Binding theory.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Linguistic Theory Lecture 7 About Nothing. Nothing in grammar Language often contains irregular paradigms where one or more expected forms are absent.
Advertisements

Week 3a. UG and L2A: Background, principles, parameters CAS LX 400 Second Language Acquisition.
Lecture 11: Binding and Reflexivity.  Pronouns differ from nouns in that their reference is determined in context  The reference of the word dog is.
Week 3b. Constituents CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Week 2b. Constituents CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Pronoun-Antecedent Agreement. Pronoun A pronoun is a substitute for a noun. It refers to a person, place, thing, feeling, or quality but does not refer.
Pronouns.
University of Alberta6/3/20151 Governing Category and Coreference Dekang Lin Department of Computing Science University of Alberta.
Week 5a. Binding theory CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Structural ambiguity John said that Bill slipped in the kitchen. John said that Bill slipped in the kitchen.
CAS LX 522 Syntax I Week 12b. LF.
Installment 10b. Raising, etc CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Week 9b. A-movement cont’d
Week 5b.  -Theory (with a little more binding theory) CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Week 2. Clauses and Trees and c-command, oh my. CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
June 7th, 2008TAG+91 Binding Theory in LTAG Lucas Champollion University of Pennsylvania
Week 2. Clauses and Trees and c-command CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Computational Intelligence 696i Language Lecture 4 Sandiway Fong.
Week 13a. QR CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Quantifiers We interpret Bill saw everyone as We interpret Bill saw everyone as For every person x, Bill saw x. For.
‘Delay of Principle B’: The issue There is experimental evidence that children sometimes overrule principle B, whereas they do not overrule Principle A.
Episode 4a. Binding Theory, NPIs, c- command, ditransitives, and little v CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Week 14b. PRO and control CAS LX 522 Syntax I. It is likely… This satisfies the EPP in both clauses. The main clause has Mary in SpecIP. The embedded.
"She told me that she loved me." Wandering “only” Let me count the ways.
Week 6a. Case and checking (with a little more  -Theory) CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
CAS LX 522 Syntax I Week 11a. Wh-movement.
Pronouns – Part One Grade Eight.
Episode 4a. Binding Theory, NPIs, c- command. 4.3 CAS LX 522 Syntax I.
Binding Theory Describing Relationships between Nouns.
Linguistic Theory Lecture 10 Grammaticality. How do grammars determine what is grammatical? 1 st idea (traditional – 1970): 1 st idea (traditional – 1970):
The Grammar Business © 2001 Glenrothes College The Grammar Business Part Three 7. Other Common Errors.
1 LIN 1310B Introduction to Linguistics Prof: Nikolay Slavkov TA: Qinghua Tang CLASS 24, April 3, 2007.
The Grammar Business © 2001 Glenrothes College The Grammar Business Part 1 1. How to survive apostrophes.
Fact Extraction Ontology Ontological- Semantic Analysis Text Meaning Representation (TMR) Fact Repository (FR) Text Sources Lexicons Grammars Static Knowledge.
Pronouns. Pronouns Review Good morning! Answer the following as best you can in your comp book, without looking at your grammar book: 1.What is the definition.
Sight Words.
Lecture 1: Trace Theory.  We have seen that things move :  Arguments move out of the VP into subject position  Wh-phrases move out of IP into CP 
CAS LX b. Binding. Syntactic base rules (F2) S  NP VPVP  Vt NP S  S ConjPVP  Vi ConjP  Conj SNP  Det N C S  Neg SNP  N P Det  the, a, everyN.
Professor Ian Roberts having seen the two main types of rule systems (PS- rules/X’-theory and movement/transformational rules), we now.
Responding to Literature Houghton Mifflin Grade 3 D. Crisler 2012/2013.
Pronouns By: Chase Lindsey. Pronouns Definition- A word that takes the place of a noun, noun phrase, or noun clause There are several different types.
Week 3. Clauses and Trees English Syntax. Trees and constituency A sentence has a hierarchical structure Constituents can have constituents of their own.
Week 12. NP movement Text 9.2 & 9.3 English Syntax.
at a summer school during a job interview in a business meeting on a boat Read and match the conversations with the places.
Do you remember what reflexive pronouns are? Can you give me some examples? himself herself itself myself themselves ourselves yourself yourselves.
Three kinds of empty arguments
Introduction to Moral Theory
Point of View Dialect Values
English Syntax Week 1. Introduction.
PROUNOUNS.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant
English Syntax Week 12. NP movement Text 9.2 & 9.3.
Describing Relationships between Nouns
4 The scenario is: Marcia had a bad experience on Facebook, she used to receive massages from a guy that she didn't know personally; she just accepted.
Pronoun-Antecedent Agreement
Structural relations Carnie 2013, chapter 4 Kofi K. Saah.
Lecture 8: Verb Positions
Pronouns – Part One Grade Eight.
What if ? Imaginary situations or events in the present or future.
Tech Que: “Slime Time” Title Graphic
Fry Word Test First 300 words in 25 word groups
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Immanuel Kant
Subsets of the Real Numbers
The of and to in is you that it he for was.
:.
REPORTED SPEECH A short guide.
DIALOGUE.
History of Philosophy Lecture 17 Immanuel Kant’ Ethics
Jones and Davis’s Correspondent Inference Theory
Read the following paragraph.
Presentation transcript:

Binding theory

Binding Theory Binding Theory consists of three Principles that govern the allowed distribution of DPs. Pronouns: he, her, it, she, … Anaphors: himself, herself, itself, … R-expressions: John, the student, …

R-expressions R-expressions are DPs like Pat, or the professor, or an unlucky farmer, which get their meaning by referring to something in the world. Most DPs are like this.

Anaphors An anaphor does not get its meaning from something in the world—it depends on something else in the sentence. John saw himself in the mirror. Mary bought herself a sandwich.

Pronouns A pronoun is similar to an anaphor in that it doesn’t refer to something in the world but gets its reference from somewhere else. John told Mary that he likes pizza. Mary wondered if she agreed. …but it doesn’t need to be something in the sentence. Mary concluded that he was crazy.

The problem There are very specific configurations in which pronouns, anaphors, and R-expressions can/must be used. Even though both he and himself could refer to John below, you can’t just choose freely between them. John saw himself. *John saw him. John thinks that Mary likes him. *John thinks that Mary likes himself. John thinks that he is a genius. *John thinks that himself is a genius. The question Binding Theory strives to answer is: When do you use anaphors, pronouns, and R-expressions?

Indices and antecedents Anaphors and pronouns are referentially dependent; they can (or must) be co-referential with another DP in the sentence. The way we indicate that two DPs are co-referential is by means of an index, usually a subscripted letter. Two DPs that share the same index (that are coindexed) also share the same referent. Johni saw himselfi in the mirror.

Indices and antecedents Johni saw himselfi in the mirror. An index functions as a “pointer” into our mental model of the world. John here is a name that “points” to our mental representation of some guy, John, which we notate by giving the pointing relation a label (“i”). himself here shares the same pointing relation, it “points” to the same guy John that John does. So, any two DPs that share an index (pointing relation) necessarily refer to the same thing.

Indices and antecedents Johni saw himselfi in the mirror. The DP from which an anaphor or pronoun draws its reference is called the antecedent. John is the antecedent for himself. John and himself are co-referential.

Constraints on co-reference Johni saw himselfi. *Himselfi saw Johni. *Johni’s mother saw himselfi. It is impossible to assign the same referent to John and himself in the second and third sentences. What is different between the good and bad sentences?

Binding What is the difference between the relationship between John and himself in the first case and in the second case? * IP DP I IP DPi D I VP DPi I -ed John John D DP V DPi I VP ’s mother see himself -ed V DPi see himself

Binding In the first case, the DP John c-commands the DP himself. But not in the second case. * IP DP I IP DPi D I VP DPi I -ed John John D DP V DPi I VP ’s mother see himself -ed V DPi see himself

Binding When one DP c-commands and is coindexed with another DP, the first is said to bind the other. * IP DP I IP DPi D I VP DPi I -ed John John D DP V DPi I VP ’s mother see himself -ed V DPi see himself

* Binding Definition: A binds B iff A c-commands B A is coindexed with B “if and only if” * IP DP I IP DPi D I VP DPi I -ed John John D DP V DPi I VP ’s mother see himself -ed V DPi see himself

Binding Principle A of the Binding Theory (preliminary): An anaphor must be bound. * IP DP I IP DPi D I VP DPi I -ed John John D DP V DPi I VP ’s mother see himself -ed V DPi see himself

Principle A This also explains why the following sentences are ungrammatical: *Himselfi saw Johni in the mirror. *Herselfi likes Maryi’s father. *Himselfi likes Mary’s fatheri. There is nothing which c-commands and is coindexed with himself and herself. The anaphors are not bound, which violates Principle A.

Binding domains But this is not the end of the story; consider *Johni said that himselfi likes pizza. *Johni said that Mary called himselfi. In these sentences the DP John c-commands and is coindexed with (=binds) himself, satisfying our preliminary version of Principle A—but the sentences are ungrammatical. John didn’t say that anyone likes pizza. John didn’t say that Mary called anyone.

Binding domains Johni saw himselfi in the mirror. Johni gave a book to himselfi. *Johni said that himselfi is a genius. *Johni said that Mary dislikes himselfi. What is wrong? John binds himself in every case. What is different? In the ungrammatical cases, himself is in an embedded clause.

Binding domains It seems that not only does an anaphor need to be bound, it needs to be bound nearby (or locally). Principle A (revised): An anaphor must be bound in its binding domain. Binding Domain (preliminary): The binding domain of an anaphor is the smallest clause containing it.

Principle A The definition of binding domain is very complicated (this occupied many syntacticians in the early ’80s). A clause (IP) delimits a binding domain. But other things do too… Mary likes [DP John’s picture of himselfi ]. *Maryi likes [DP John’s picture of herselfi ]. Maryi wants [DP a picture of herselfi ].

Binding domain Let’s say this: The binding domain for an anaphor is the smallest of: An IP that dominates it. A DP, with a specifier, that dominates it. Note! This is not perfect, but it is a pretty close approximation.

Pronouns *Johni saw himi in the mirror. Johni said that hei is a genius. Johni said that Mary dislikes himi. Johni saw himj in the mirror. How does the distribution of pronouns differ from the distribution of anaphors? It looks like it is just the opposite.

Principle B Principle B A pronoun must be free in its binding domain. Free Not bound *Johni saw himi. Johni’s mother saw himi.

Principle C We now know where pronouns and anaphors are allowed. So what’s wrong with these sentences? The pronouns are unbound as needed for Principle B. What are the binding relations here? *Hei likes Johni. *Shei said that Maryi fears clowns. Hisi mother likes Johni.

Principle C Binding is a means of assigning reference. R-expressions have intrinsic reference; they can’t be assigned their reference from somewhere else. R-expressions can’t be bound, at all. Principle C An r-expression must be free.

Binding Theory Principle A. An anaphor must be bound in its binding domain. Principle B. A pronoun must be free in its binding domain. Principle C. An r-expression must be free. The binding domain for an anaphor is the smallest of (i) An IP that dominates it, (ii) A DP, with a specifier, that dominates it. Bound: coindexed with a c-commanding antecedent (Free: not bound).

Constraints on interpretation Binding Theory is about interpretation. Only a structure that satisfies Binding Theory is interpretable. pronounce Lexicon Merge interpret Workbench

Constraints on interpretation If we put together a tree that isn’t interpretable, the process (derivation) is sometimes said to crash. pronounce Lexicon Merge interpret Workbench

Constraints on interpretation If we succeed in putting together a tree that is interpretable (satisfying the constraints), we say the process (derivation) converges. pronounce Lexicon Merge interpret Workbench

       

Exercise to ponder Young kids (5-6 years) seem to accept sentences like (1) as meaning what (2) means for adults. (1) Mama Bear is pointing to her. (2) Mama Bear is pointing to herself. Suppose that contrary to appearances, kids do know and obey Principle B. Look carefully at the definitions of Binding Theory. If Principle B isn’t the problem, what do you think kids are getting wrong to allow (1) to have the meaning of (2)? Think in particular about how you decide which index to assign to her. What is the implication of having the same index? What is the implication of having different indices?