways we get it wrong 1. we fear snakes, not cars 2. We fear spectacular, unlikely events 3. We fear cancer but not heart disease 4. No pesticide in my backyardunless I put it there (i.e. Risks are okay if I can control them) 5. We speed up when we put our seat belts on 6. Teens may think to much about riskand not feel enough (sometimes rational thought leads us into bad actions) 7. Why young men will never get good rates on car insurance 8. We worry about teen pot but not about teen sports 9. We love sunlight but fear nuclear power 10. We should fear fear itself

Download ppt "Notes: Prospect Theory in the Wild Paper by Colin F. Camerer."

Similar presentations

Ads by Google