Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Logics for Data and Knowledge Representation

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Logics for Data and Knowledge Representation"— Presentation transcript:

1 Logics for Data and Knowledge Representation
Exercises of Propositional Logic Vincenzo Maltese

2 Modeling the world World Monkey SEMANTIC GAP Mental Model Language L 2
PROPOSITION SENTENCE 2

3 The famous triangle Monkey CONCEPT (what we have in mind) refers to
symbolizes Monkey REFERENT (the real object) SYMBOL (what we write) stands for 3

4 Example: what is a Banana?
THE WORLD CHANGED MENTAL MODEL MENTAL MODEL I mean banana as something yellow and curve, no matter if partially opened I mean banana as something yellow or red, which can be one or many together, no matter how big they are, and whether they are opened or not T F T F FORMAL MODEL M1 FORMAL MODEL M2 4

5 Symbols in PL Which of the following symbols are used in PL?
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Which of the following symbols are used in PL? ⊓  ⊤ ∨ ≡ ⊔ ⊑ → ↔ ⊥ ∧ ⊨

6 Symbols in PL (solution)
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Which of the following symbols are used in PL? ⊓  ⊤ ∨ ≡ ⊔ ⊑ → ↔ ⊥ ∧ ⊨ 6

7 Formation Rules (FR): well formed formulas
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Well formed formulas (wff) in PL can be described by the following BNF grammar (codifying the FR): <Atomic Formula> ::= A | B | ... | P | Q | ... | ⊥ | ⊤ <wff> ::= <Atomic Formula> | ¬<wff> | <wff>∧ <wff> | <wff> ∨ <wff> <wff> <wff> | <wff>  <wff> Σ0 + FR define a propositional language A formula is correct if and only if it is a wff PARSER ψ, PL Yes, ψ is correct! No

8 Formation rules Which of the following is not a wff?
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Which of the following is not a wff?  MonkeyLow ∨ BananaHigh   MonkeyLow  BananaHigh MonkeyLow   BananaHigh MonkeyLow →  GetBanana NUM. 3 IS WRONG! 8

9 Translate NL sentences into PL
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS If David comes to the party then Bruno and Carlo come too D  B ∧ C Carlo comes to the party only if Angelo and Bruno do not come (A ∧ B)  C Carlo comes to the party given that David doesn't come, but, if David comes, then Bruno doesn't come (C  D) ∧ (D  B) A necessary condition for Angelo coming to the party, is that, if Bruno and Carlo aren't coming, David comes A  ((B ∧ C)  D) CHANGED 9

10 Modeling the problem of passing the exam
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS If you play and you study you'll pass the exams, while if you play and don't study you won't pass. Thus, if you play, then you study and you'll pass the exams, or you don't study and you won't pass. L = {P, S, E} P = “you play”, S = “you study”; E = “you pass the exam” (P ∧ S)  E (P ∧ S)  E P  (S ∧ E)  (S ∧ E) CHANGED 10

11 Modeling the Bananas SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Bananas may differ in many ways. However, there are red and yellow bananas. I like bananas, but I eat only yellow bananas. If I do not eat at least a banana I get crazy. CHANGED L = {RedBanana, YellowBanana, EatBanana, GetCrazy, Banana} T = {RedBanana → Banana, YellowBanana → Banana, EatBanana → YellowBanana,  EatBanana → GetCrazy} 11

12 Truth-values SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Definition: a truth valuation on a propositional language L is a mapping ν assigning to each formula A of L a truth value ν(A), namely in the domain D = {T, F} ν(A) = T or F according to the modeler, with A atomic ν(¬A) = T iff ν(A) = F ν(A∧B) = T iff ν(A) = T and ν(B) = T ν(A∨B) = T iff ν(A) = T or ν(B) = T ν(⊥) = F (since ⊥=df P∧¬P) ν(⊤) = T (since ⊤=df ¬⊥) ν(A  B) = T iff ν(A) = F or ν(B) = T

13 Truth valuations and Truth Tables
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS A truth valuation on a PL language L is a mapping ν that assigns to each formula P of L a truth value ν(P). A truth table is composed of one column for each input variable and one (or more) final column for all of the possible results of the logical operation that the table is meant to represent. Each row of the truth table therefore contains one possible assignment of the input variables, and the result of the operation for those values. LOGICAL OPERATION VARIABLES A B A∧B T F POSSIBLE ASSIGNEMENTS

14 Example Calculate the Truth Table of the following formulas:
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Calculate the Truth Table of the following formulas: (1) A ∧ B; (2) A ∨ B; (3) A ↔ B. VARIABLES (1) (2) (3) A B A∧B A∨B A↔B T F POSSIBLE ASSIGNEMENTS

15 Provide the models for the propositions
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS RECALL: a truth valuation ν is a model for a proposition P iff ν(P) = true List the models for the following formulas: A ∧ ¬B (A ∧ B) ∨ (B ∧ C) A ∨ B → C ¬A ↔ B ↔ C A B A ∧ ¬ B T F MODEL 15

16 Exercise: Truth Valuations
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Compute truth valuations for the formula P: (A∨B)→ C a) Rewrite as  (A ∨ B) ∨  C b) Rewrite as ( A ∧  B) ∨  C A B C P T F 16

17 Exercise: Truth Valuations
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Compute truth valuations for the formula P: (A  B)  ¬B Notice that the formula is unsatisfiable. In fact: A B P T F 17

18 Exercise: Truth Valuations
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Compute truth valuations for the formula P: ¬(A → B) → (A  ¬B) Notice that the formula is valid. In fact: a) Rewrite as ¬¬(A → B) ∨ (A  ¬B) b) Rewrite as (¬A ∨ B) ∨ (A  ¬B) A B P T F 18

19 Entailment SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS RECALL:  ⊨ ψ iff all models satisfying the formulas in  also satisfy ψ Let A, B, C be propositional sentences. If A ⊨ B ∧ C, then A ⊨ B or A ⊨ C or both? Proof: If A ⊨ B ∧ C, for all ν such that v(A) = T it should be v(B ∧ C) = T. However, by definition this means that v(B) = T and v(C) = T. Therefore it is true for both.

20 Exercise: prove entailment
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Given that: P = (A ∨ B ) ∧ (C ∨ D ∨ E) Q1 = A ∨ B Q2 = (A ∨ B ∨ C) ∧ ((B ∧ C ∧ D) → E) Q3 = (A ∨ B) ∧ (D ∨ E) Does P ⊨ Qi ? Proof: Let X = A ∨ B, Y = D ∨ E, then we can rewrite: P = X ∧ (¬C ∨ Y); Q1 = X; Q2 = (X ∨ C) ∧ (¬B ∨ ¬C ∨ Y); Q3 = X ∧ Y P ⊨ Q1 is obvious. Since X ⊨ X ∨ C and (¬ C ∨ Y) ⊨ (¬B ∨ ¬C ∨ Y), then P ⊨ Q2. Since Y ⊨ (¬C ∨ Y), then Q3 ⊨ P (and not vice versa).

21 Exercise: prove entailment using truth tables
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Given that: P = (A ∨ B ) ∧ (C ∨ D ∨ E) Q1 = A ∨ B Q2 = (A ∨ B ∨ C) ∧ ((B ∧ C ∧ D) → E) Q3 = (A ∨ B) ∧ (D ∨ E) (1) List all truth assignments such that P ⊨ Qi (2) Is there any assignment such that P ⊨ Qi for all i? Solution to (1): First compute the truth tables for all the propositions above. Then, list all rows for which both P and Qi are true. Solution to (2): Check whether there is any assignment for which all the sentences above are true. 21

22 Logical implication and deduction
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Deduction (⊢) is the process of inferring new knowledge from known facts. Logical implication (→) is a way to include deduction directly in the language. It is an alternative way to implement deduction (deduction theorem). For instance: ¬(A ∨ B) → (¬A ∧ ¬B) iff ¬(A ∨ B) ⊢ (¬A ∧ ¬B) Well-known tautologies (e.g. the De Morgan Law above) can be used 22

23 Prove using truth tables, the following deductions
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Double negative elimination  P ⊢ P Conjunction introduction / elimination (a) {P, Q} ⊢ P∧Q; (b) P ∧ Q ⊢ P; (c) P ∧ Q ⊢ Q. Disjunction introduction / elimination  (a) P ⊢P ∨ Q; (a) Q ⊢ P ∨ Q; (c) {P ∨ Q, P → R, Q → R} ⊢ R Bi-conditional introduction / elimination (P → Q) ∧ (Q → P) ⊢ (P ↔ Q)  De Morgan (a) (P ∧ Q) ⊢ P ∨ Q; (b) (P ∨ Q) ⊢ P ∧ Q 23

24 Proofs of the Deduction Rules
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS P Q P∧Q P∨Q P↔Q T F P Q ¬¬P P→Q Q→P ¬(P∧Q) ¬P∨¬Q ¬(P∨Q) ¬P∧¬Q T F 24

25 Prove validity (I) SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Suppose p, q, r, s are four propositional sentences, is the following sentence valid? A = (p → r) → (p ∨ r) A way to prove validity is to show that the proposition entails ⊤. This can be done by applying well known tautologies (e.g. De Morgan). In alternative we can show using truth tables that all the assignments are true. (p → r) → (¬p ∨ r) = ¬(p → r) ∨ (¬p ∨ r) = ¬(¬p ∨ r) ∨ (¬p ∨ r) = ⊤

26 Recall the DPLL algorithm
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Recall the DPLL algorithm Input: a proposition P in CNF Output: true if "P satisfiable" or false if "P unsatisfiable" boolean function DPLL(P) { if consistent(P) then return true; if hasEmptyClause(P) then return false; foreach unit clause C in P do P = unit-propagate(C, P); foreach pure-literal L in P do P = pure-literal-assign(L, P); L = choose-literal(P); return DPLL(P  L) OR DPLL(P  L); } Consistency Check Empty Close Test Unit Propagation Pure Literal Elimination Splitting rule 26

27 Convert a formula in CNF
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS (A  B)  ¬A ¬ (A  B)  ¬A ¬ A  ¬B  ¬A (C  ¬A)  ¬(B  ¬A) (¬C  ¬A)  ¬(B  ¬A) (¬C  ¬A)  (¬B  ¬¬A) (¬C  ¬A)  (¬B  ¬A)

28 Convert a formula in CNF
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS (A  C)  (C  ¬A) ¬(A  C)  (C  ¬A) ¬(A  C)  (¬C  ¬A) ¬A  ¬C  ¬C  ¬A ¬A  ¬ C ((A → B) → A) → A (( A  B)  A)  A ((A  B)  A)  A ((A  A)  (A  B))  A A  (A  B)  A (A  B) A  B

29 Using DPLL for reasoning tasks
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Model checking Does ν satisfy P? (ν ⊨ P?) Check if ν(P) = true Satisfiability Is there any ν such that ν ⊨ P? Check that DPLL(P) succeeds and returns a ν Unsatisfiability Is it true that there are no ν satisfying P? Check that DPLL(P) fails Validity Is P a tautology? (true for all ν) Check that DPLL(P) fails NOTE: typical DPLL implementations take two parameters: the proposition P and a model ν. Therefore, in case of model checking the real call would be DPLL(P, ν) and check that it succeeds 29

30 Use DPLL to prove satisfiability
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS B  ¬A  (¬C  A)  (B  C) 1. Is it a consistent set of literals? There are no contradictions, but there are closes which are not atomic. 2. Are there any empty clauses? No, go ahead. 3. Assign the right truth value to all literals and simplify the formula: Assign v(B) = T, v(A) = F and then the formula simplifies to ¬C 4. Assign the right value to pure literals: Assign v(C) = F. Done. 5. No need for the splitting rule The formula is satisfiable at least for the assignment (a model for it): v(A) = F, v(B) = T, v(C) = F

31 Use DPLL to prove satisfiability
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS (C  A)  (C  B)  (A  B) First convert in CNF: ( C  A)  ( C  B)  ( A   B) 1. Is it a consistent set of literals? There are no contradictions, but there are closes which are not atomic. 2. Are there any empty clauses? No, go ahead. 3. Assign the right truth value to all literals and simplify the formula. There are no atomic clauses. Go ahead. 4. Assign the right value to pure literals: Assign v(C) = T and simplify to ( A   B) 5. Apply the splitting rule and return DPLL(( A   B)  A) or DPLL(( A   B)   A) …

32 Use DPLL to prove unsatisfiability
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Using DPLL, prove the unsatisfiability of (B → A)  (¬A  B) First convert in CNF: (B  A)  ¬A  B Assign the right truth value to all literals and simplify the formula: Assign v(A) = F, v(B) = T. Now, by propagation all the literals in the first clause become false. This generates an empty clause, thus the DPLL returns false.

33 Use DPLL to prove validity
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Using DPLL, prove the validity of (A → B) → (¬B → ¬A) First negate the formula: ¬((A → B) → (¬B → ¬A)) Then convert in CNF: ¬((¬A  B) → (B  ¬A)) ¬(¬(¬A  B)  (B  ¬A)) (¬A  B)  ¬(B  ¬A) (¬A  B)  ¬B  A Assign the right truth value to all literals and simplify the formula: Assign v(A) = T, v(B) = F. Now, by propagation all the literals in the first clause become false. This generates an empty clause, thus the DPLL returns false. Thus, the original formula is valid.

34 Use DPLL to prove validity
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS Using DPLL, prove the validity of ¬(A → B) → (A  ¬B) First negate the formula: ¬(¬(A → B) → (A  ¬B)) Then convert in CNF: ¬((A → B)  (A  ¬B)) ¬(A → B)  ¬(A  ¬B) ¬(¬A  B)  ¬(A  ¬B) (A  ¬B)  (¬A  B) (A  ¬B  ¬A)  (A  ¬B  B) (¬B  ⊥)  (A  ⊥) This is clearly unsatisfiable even before calling DPLL.

35 Are you ‘Sherlock Holmes’?
SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS There was a robbery in which a lot of goods were stolen. The robber(s) left in a truck. It is known that : (1) Nobody else could have been involved other than A, B and C. (2) C never commits a crime without A's participation. (3) B does not know how to drive. Is A innocent or guilty? Proof: The 3 points above can be translated in PL as follows: (1) θ1 = A ∨ B ∨ C; (2) θ2 = C → A; (3) θ3 = B → (B ∧ A) ∨ (B ∧ C) Does {θ1 , θ2 , θ3} ⊨ A ? Yes! We can prove it by showing that θ1 ∧ θ2 ∧ θ3 → A is a tautology.

36 Knights and Knaves SYNTAX :: MODELING A PROBLEM :: SEMANTICS :: LOGICAL IMPLICATION :: REASONING :: SOME NICE PROBLEMS A very special island is inhabited only by knights and knaves. Knights always tell the truth, and knaves always lie. You meet two inhabitants: Zoey and Mel. Zoey tells you that Mel is a knave. Mel says ‘Neither Zoey nor I are knaves’. Can you determine what are they? (who is a knight and who is a knave?) Proof: The two sentences above can be translated in PL as follows: (1) Z → M; (2) M → Z ∧ M. We can use truth tables to prove that there are two possible situations: - Both lie (they are both knaves) - Zoey tells the true (is a Knight) and Mel lies (is a knave)


Download ppt "Logics for Data and Knowledge Representation"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google