Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 10 Epistemology #3 (Berkeley)

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Michael Lacewing Idealism Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Advertisements

Meditation IV God is not a Deceiver, Truth Criterion & Problem of Error.
The ontological argument. I had the persuasion that there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor.
The Cogito. The Story So Far! Descartes’ search for certainty has him using extreme sceptical arguments in order to finally arrive at knowledge. He has.
© Michael Lacewing Scepticism Michael Lacewing
Berkeley’s Epistemology George Berkeley – Born in 1685 at Dysert Castle in Ireland. – Elected a junior lecturer at Trinity College in Dublin in 1707.
Descartes’ rationalism
Descartes’ rationalism
René Descartes ( ) Father of modern rationalism. Reason is the source of knowledge, not experience. All our ideas are innate. God fashioned us.
Meditations on First Philosophy
Berkeley’s idealism (brief)
Charting the Terrain of Knowledge-1
Lecture Three “The Problem of Knowledge” Think (pp. 32 – 48)  Review last lecture  Descartes’ Clear and Distinct Ideas  “The Trademark Argument”  The.
Descartes on Certainty (and Doubt)
The Rationalists: Descartes Certainty: Self and God
Michael Lacewing Idealism: objections Michael Lacewing
René Descartes The father of modern Western philosophy and the epistemological turn Methodological doubt, his dreaming argument and the evil.
Results from Meditation 2
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 10 Epistemology #3 (Berkeley)
Descartes’ First Meditation
BERKELEY’S CASE FOR IDEALISM (Part 2 of 2)
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 9 Epistemology #2: Descartes
 According to philosophical skepticism, we can’t have knowledge of the external world.
© Michael Lacewing Reason and experience Michael Lacewing
Matter is Not the Object of Our Perceptions (1)Sensible things are just those that are perceived by the senses. (2)The senses perceive nothing that they.
Rationalism and Empiricism
David Hume’s Skepticism The nature of ideas and reasoning concerning ‘matters of fact’
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
Rene Descartes 1596—1650. Some dates 1543: publication of Copernicus’s De Revolutionibus 1543: publication of Copernicus’s De Revolutionibus 1633: Galileo.
Epistemology Section 1 What is knowledge?
BERKELEY’S CASE FOR IDEALISM (Part 1 of 2) Text source: A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, sectns. 1-21,
The Problem of Knowledge 2 Pages Table of Contents Certainty p – Radical doubt p Radical doubt Relativism p Relativism What should.
Descartes’ Meditations
René Descartes ( AD) Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) (Text, pp )
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 12 Minds and bodies #1 (Descartes) By David Kelsey.
Berkeley’s idealism (long) Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 9 Epistemology #2: Descartes By David Kelsey.
GEORGE BERKELEY ( ). Protestant Irish; Bishop of Cloyne A key figure in British empiricism Developed a form of subjective idealism.
BERKELEY AND IDEALISM Strange to claim there is an external world;
René Descartes, Meditations Introduction to Philosophy Jason M. Chang.
L ECTURE 14: H UME ’ S R ADICAL E MPIRICISM. T ODAY ’ S L ECTURE In Today’s Lecture we will: 1.Recap our investigation into empiricist theories of knowledge.
1 The Empiricists: Berkeley Immaterialism Soazig Le Bihan - University of Montana.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Descates Meditations II A starting point for reconstructing the world.
Three Theories of Knowledge
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 8 Epistemology #1 By David Kelsey.
What is an example of a secondary quality?
Epistemology (How do you know something?)  How do you know your science textbook is true?  How about your history textbook?  How about what your parents.
Meditations: 3 & 4.
An Outline of Descartes's Meditations on First Philosophy
WEEK 4: EPISTEMOLOGY Introduction to Rationalism.
Knowledge and Skepticism
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
Intuition and deduction thesis (rationalism)
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
PHILOSOPHY OF HUMAN PERSON
The Trademark Argument and Cogito Criticisms
Concept Innatism.
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
Descartes, Meditations 1 and 2
On your whiteboard: What is empiricism? Arguments/evidence for it?
Problems with IDR Before the holidays we discussed two problems with the indirect realist view. If we can’t perceive the external world directly (because.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 Berkeley
Philosophy Sept 28th Objective Opener 10 minutes
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 6 Descartes
Introduction to Humanities Lecture 18 George Berkeley
Epistemology “Episteme” = knowledge “Logos” = words / study of
Descartes and Hume on knowledge of the external world
Presentation transcript:

Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 10 Epistemology #3 (Berkeley) By David Kelsey

Rationalism vs. Empiricism Basic beliefs: Those beliefs not justified by other beliefs. But then how are basic beliefs justified? Rationalists: Descartes was a Rationalist For Rationalists, basic beliefs are self justified. Rationalism is too restrictive: Some philosophers say that the very problem with Rationalism is that it is too restrictive about what can be a basic belief. Empiricists: Berkeley was an Empiricist. For Empiricists, basic beliefs may be either self-justified, or justified directly by experience.

Berkeley George Berkeley lived from 1685-1753. He was one of the ‘British Empiricists’ along with Hume and Locke. He was a bishop of the Anglican church in Ireland and lived in America for a few years (1728-1731). Berkeley, Ca is named after him.

Empiricism More Basic Beliefs: Empiricists such as Berkeley want to grant us more basic beliefs than the Rationalists. This way we won’t have to appeal to God to explain how our knowledge of the external world is justified. According to Empiricists, these are basic beliefs: There is a blue blob in my visual field. It seems to me that I am in a philosophy lecture. And there are many more.

How Empiricists justify the basic beliefs The Empiricist answer to the Evil Demon: According to the Empiricist: Even the evil demon victim cannot be deceived about the content of their experience. Of course, the demon can deceive me. He can trick me into believing false things about the external world. But then I am having experiences… Thus, if it seems to me that there is a blue blob in my visual field, then there really is a blue blob in my visual field. So there’s no such thing as ‘seeming to seem’.

How Empiricists justify the non-basic beliefs Justifying the non-basic beliefs: How do Empiricists like Berkeley justify our beliefs in things other than our experiences? Empiricists hold that such beliefs must be justified by the basic beliefs, I.e. beliefs about sense experience. Classroom example: There are some experiences that go along with being in a classroom, and others that don’t.

Berkeley’s gap Berkeley’s Gap: A difficult question for the Empiricist: Do my beliefs about my visual experiences really justify my beliefs about the external world? Hallucinations and Dreams… The Empiricist will say: you just need to take into account more basic beliefs. But it seems as though no amount of beliefs about my experiences can ever add up to a conclusive reason to believe something about a wholly external reality. There is no valid argument from beliefs about experiences to beliefs about an external reality… This won’t work: beliefs about experience  external world This is called Berkeley’s gap.

Closing Berkeley’s gap No way to Close Berkeley’s Gap: The problem with Empiricism is Berkeley’s gap--there seems to be no way to get from the basic beliefs to the non-basic ones. Closing Berkeley’s gap: Berkeley aims to close the gap. He does so in a surprising way… According to Berkeley: There is an impassible gap between our basic beliefs and any beliefs about the external, non-mental world. In fact, we can have no knowledge at all of the external world. But our ordinary beliefs are not about the external world. They are complex beliefs and expectations about our own experiences. So there are only our own experiences and our own ideas. There is no such thing as an external world!!

Berkeley’s idealism Berkeley’s Idealism: On the face of it, Berkeley’s view seems absurd. What could a classroom or an oak tree be, if not a mind-independent, physical object? But according to Berkeley, an oak tree is just our sense experience of the oak tree and a classroom is just our sense experience of the classroom. Berkeley’s argument for Idealism: First, Berkeley argues that the only things we can directly perceive are our own ideas and experiences. Second, Berkeley argues that it is incoherent to suppose that something exists without being perceived. As Berkeley puts it: ‘esse est percipi’ From this it follows that the only things there are are ideas and experiences. This is his doctrine of Idealism.

Realism vs. Idealism Realism: Anti-realism: Any thoughts on Idealism? Berkeley’s idealism is often contrasted with realism. Realism is the view that some of reality is mind-independent. Anti-realism: the view that all of reality is mind-dependent. Any thoughts on Idealism? Of course, it helps Berkeley because it closes the gap between basic beliefs and non-basic beliefs. But doesn’t Idealism seem absurd?

Berkeley’s argument for Idealism Berkeley’s argument for his Idealism: 1 Nothing is perceived or conceived except mental things, I.e. experiences or ideas. This is called Representationalism. 2. There is nothing which is not perceived (or conceived.) 3. Thus, there is nothing except mental things. Any thoughts about this argument? Is it sound? What about premise two? Is it true?

Representationalism Premise 1: Justification for Premise 1: 1. Nothing is perceived or conceived except mental things--experiences or ideas. Thus, you never perceive external objects. Instead, you only perceive mental representations… Justification for Premise 1: Suppose you stand for a while with your left hand in a bucket of cold water and your right hand in a bucket of hot water. Then you plunge both hands into a bucket of warm water. Your left hand will feel hot, and your right hand will feel cold. But it can’t be the water you are feeling--the water isn’t both hot and cold. What you are feeling is your experience of the water.

Conceiving the Unconceived Premise 2: 2. There is nothing which is not perceived (or conceived). Esse est percipi: to be is to be perceived So Berkeley here is arguing for a specific analysis of existence: to exist is to be experienced. So there is no abstract notion of existence. Existence is relative…

Conceiving the Un-conceived A thought experiment: Conceiving the Un-conceived Berkeley thinks the idea of something existing without being perceived or thought of is just incoherent--unimaginable. It certainly seems as though I can imagine something that is not being seen, heard, thought of etc. pretty easily. I just think of a tree standing in a clearing with nobody around. Berkeley’s response: But that tree you are imagining is being thought of, for you are thinking of it.

So how does Berkeley answer the skeptic? Remember the skeptic: Asks you to consider the scenario in which you have the very same experiences you are having now but you are being deceived by an evil demon. You don’t know for sure that you aren’t being deceived by an evil demon, so you don’t know for sure that you are in class right now. Berkeley’s response to the skeptic: There is no external reality on my view so what is it you are being deceived about? So according to Berkeley, skeptical scenarios are impossible.

Objection 1: How is error possible? On Berkeley’s view, how can I be mistaken about anything? There’s no room for mistakes about my own ideas and experience; and Berkeley thinks that all my beliefs are beliefs about ideas and experiences. Surely we do make mistakes sometimes! Even if the evil demon is not possible, dreams and hallucinations are… Question: Can Berkeley make a distinction between dreamed experiences and waking ones?

Objection 2: continued existence Disappearing objects: It seems to follow from Berkeley’s view that objects just go out of existence when there is nobody around to perceive them. For to exist is to be perceived. But this seems really contrary to common sense. Berkeley’s response: “it is evident to every one that those things which are called the Works of Nature--that is, the far greater part of the ideas or sensations perceived by us--are not produced by, or dependent on, the wills of men. There is therefore some other Spirit that causes them; since it is repugnant that they should subsist by themselves…But, if we attentively consider the constant regularity, order, and concatenation of natural things, the surprising magnificence, beauty and perfection of the larger, and the exquisite contrivance of the smaller parts, together with the exact harmony of the and correspondence of the whole…and at the same time attend to the meaning and import of the attributes One, Eternal, Infinitely Wise, Good, and Perfect, we shall clearly perceive that they belong to the aforesaid Spirit, “who works all in all,” and “by whom all things consist.” (Principles, I, 146)

God’s existence God’s existence: Common sense: So Berkeley held that God, being omnipresent, is always perceiving everything. So it is God’s perceiving everything all the time that keeps real things from popping in and out of existence. Common sense: Thus, our common sense intuition that things have a reality independent of our perceiving them, on Berkeley’s view, is cashed out as a reality they have as perceived by an Infinite spirit… A proof of God’s existence: So for Berkeley it is the regularity we observe in nature together with his argument that there are only mental things which leads him to conclude that God must exist. So since “we are not in control of the course of the ideas we call the world,and yet they must exist in a spirit, and only a spirit could cause these ideas in our minds, it follows that there must be a spirit in which these ideas exist and which produces them in us.” ()

The Problem of the Criterion again For Berkeley, all our knowledge is gained through sense experience. But how do we know that the senses are the correct criterion? Don’t the senses deceive us? But of course Berkeley would say my senses always bring about truth so long as I form beliefs only about the content of my experience… But Maybe rationality is a better criteria though?

Final thoughts on skepticism The skeptical argument again: 1. If I don’t know that I’m not dreaming (or a victim of the evil demon) then I don’t know that I’m in a lecture. 2. I don’t know that I’m not dreaming (or a victim of the evil demon). 3. Thus, I don’t know that I’m in a lecture. Descartes reply to this argument: He denied premise 2. He thinks he knows he isn’t in a skeptical scenario because he knows God wouldn’t allow it. Berkeley’s reply to this argument: He also denied premise 2. But for Berkeley, skeptical scenarios are impossible.

How do we answer the skeptic? Which answer to the skeptic is best? It seems really that both have problems: Descartes has to justify God’s existence and Berkeley’s idealism runs so counter to common sense. Maybe we needn’t be so worried about the skeptical arguments… Any thoughts?