The Ontological Proof (I)

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Modal Versions of the Ontological Argument Based on Alvin Plantingas discussion in God, Freedom, and Evil (1974).
Advertisements

Ontological Argument for God Introduction to Philosophy Jason M. Chang.
The Ontological Argument
The Ontological Proof For around a thousand years, various proofs for the existence of God have gone by the name ‘The Ontological Proof.’ The first person.
The Ontological Argument
Proslogion (and commentary) Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
The Perfect God Anselm’s clever trick.
Is Religion Reasonable? Faith Seeking Understanding The ontological argument The cosmological argument The teleological argument (from design)
Can we prove that God Exists? Philosophers through the centuries have tried to prove whether God exists.
The Ontological Proof (II) We have seen that, if someone wishes to challenge the soundness of the Modal Ontological, he denies the truth of the second.
PHL 201 Problems of Philosophy March 25 th Chapter Five, ‘God’
 Born to a noble family in Italy  As a young man, joins the Benedictine Order in Normandy, France, residing in the monastery there for 30 years – 15.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Arguments for God’s existence.  What are we arguing for?
PHIL/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Ontological Argument.
Introduction to Humanities Lecture 11 Anselm & Aquinas By David Kelsey.
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION  Preliminary Issues:  Agreement vs. Tolerance  Different Religions ARE Incompatible  Religious Claims Aren’t True FOR Individuals.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
A Mickey Mouse Guide to the Ontological Argument
Arguments for The Existence of God Ontological Cosmological Telelogical Ontological Cosmological Telelogical.
Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.
LECTURE 14 WHY IS THERE ANYTHING AT ALL? THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
The Ontological Argument for the Existence of God August 15, 2015 George Cronk, J.D., Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy & Religion Bergen Community College.
The Ontological Argument
Anselm’s Ontological Argument STARTER TASK: ‘Fools say in their hearts, “There is no God”’ Psalm 14:1 Copy this statement down. What do you think it is.
Anselm & Aquinas. Anselm of Canterbury ( AD) The Ontological Argument for the Existence of God (Text, pp )
Meditations: 3 & 4.
WEEK 3: Metaphysics Natural Theology – Anselm’s Ontological Argument.
The Ontological Argument
Ontological Argument (Ontological is from the Greek word for being, named by Kant) Learning Objectives To know the specification content To know the meaning.
Philosophy of Religion Ontological Argument
The Mickey Mouse Guide to the Ontological Argument
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT 1
OA: Faith and Reason What difference does the argument make
The Ontological Argument
The ontological argument
Other versions of the ontological argument
Philosophy MAP 2 and new topic The Idea of God
Unit 2: Arguments relating to the existence of God.
Challenges to the OAs The different versions of OA are challenged by:
A Mickey Mouse Guide to the Ontological Argument
Philosophy of Religion AO2 1 d, e and f evaluation questions
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
Other versions of the ontological argument
Ontological arguments for God’s existence:
Philosophy of Religion AO2 1 d, e and f evaluation questions
The Ontological Argument: St. Anselm’s First Argument
Draw the most perfect holiday Island you can imagine...
Philosophy of Religion AO2 1 d, e and f evaluation questions
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT
In pairs, write a list of all the reasons people believe in God.
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Explore key ideas in the ontological argument. (8 marks)
The Ontological Argument Aim: To explore the attributes of God.
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
Explore the use of a’priori reasoning in the ontological argument
Necessary Being Discussion 1
Norman Malcolm on the Ontological Argument
Describe this object: Does it help describe it further by saying it exists?
The Big Picture Deductive arguments - origins of the ontological argument Deductive proofs; the concept of ‘a priori’. St Anselm - God as the greatest.
Other versions of the ontological argument
The Ontological Argument
The Ontological Argument
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Clarify and explain the key ideas. A’priori Deductive
Clarify and explain the key ideas. A’priori Deductive
By the end of today’s lesson you will:
Ontological Argument – challenges against
Arguments for The Existence of God
Clarify the key ideas Logic Definition Premises Outline opinion Flawed
Presentation transcript:

The Ontological Proof (I) For around a thousand years, various proofs for the existence of God have gone by the name ‘The Ontological Proof.’ The first person to give such a proof was St. Anselm of Canterbury in the 11th Century in his Proslogion. A Priori Proof: A proof the key premises of which can be known independent of any experience of the actual world.

Anselm also provided a very influential, short-hand definition for God. God = The Being than Whom none greater can be conceived. Actually, Anselm gave two Ontological Proofs. We shall concentrate on a simplified version of the second one. This Proof, in recent years, has been developed by such philosophers as Charles Hartshorne, Norman Malcolm, and Alvin Plantinga.

Anselm’s Second Ontological Proof (Simplified) If it is possible for God to exist, then God actually exists. It is possible for God to exist. Therefore, God actually exists. Now, at first glance, it would appear that no one could take this proof seriously. God’s mere possibility implies His actuality?

Many things are possible. For example, Polka Dot Zebras Striped Leopards Janet Jackson – The opera singer The mere fact that these things are possible does not mean they actually exist. Why should we believe that, in the case of God, and God alone, His possibility implies His actuality?

St. Anselm of Canterbury, Proslogion “It is possible to conceive of a Being which cannot be conceived not to exist, and this [Being] is greater than one which can be conceived not to exist. Hence, if [the Being] than which nothing greater can be conceived can be conceived not to exist, [it] is not [the Being] than which nothing greater can be conceived. But, this is an irreconcilable contradiction. There is, then, so truly a Being than which nothing greater can be conceived . . . , that it cannot even be conceived not to exist, and this Being Thou art, O Lord, our God.” St. Anselm of Canterbury, Proslogion

Now, this is very dense English translated from even denser Latin Now, this is very dense English translated from even denser Latin. What does Anselm mean here? We will restate the proof Anselm gives here as Lemma Θ. A lemma is a smaller proof done within the context of a larger proof. Here Lemma Θ is the proof for Step (A.) of the simplified version of Anselm’s Second Ontological Proof.

Preliminaries God – The Being than Whom none greater can be conceived, i.e. the Being Who is as perfect as any being can be, the maximally perfect Being. Some of God’s properties are omnipotence, omniscience, and omnibenevolence. Possible Reality – A reality that can be. A possible reality might or might not be actual. The possible reality in which George W. Bush is the President of the USA is actual. The possible reality in which Janet Jackson is an opera singer is not actual.

Lemma Θ is an example of the proof type known as Reductio ad Absurdum. In a Reductio proof, one proves the conclusion is true by proving its opposite is false. One proves the opposite of the conclusion is false by validly deducing from the opposite a self-contradiction. For example, ‘Today is and is not Thursday.’

Any statement from which one can validly deduce a self-contradiction, i.e any statement that reduces to an absurdity, must be false. Therefore its opposite, in this case, the conclusion one wants to prove, must be true. Lemma Θ Conclusion to Prove: If a Being, call the Being D, is God in one possible reality, then D is God in every possible reality. (This statement is a more precise formulation of Step (A.) in the simplified version of Anselm’s Second Ontological Proof.)

Suppose not, i.e suppose that D is God in some possible realities but not in other possible realities. (Assumption for Reductio) It is greater to be God in every possible reality instead of being God only in some possible realities. (Premise) In every possible reality in which D is God, one can conceive of another being D* who is God in every possible reality. (from A)

In any possible reality in which D is God, one can conceive of another being D* who is greater than D. (from 2 & 3) In any possible reality in which D is God, one can conceive of another being D* greater than the Being than Whom none greater can be conceived. (from 4 and the Definition of God) [(5.) is a self-contradiction]

Thus, if a being, call the being D is God in one possible reality, then D is God in every possible reality. (from 1 thru 5 by Reductio ad Absurdum) Philosopher J. N. Findlay sums up the insight of Lemma Θ (and Anselm’s original proof): “It is [contrary to the demands and claims inherent in religious attitudes that their object] should possess its various excellences in some merely

“adventitious manner. It would be quite unsatisfactory, from the religious standpoint, if an object merely happened to be wise, good, powerful and so forth, even to a superlative degree.” J. N. Findlay, Mind, 57 (1948) In other words, a being who happens to be God in one possible reality, but who is, for example, Pee Wee Herman in every other possible reality is not a being worth worshipping in any possible reality.

To be worthy of worship, to be truly God, in ANY possible reality, a being must be maximally perfect in EVERY possible reality. But, for a being to be anything in every possible reality means the being must exist in every possible reality. Thus, if a being is God in even one possible reality, then the being is God in every possible reality. Since actual reality is a possible reality, if a being is God in even one possible reality (i.e if it’s possible for God to exist), then God actually exists.

Norman Malcolm, Knowledge and Certainty Today, thanks to the efforts of Hartshorne, Malcolm, and Plantinga, almost everyone concedes the truth of Step (A.) of the simplified version of Anselm’s Second Ontological Proof. Today, if someone challenges Anselm’s Second Ontological Proof, they tend to deny Step (B.) of the simplified version, i.e. that it’s possible for God to exist. “The only intelligible way of rejecting Anselm's . . . [proof] is to maintain that the the concept of God, as [the] Being greater than which cannot be conceived, is self-contradictory or nonsensical.” Norman Malcolm, Knowledge and Certainty