Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 Prof. Francesco Squintani

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 Prof. Francesco Squintani"— Presentation transcript:

1 1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 Prof. Francesco Squintani f.squintani@warwick.ac.uk

2 2 Syllabus 1. Social Preference Orders May's Theorem Arrow Impossibility Theorem (Pref. Orders) 2. Social Choice Functions Arrow Impossibility Theorem (Choice Funct.) Rawlsian Theory of Justice Arrow Theory of Justice

3 3 3. Single Peaked Preferences Black's Theorem Downsian Electoral Competition 4. Probabilistic Voting and Ideological Parties 5. Private Polling and Elections Citizen Candidate Models

4 4 References Jehle and Reny Ch. 6 Jehle and Reny Ch. 6 Mas Colell et al. Ch 21 Mas Colell et al. Ch 21 Lecture Notes Lecture Notes D. Bernhardt, J. Duggan and F. Squintani (2009): “The Case for Responsible Parties”, American Political Science Review, 103(4): 570-587. D. Bernhardt, J. Duggan and F. Squintani (2009): “The Case for Responsible Parties”, American Political Science Review, 103(4): 570-587.

5 5 D. Bernhardt, J. Duggan and F. Squintani (2009): “Private Polling in Elections and Voters’ Welfare” Journal of Economic Theory, 144(5): 2021-2056. D. Bernhardt, J. Duggan and F. Squintani (2009): “Private Polling in Elections and Voters’ Welfare” Journal of Economic Theory, 144(5): 2021-2056. M. Osborne and A. Slivinski (1996): “A Model of Political Competition with Citizen-Candidates,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 111(1): 65-96. M. Osborne and A. Slivinski (1996): “A Model of Political Competition with Citizen-Candidates,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 111(1): 65-96. T. Besley and S. Coate (1997), “An Economic Model of Representative Democracy,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112: 85-114. T. Besley and S. Coate (1997), “An Economic Model of Representative Democracy,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112: 85-114.

6 6 What is Social Choice? Normative economics. What is right or wrong, fair or unfair for an economic environment. Normative economics. What is right or wrong, fair or unfair for an economic environment. Axiomatic approach. Appropriate axioms describing efficiency, and fairness are introduced. Allocations and rules are derived from axioms. Axiomatic approach. Appropriate axioms describing efficiency, and fairness are introduced. Allocations and rules are derived from axioms. Beyond economics, social choice applies to politics, and sociology. Beyond economics, social choice applies to politics, and sociology.

7 7 Social Preferences Consider a set of social alternatives X, in a society of N individuals. Each individual i, has preferences over X, described by the binary relation R(i), a subset of X 2. The notation `x R(i) y’ means that individual i weakly prefers x to y. Strict preferences P(i) are derived from R(i): `x P(i) y’ corresponds to `x R(i) y but not y R(i) x.’

8 8 Indifference relations I(i) are derived from R(i): `x I(i) y’ corresponds to `x R(i) y and y R(i) x.’ The relation R(i) is complete: for any x, y in X, either `x R(i) y’ or `y R(i) x’, or both. The relation R(i) is transitive: for any x, y, z in X, if `x R(i) y’ and `y R(i) z’, then `x R(i) z’. Social preference relation: a complete and transitive relation R = f (R (1), …, R(N)) over the set of alternative X, that aggregates the preferences R(i) for all i = 1,…, N, and satisfies appropriate efficiency and fairness axioms.

9 9 Example: Exchange Economy x22x22 x11x11 x12x12 x21x21 In the exchange economy with 2 consumers, and 2 goods, x are such that + = +, where w is the initial endowment, and j is the good. xj1xj1 xj2xj2 wj1wj1 wj2wj2 w I1I1 I2I2

10 10 x22x22 x11x11 x12x12 x21x21 w I1I1 I2I2 For individual i, `x I(i) y’ if (, ) and (, ) are on the same indifference curve I i The relations R(i) and P(i) are described by the contour sets of the utilities u i x x 2 i y 2 i y

11 11 x22x22 x11x11 x12x12 x21x21 w I1I1 I2I2 x The line of contracts describes all Pareto optimal allocations. One possible social preference is R such that `x P y’ if and only if x is on the line of contracts, and y is not.

12 12 The case of two alternatives Suppose that there are only two alternatives: x is the status quo, and y is the alternative. Each individual preference R(i) is indexed as q in {-1, 0, 1}, where 1 is a strict preference for x. The social welfare rule is a functional F(q(1), …, q(N)) in {-1, 0, 1}.

13 13 May’s Axioms AN: The social rule F is anonymous if for every permutation p, F(q(1), …, q(N))= F(q(p(1)),…q(p(N))) NE: The social rule F is neutral if F(q) = - F (- q ). PR: The rule F is positively responsive if q > q’, q = q’ and F(q’) > 0 imply that F(q) = 1.

14 14 May’s Theorem A social welfare rule is majoritarian (i.e. F(q) =1 if and only if n + (q) =#{i: q(i) = 1} > n - (q) =#{i: q(i) = - 1}, F(q) =-1 if and only if n + (q) < n - (q), F(q) =-1 if and only if n + (q) < n - (q), F(q) =0 if and only if n + (q) = n - (q) ), F(q) =0 if and only if n + (q) = n - (q) ), if and only if it is neutral, anonymous, and positively responsive.

15 15 Proof. Clearly, majority rule satisfies the 3 axioms. By anonimity, F(q) = G(n + (q), n - (q)). If n + (q) = n - (q), then n + (-q) = n - (-q), and so: F(q)= G(n + (q), n - (q))= G(n + (-q), n - (-q))= =F(-q)=-F(q), by NE. This implies that F(q)=0. If n + (q) > n - (q), pick q’ with q’ n - (q), pick q’ with q’<q and n + (q’) = n - (q’), Because F(q’) = 0, by PR, it follows that F(q) = 1. When n + (q) n - (-q), hence F(-q) = 1 and by NE, F(q) = -1.

16 16 Transitivity Transitivity is apparently a sound axiom. But it fails for the majority voting rule. Suppose that X={x, y, z}, and `x P(1) y P(1) z’, `y P(2) z P(2) x’ and `z P(3) x P(3) y’. Aggregating preferences by the majority voting rule yields `x P y’, `y P z’, and `z P x’. This is called a Condorcet cycle.

17 17 Arrow’s Axioms U. Unrestricted Domain. The domain of f must include all possible (R(1), …, R(n)) over X. WP. Weak Pareto Principle. For any x, y in X, if `x P(i) y’ for all i, then `x P y’. ND. Non-Dictatorship. There is no individual i such that for all x,y, if `x P(i) y’ i, then `x P y’, regardless of the relations R(j), for j other than i.

18 18 IIA. Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives. Let R = f(R(1), …, R(N)), and R’ = f(R’(1),…, R’(N)). For any x,y, if every individual i ranks x and y in the same way under R(i) and R’(i), then the ranking of x and y must be the same under R and R’. This axiom requires some comments. In some sense, it requires that each comparison can be taken without considering the other alternatives at play. The axiom fails in some very reasonable voting rules.

19 19 Borda Count Suppose that X is a finite set. Let B i (x) = #{y : x P(i) y}. The Borda rule is: x R y if and only if B 1 (x) + …+ B N (x) > B 1 (y) + …+ B N (y). This rule does not satisfy IIA. Suppose 2 agents and {x,y,z} alternatives. x P(1) z P(1) y, y P(2) x P(2) z yields x P y x P*(1) y P*(1) z, y P*(2) z P*(2) x yields y P x

20 20 Theorem If there are at least 3 allocations in X, then the axioms of Unrestricted Domain, Weak Pareto and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives imply the existence of a dictator. Corollary There is no social welfare function f that satisfies all the Arrow axioms for the aggregation of individual preferences. Arrow Impossibility Theorem

21 21 Proof (Geanakoplos 1996). Step 1. Consider any social state c. Suppose that `x P(i) c’ for any x other than c, and for any i. By Weak Pareto, it must be that `x P c’ for all such x. Step 2. In order, move c to the top of the ranking of 1, than of 2, all the way to n. Index these orders as (P 1 (1),…, P 1 (N)), … (P N (1),…, P N (N)). By WP, as `c P N (i) x’ for all i and x other than c, it must be that `c P N x’ for all x other than c. The allocation c is at the top of the ranking.

22 22 Because c is at the top of the ranking P after raising it to the top in all individual i’ s ranking P(i), there must be an individual n such that c raises in P, after raising c to the top in all rankings P(i) for i smaller or equal to n. We let this ranking be (P n (1),…, P n (N)) We now show that c is raised to the top of P n for the ranking (P n (1), …, P n (N)), i.e. when raising c to the top of P(i), for all i < n.

23 23 By contradiction, say that `a P n c’ and `c P n b.’ Because c is at the top of P n (i) for i < n, and at the bottom of P n (i) for i > n, we can change all i‘s preferences to P*(i) so that `b P*(i) a’. By WP, `b P* a’. By IIA, `a P* c’ and `c P* b.’ By transitivity `a P* b’, which is a contradiction. This concludes that c is at the top of P n, i.e. when raising c to the top of P(i) for all individuals i < n.

24 24 Step 3. Consider any a,b different from c. Change the preferences P n to P* such that `a P*(n) c P*(n) b’, and for any other i, a and b are ranked in any way, as long as the ranking of c (either bottom or top), did not change. Compare P n+1 to P*: by IIA, `a P* c’. Compare P n-1 to P*: by IIA, `c P* b’. By transitivity, `a P* b’, for all a, b other than c. Because a,b are arbitrary, we have: if `a P*(n) b’, then `a P* b’. n is a dictator for all a, b other than c.

25 25 Step 4. Repeat all previous steps with state a, playing the role of c. Because, again, it is the ranking P n of n which determines whether d is at the top or at the bottom of the social ranking, we can reapply step 3. Again, we have: if `c P*(n) b’, then `c P* b’. n is a dictator for all c, b other than a. Because n is a dictator for all a, b other than c, and n is a dictator for all c, b other than a, we obtain that n is a dictator for all states.

26 26 A diagrammatic proof We assume that preferences are continuous. Continuity. For any i, x, the sets {y: y R(i) x} and {y: x R(i) y} are closed. Complete, transitive and continuous preferences R(i) can be represented as continuous utility functions u i

27 27 We aggregate the utility functions u into a social welfare function V (x) = f (u 1 (x), …, u N (x)). PI. Pareto indifference. If u i (x)= u i (y), for all i, then V(x)=V(y). If V satisfies U, IIA, and P, then there is a continuous function W such that: V(x) > V(y) if and only if W(u(x)) > W(u(y)). The welfare function depends only on the utility ranking, not on how the ranking comes about.

28 28 The axioms of Arrow’s theorem require that the utility is an ordinal concept (OS) and that utility is interpersonally noncomparable (NC). If u i represents R(i), then so does any increasing transformation v i (u i ). All increasing transformations v i must be allowed, independently across i. The function W aggregates the preferences (u i ) i=1 if and only if the function g(W) aggregates the preferences (v i (u i )) i=1, where g is an increasing transformation.

29 29 Suppose that N =2 (when N>2 the analysis is a simple extension) Pick an arbitrary utility vector u. u I II IIIIV u1u1 u2u2

30 30 By weak Pareto, W( By weak Pareto, W(u) > W(w) for all utility indexes W( w in III, and W(w)>W(u) for all utility indexes w in I. u I II IIIIV u1u1 u2u2

31 31 Suppose that W (u) > W (w) for some w in II. v 1 11 Applying the transformation v 1 (w 1 ) = w* 1 and v 2 22 v 2 (w 2 ) = w* 2, the OS/NC principle implies that W (u) > W (w*). u I II IIIIV u1u1 u2u2 w* w

32 32 This concludes that for all w in II, either W (u) W (w). It cannot be that W (u) = W (w) because transitivity would imply W (w*) = W (w). u I II IIIIV u1u1 u2u2 w* w

33 33 Suppose that W (u) > W (w). In particular, W (u) > W (u 1 -1, u 2 +1). Consider the transform v 1 (u 1 ) = u 1 +1, v 2 (u 2 ) = u 1 -1. By the OS/NC principle, W (v(u)) > W (v 1 (u 1 -1), v 2 (u 2 +1)) = W (u). u I II III IV u1u1 u2u2 w v(u) v(w)

34 34 By repeating the step of quadrant II, the transform v 1 11 v 2 22 v 1 (w 1 ) = w* 1 and v 2 (w 2 ) = w* 2, the OS/NC principle implies W (u) < W (w*) for all w* in IV. u I II III IV u1u1 u2u2 w* v(u)

35 35 The indifference curves are either horizontal or vertical. Hence there must be a dictator. In the figure, agent 1 is the dictator. u I II III IV u1u1 u2u2

36 36 Conclusion We have defined the general set up of the social choice problem. We have shown that majority voting is particularly valuable to choose between two alternatives. We have proved Arrow’s theorem: The only transitive complete social rule satisfying weak Pareto, IIA and unrestricted domain is a dictatorial rule.

37 37 Preview next lecture We will extend Arrow’ theorem to social choice functions. We will introduce the possibility of interpersonal utility comparisons. We will axiomatize the Rawlsian Theory of Justice and the Arrowian Theory of Justice


Download ppt "1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 Prof. Francesco Squintani"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google