Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Logic and Proof. Argument An argument is a sequence of statements. All statements but the first one are called assumptions or hypothesis. The final statement.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Logic and Proof. Argument An argument is a sequence of statements. All statements but the first one are called assumptions or hypothesis. The final statement."— Presentation transcript:

1 Logic and Proof

2 Argument An argument is a sequence of statements. All statements but the first one are called assumptions or hypothesis. The final statement is called the conclusion. An argument is valid if: whenever all the assumptions are true, then the conclusion is true. If today is Wednesday, then yesterday is Tuesday. Today is Wednesday. Yesterday is Tuesday.

3 Modus Ponens If p then q. p q pqp→qpq Modus ponens is Latin meaning “method of affirming”.

4 Modus Tollens If p then q. ~q ~p pqp→q~q~p Modus tollens is Latin meaning “method of denying”.

5 Equivalence A student is trying to prove that propositions P, Q, and R are all true. She proceeds as follows. First, she proves three facts: P implies Q Q implies R R implies P. Then she concludes, ``Thus P, Q, and R are all true.'' Proposed argument: Is it valid?

6 Valid Argument? Conclusion true whenever all assumptions are true. assumptionsconclusion To prove an argument is not valid, we just need to find a counterexample.

7 Valid Arguments? If p then q. q p If p then q. ~p ~q If you are a fish, then you drink water. You drink water. You are a fish. If you are a fish, then you drink water. You are not a fish. You do not drink water.

8 Exercises

9 More Exercises Valid argument True conclusion True conclusion Valid argument

10 Contradiction If you can show that the assumption that the statement p is false leads logically to a contradiction, then you can conclude that p is true. You are working as a clerk. If you have won Mark 6, then you would not work as a clerk. You have not won Mark 6.

11 Arguments with Quantified Statements Universal instantiation: Universal modus ponens: Universal modus tollens:

12 Universal Generalization valid rule providing c is independent of A e.g. given any number x, 2x is an even number => for all x, 2x is an even number.

13 Proof: Give countermodel, where  z [Q(z)  P(z)] is true, but  x.Q(x)   y.P(y) is false. In this example, let domain be integers, Q(z) be true if z is an even number, i.e. Q(z)=even(z) P(z) be true if z is an odd number, i.e. P(z)=odd(z)  z [Q(z)  P(z)] → [  x.Q(x)   y.P(y)] Not Valid Find a domain, and a predicate.

14 Proof strategy: We assume  z [Q(z)  P(z)] and prove  x.Q(x)   y.P(y)  z [Q(z)  P(z)] → [  x.Q(x)   y.P(y)] Validity

15 Proof: Assume  z [Q(z)  P(z)]. So Q(z)  P(z) holds for all z in the domain. Now let c be some domain element. So Q(c)  P(c) holds, and therefore Q(c) by itself holds. But c could have been any element of the domain. So we conclude  x.Q(x). We conclude  y.P(y) similarly. Therefore,  x.Q(x)   y.P(y) QED. (by UG)  z [Q(z)  P(z)] → [  x.Q(x)   y.P(y)] Validity

16 Proof and Logic We prove mathematical statement by using logic. not valid To prove something is true, we need to assume some axioms! This is invented by Euclid in 300 BC, who begins with 5 assumptions about geometry, and derive many theorems as logical consequences. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Euclidean_geometry

17 Proofs

18 Proving an Implication Goal: If P, then Q. (P implies Q) Method 1: Write assume P, then show that Q logically follows. If Claim:, then

19 Proving an Implication Goal: If P, then Q. (P implies Q) Method 1: Write assume P, then show that Q logically follows. If Claim:, then Reasoning: When x=0, it is true. When x grows, 4x grows faster than x 3 in that range. Proof: When

20 Proving an Implication Claim: If r is irrational, then √r is irrational. How to begin with? What if I prove “If √r is rational, then r is rational”, is it equivalent? Yes, this is equivalent; proving “if P, then Q” is equivalent to proving “if not Q, then not P”. Goal: If P, then Q. (P implies Q) Method 1: Write assume P, then show that Q logically follows.

21 Proving an Implication Claim: If r is irrational, then √r is irrational. Method 2: Prove the contrapositive, i.e. prove “not Q implies not P”. Goal: If P, then Q. (P implies Q)

22 Proving an Implication Claim: If r is irrational, then √r is irrational. Method 2: Prove the contrapositive, i.e. prove “not Q implies not P”. Proof: We shall prove the contrapositive – if √r is rational, then r is rational. Since √r is rational, √r = a/b for some integers a,b. So r = a 2 /b 2. Since a,b are integers, a 2,b 2 are integers. Therefore, r is rational. (Q.E.D.) "which was to be demonstrated", or “quite easily done”. Goal: If P, then Q. (P implies Q)

23 Proving an “if and only if” Goal: Prove that two statements P and Q are “logically equivalent”, that is, one holds if and only if the other holds. Example: An integer is a multiple of 3 if and only if the sum of its digits is a multiple of 3. Method 1: Prove P implies Q and Q implies P. Method 1’: Prove P implies Q and not P implies not Q. Method 2: Construct a chain of if and only if statement.

24 Proof the Contrapositive Statement: If m 2 is even, then m is even Try to prove directly.

25 Proof the Contrapositive Statement: If m 2 is even, then m is even Contrapositive: If m is odd, then m 2 is odd. Proof (the contrapositive):

26 Since m is an odd number, m = 2l+1 for some natural number l. So m 2 is an odd number. Proof the Contrapositive Statement: If m 2 is even, then m is even Contrapositive: If m is odd, then m 2 is odd. So m 2 = (2l+1) 2 = (2l) 2 + 2(2l) + 1 Proof (the contrapositive):

27 Proof by Contradiction To prove P, you prove that not P would lead to ridiculous result, and so P must be true. You are working as a clerk. If you have won Mark 6, then you would not work as a clerk. You have not won Mark 6.

28 Theorem: is irrational. Proof (by contradiction): Proof by Contradiction

29 Suppose was rational. Choose m, n integers without common prime factors (always possible) such that Show that m and n are both even, thus having a common factor 2, a contradiction! Theorem: is irrational. Proof (by contradiction): Proof by Contradiction

30 Theorem: is irrational. Proof (by contradiction):Want to prove both m and n are even.

31 so can assume so n is even. so m is even. Proof by Contradiction Theorem: is irrational. Proof (by contradiction):Want to prove both m and n are even.

32 Proof by Cases x is positive or x is negative e.g. want to prove a nonzero number always has a positive square. if x is positive, then x 2 > 0. if x is negative, then x 2 > 0. x 2 > 0.

33 Rational vs Irrational Question: If a and b are irrational, can a b be rational?? We know that √2 is irrational, what about √2 √2 ? Case 1: √2 √2 is rational Case 2: √2 √2 is irrational So in either case there are a,b irrational and a b be rational. We don’t need to know which case is true!

34 Rational vs Irrational Question: If a and b are irrational, can a b be rational?? We know that √2 is irrational, what about √2 √2 ? Case 1: √2 √2 is rational Then we are done, a=√2, b=√2. Case 2: √2 √2 is irrational Then (√2 √2 ) √2 = √2 2 = 2, a rational number So a=√2 √2, b= √2 will do. So in either case there are a,b irrational and a b be rational. We don’t need to know which case is true! We’ll also prove this fact later.

35 Extra

36 Power and Limits of Logic Good news: Gödel's Completeness Theorem Only need to know a few axioms & rules, to prove all validities. That is, starting from a few propositional & simple predicate validities, every valid assertion can be proved using just universal generalization and modus ponens repeatedly! modus ponens

37 Thm 2, bad news: Given a set of axioms, there is no procedure that decides whether quantified assertions are valid. (unlike propositional formulas). Power and Limits of Logic

38 Thm 3, worse news: For any “reasonable” theory that proves basic arithmetic truth, an arithmetic statement that is true, but not provable in the theory, can be constructed. Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem for Arithmetic Power and Limits of Logic No hope to find a complete and consistent set of axioms! An excellent project topic:

39 Application: Logic Programming

40 Other Applications Making queries Data mining Digital logic: Database system:


Download ppt "Logic and Proof. Argument An argument is a sequence of statements. All statements but the first one are called assumptions or hypothesis. The final statement."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google