Immanuel Kant and the moral law. Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project,

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
What is deontology?.
Advertisements

Morality As Overcoming Self-Interest
Frameworks for Moral Arguments
The Categorical Imperative
Kant Are there absolute moral laws that we have to follow regardless of consequences? First we want to know what Kant has to say about what moral rule.
Moral law and Kant’s imperatives.
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
Categorical Imperative
Kantian Ethics (Duty and Reason)
Immanuel Kant The Good Will and Autonomy. Context for Kant Groundwork for Metaphysics of Morals after American Revolution and Before French- rights.
Deontology: the Ethics of Duty
Ethical Theory.
Phil 160 Kant.
Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Hassan Ismail.
Deontological Ethics Deontological theory—Asserts that the rightness of actions is determined partly or entirely by their intrinsic value Consequentialist.
How Actions Can Be Morally Evaluated l Teleological Ethics: morality is the means to achieve what is identified as good or valuable l Deontological Ethics:
How Actions Can Be Morally Evaluated l Teleological Ethics: morality is the means to achieve what is identified as good or valuable l Deontological Ethics:
Kantian Ethics Exam Questions
Kant’s deontological ethics
Consequentialism, Natural Law Theory, Kantian Moral Theory
Ethics and Ethical Theories
Kant’s Ethics of Duty 3 insights form the basis for his theory  An action has moral worth if it is done for the sake of duty. (DUTY)  An action is morally.
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
What is the right thing to do?
Deontological Ethics Is saving someone from drowning a morally praiseworthy act? Do motives play any role in whether an act is morally praiseworthy?
THEORIES OF ETHICS PART 2 OF CHAPTER 12 (ETHICS).
Kantian ethics (& suicide): Kantian ethics (& suicide): Immanuel Kant ( ). A German philosopher. Ought implies Can Maxims Categorical Imperative.
Kant and Moral Duties.  We don’t require moral theory(ies) to tell us that lying and homicide are wrong, and helping those in need is a good thing.
Immanuel Kant. Two worlds Reason is part of the intelligible world Sensible (Lesser faculty) Part of the world of nature (empirical)
Categorical and Practical Imperative
Immanuel Kant Duty Ethics The moral worth of an action depends on motive (do the right thing for the right reason)
DEONTOLOGY “DUTY” ETHICS IMMANUEL KANT
Duties, Rights, and Kant Ethics Dr. Jason M. Chang.
Kant’s Ethics Kant’s quotes are from FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS.
The Categorical Imperative Kantian Ethics. Learning Intentions and Outcomes You will: Investigate the three formulations of the Categorical Imperative.
Objectives: SWBAT  Identify Immanuel Kant  Analyze Kantian Rationality  Identify and discuss the Categorical Imperative.
Immanuel Kant Deontological Ethics.
READING #1: “What This Book is About” Chapter One from The Ethics of Teaching.
WHAT IS HIS DUTY? Duty - something that one is expected or required to do by moral or legal obligation. Your response:
Normative Ethical Theory: Utilitarianism and Kantian Deontology
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant By David Kelsey.
Kant Deontology Categorical Imperative. Immanuel Kant Profile: Dead German Time of Berkley, Rousseau, Hume, Bentham Not a fan of music or arts.
You Are What You Do In Search of the Good, chapter 2.
AREA 1 GUIDING PRINCIPLES SECTION 3 Consequences (Utilitarian Ethics) Duty and Reason (Kantian Ethics)
Consequentialism, Natural Law Theory, Kantian Moral Theory
Class 6 Kant. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) From Königsberg, Germany.
© Michael Lacewing Kant’s Categorical Imperative Michael Lacewing
AIT, Comp. Sci. & Info. Mgmt AT02.98 Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues in Computing September Term, Objectives of these slides: l to describe an.
The Moral Philosophy of Immanuel Kant The Ethics of Duty and Reason
Morality in the Modern World
Ethics Overview: Deontological and Teleological ( Consequentalist) Systems.
Definitions. Definitions to Know Morality: any major decisions that affect others becomes a moral decision. Immoral: refers to the way people ought not.
Standard Form ► 1. State your position ► 2. 1 st Premise (Fact 1: State fact and source) ► 3. 2 nd Premise (Fact 2: State fact and source) ► 4. 3 rd Premise.
Morality. 1. Fundamental differences between abstract right and morality (1) Unlike the content of abstract right, the content of the moral will is not.
Lesson Objective Key Words Lesson outcomes Hypothetical Categorical Imperatives Freedom To evaluate the differences between the Hypothetical and Categorical.
Immanuel Kant and the Enlightenment Immanuel Kant: German ( ) Enlightenment: 1700's (18th Century) Applies the new rational scientific method of.
Kantian Ethics Good actions have intrinsic value; actions are good if and only if they follow from a moral law that can be universalized.
Lecture 13 Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant ( )
MNU Five Other Ethical Systems Dr. Judy Martin Session 7 – February 18, 2014.
The Study of Ethics How do we know how to do the Right Thing?
 Welcome! The objective of this 26 slide presentation is to: 1. Identify the fundamental concepts and key issues of ethics and morality. 2. Describe rules.
Philosophy, Logic and Human Existence ETHICS AND HUMAN CONDUCT IN THE SOCIETY.
Ethical Decision Making and Ethical Theory Mgmt 621 Contemporary Ethical Issues in Management Jeffery D. Smith.
It is unclear exactly what counts as a benefit or a cost
Theory of Formalism.
Absolutism.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative - revision
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Immanuel Kant
Kant’s Moral Theory.
Presentation transcript:

Immanuel Kant and the moral law

Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project, which aimed to bring religion within the limits of reason alone. He developed his thinking in the Critique of Practical Reason (1788) and Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone (1793), which follow Kant’s thorough rebuttal of the ‘it is not possible to know God by means of a priori reason’ (hence his rejection of the ontological argument — we can have such knowledge by means of pure practical reason).

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Kant (2) The Critique of Practical Reason develops moral arguments for God and immortality to take the place of the arguments he disputed in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kant’s account of Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone begins with a pessimistic account of the evil in human nature, while in the final three books of Religion Kant gives an account of the kind of religion that could be acceptable in the Age of Reason: one that is built on a foundation of universal reason and practised in the service of universal morality.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Kant (3) Particularly significant for our purposes, Kant was concerned to clarify the relation between religion and morality, which he observes can be expressed in three ways: First, ‘morality does not need religion at all’ — either in the discovery of what our duty is or in the motivation for doing it. Second, ‘morality leads inevitably to religion.’ Third, ‘religion is (subjectively regarded) the recognition of all duties as divine commands.’ As such it is an aid, useful if unnecessary, to the moral life.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Morality and freedom (1) Kant held strongly to the view that morality arises from human nature and understood the central point of morality to be that it imposes absolute duties, pointing to what humans have to do, no matter what else may happen or what other influences we may be under. However, in what appears to be almost a contradiction of logic, Kant held that this sense of moral obligation could only arise from a law we impose on ourselves. Kant’s understanding of duty was not the oppressive understanding it is sometimes given in the twenty-first century — it was not restrictive and forbidding, but essentially free.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Morality and freedom (2) The knowledge that we must do something and that we can do it can only be truly the case if we are free to do it. To be truly free means to be free from any determined action or response, or from determination by anything other than ourselves. No external agent can impose morality on us, since a good action can never be one that is imposed on us. Moral goodness comes from the heart of the truly free moral agent, acting out of their own will and from their own nature.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Morality and freedom (3) Interestingly, this means that to act morally we cannot be acting instrumentally, or with an intended purpose other than to do good for good’s sake. We cannot pursue natural goods — such as happiness, pleasure, rights or privileges — and we cannot act with the intention of conforming to the laws that God has handed down (divine command ethics) because God is an agent external to ourselves.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Morality and freedom (4) It is not even a question of morality requiring us to do good to others. The only moral obligations we have are those that derive from a moral law we ourselves legislate and that tells us to act in such a way that everyone could rationally agree to act — it sets universalisable principles. The moral law, Kant holds, is not a requirement to do good to others. Rather, it tells us to act only in ways we could all rationally agree on. It sets universal principles that are independent of all factors that may otherwise influence our actions — even God himself.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Morality and freedom (5) The purpose of his law is to provide a moral test that we can apply before we act: function in our thinking is to serve as a test for our plans. Each of us, Kant holds, should ask ourselves, ‘Can I, without self-contradiction, will that this act become a law according to which everyone would always act?’ Only if our planned action passes that test can we act upon it.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Making laws for ourselves (6) Kant’s position does away with the view that if an action yields good consequences — or if it serves as a means to an end of any kind, even obedience to God — then it is deemed to be right. Rather, for Kant we must always decide, by use of reason, what is right before we can know what is good. By legislating for ourselves, Kant believed that we generate a greater respect for the law we have imposed ourselves and we are genuinely and truly autonomous (self-governing).

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Making laws for ourselves (7) Kant believed that because we impose moral duties on ourselves, we have a genuine reason to act upon them, which arises from the free exercise of our reason. We are also free to impose moral constraints upon ourselves. This freedom is the source of human worth and dignity and distinguishes humans from other animals as we rationally assess the moral value of our actions independently of all self-interested desires.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Making laws for ourselves (8) Self-interest motivates us to act on hypothetical imperatives and Kant essentially has no problem with this, as long as we recognise that such actions have no moral value because they determine our actions — we do them for a reason which motivates us to act. By contrast, when we act with no other motivation than to do that which is morally required of us, we act freely and with genuine autonomy. For Kant, morality is never about getting what we desire, but about exercising our capacity to make a free moral choice, a capacity that is undermined if we allow our emotions to override our reasoning.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Making laws for ourselves (9) Kant had a particularly distinctive view that morality derived from human nature, but both Thomas Reid (1710–96), founder of the nineteenth-century Scottish ‘common sense’ school, and Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), the best-known proponent of utilitarianism, also adopted the belief that everyday morality could be guided by the use of abstract moral principles. Kant had thus laid down a basic principle of moral action that could be universalised without contradiction.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Universalisable moral laws (1) The principle of universalisabilty is absolutely central to Kant’s moral thinking. He wanted to offer a systematic way of determining when our actions are morally justified, and the principle ‘Act as if the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law’ provides the answer. This principle enables moral agents to act consistently by establishing maxims that can be applied to all similar cases. When we ask ‘Can I universalise my maxim?’ — for example, that whenever the weather is bad I should stay away from school — we need to ask whether we would consistently want all students to stay away from school when the weather is bad.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Universalisable moral laws (2) Kant asked that we should not appeal to the consequences of this — for example, empty classes and slow progress through the course — but to whether the principle is coherent or not. The possible consequences are hypothetical only and we cannot all agree on what constitutes a good or bad consequence. However, the principle is incoherent, since if students stayed away from school when the weather was bad, teachers would also stop coming into school because there would be no students to teach and so it would be pointless to put forward the maxim that students should not go into school in bad weather because the school would be closed as there would be neither students nor teachers present.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Universalisable moral laws (3) Universalisability allows morality to be stable, since if notions of right or wrong vary between individuals, cultures or situations, moral life in society will lack the foundation of trust and coherence for us to develop morally. Morality therefore has to be rooted in something that is good without qualification, and this Kant calls the ‘good will’. Anything else that we may value can be used for evil purposes, but the good will can be used for nothing but good since it wills to follow the moral law. The good will acts on the only proper moral motive — a respect for the moral law — and nothing outside the agent’s good will can affect the moral worth determined by such a motive.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Universalisable moral laws (4) Kant’s ethics therefore rest on the principle that we are moral agents capable of rationally deliberating about moral behaviour, and we make a free choice derived from that deliberation. Significantly, this means that every moral agent must recognise that all individuals can go about the same rational process of deliberation and choice and as a result we must recognise the intrinsic worth of all human persons, capable of making rational, independent judgements regarding how to live.

Immanuel Kant and the moral law Universalisable moral laws (5) As a result, we must be committed to respecting the interests of others and true morality must therefore go beyond preference and partiality, self-interest or even commitment to God’s moral law. Nothing but the motivation of the good will is sufficient to show us what is good.