Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Auctions & Combinatorial Auctions Adapted from notes by Vincent Conitzer.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Auctions & Combinatorial Auctions Adapted from notes by Vincent Conitzer."— Presentation transcript:

1 Auctions & Combinatorial Auctions Adapted from notes by Vincent Conitzer

2 Auctions Assumption is – If you buy the item for exactly what it is worth, there is no utility. Yale slides bring this home – especially if your evaluation isn’t correct. If you sell the item for exactly what is it worth, there is no utility. We are trying to do better than purchase for its actual value – a good deal for both. 2

3 Auction Parameters Goods can have –private value (Aunt Bessie’s Broach) –public/common value (oil field to oil companies) –correlated value (partially private, partially values of others): consider the resale value –Reservation Price Winner pays –first price (highest bidder wins, pays highest price) –second price (to person who bids highest, but pay value of second price) Bids may be –open cry –sealed bid Bidding may be –one shot –ascending –descending 3

4 English Auctions Most commonly known type of auction: –first price –open cry –ascending –Real time Dominant strategy is for agent to successively bid a small amount more than the current highest bid until it reaches their valuation, then withdraw Efficient (pareto sense) as person who values item most gets it If you win in an English auction, you know that no one else valued it as much as you. Are you happy you have won? 4

5 English Auctions Susceptible to: –winner’s curse – get excited and bid too much or not know true valuation –shills (no intention of buying. Bid up the price. Work for auctioneer on commission. Illegal in most cases.) –The earliest use of the word 'shill' actually dates back to Elizabethan England when theatre owners would pay a 'shilling' to a theatre goer who would applaud and cheer loudly at the end of a performance. Since applause is contagious, this would help ensure the success of a production. 5

6 Auction protocols: Dutch (open-cry descending) 6 The hand of the clock starts always on the top. The hand of the clock runs counter clockwise, from left to right. The price drops from high to low. The first person, out of the 300 buyers, who pushes the button is the buyer of the goods

7 Protocol: Auctioneer continuously lowers the price until a bidder takes the item at the current price Strategically equivalent to first-price sealed-bid protocol in all auction settings Time efficient (real-time) – auction happens fast Strategy: Bid as a function of agent’s private value and his prior estimates of others’ valuations. Bayesian – reasoning with uncertain statements. –Specify from prior probability and update in light of new relevant data. Best strategy: No dominant strategy in general (without more info) –Lying (down-biasing bids) & counter-speculation –Possible to determine Nash equilibrium strategies via common knowledge assumptions regarding the probability distributions of others’ values –Requires multiple rounds of posting current price Dutch flower market, Ontario tobacco auction, Filene’s basement, Waldenbooks 7

8 Multiple identical item auction – can all pay lowest price or The Yankee auction– only actually pay what you bid: Example of Yankee auction: Bidder D bids 2 items at $7 each. Bidder C bids 3 items at $6 each. Bidder B bids 5 items at $5 each. Bidder A bids 5 items at $3 each. 10 items total yields: Bidder D wins 2 items at $7 each. Bidder C wins 3 items at $6 each. Bidder B wins 5 items at $5 each. Bidder A wins no items. 8

9 First-price sealed-bid Protocol: Each bidder submits one bid without knowing others’ bids. The highest bidder wins the item at the price of his bid –Single round of bidding –(once you bid, there are no counter offers) Strategy: Bid as a function of agent’s private value and his prior estimates of others’ valuations Best strategy: No dominant strategy in general –Strategic underbidding & counter speculation –Can determine Nash equilibrium (not do anything different, knowing what others would do) strategies via common knowledge assumptions about the probability distributions from which valuations are drawn –Goal is to try to maximize the expected profit. No relevant information is revealed – not even price or winner (if you aren’t the winner) Bidder uncertainty of valuation is a factor No dominant strategy – as may not be pareto optimal using the “best strategy”. Efficient in real time as each person takes minimal time (as bidding happens in parallel) – but not too satisfying (no feedback). Lot’s of communication – all must bid. 9

10 Second-price sealed-bid Vickrey Auction Vickrey auctions are: –one shot –second-price –sealed-bid Good is awarded to the agent that made the highest bid; at the price of the second highest bid Bidding your true valuation is dominant strategy in Vickrey auctions. Why? Not prone to strategic manipulation. Vickrey auctions susceptible to antisocial behavior (bid really high to guarantee win, someone else bids somewhat high to stick you with it) Effort not wasted in counter-speculation as just bid true value. Widely advocated for computational multiagent systems Old method [Vickrey 1961], but not widely used among humans 10

11 direct revelation: only option is for agent to announce his private information A direct mechanism is said to be truthful if the agent announces his true value

12 1-item auction mechanisms English auction: –Each bid must be higher than previous bid –Last bidder wins, pays last bid Japanese auction: –Price rises, bidders drop out when price is too high (signal when leave) –Last bidder wins at price of last dropout Dutch auction: –Price drops until someone takes the item at that price Sealed-bid auctions (direct revelation mechanisms): –Each bidder submits a bid in an envelope –Auctioneer opens the envelopes, highest bid wins First-price sealed-bid auction: winner pays own bid Second-price sealed bid (or Vickrey) auction: winner pays second- highest bid

13 Complementarity and substitutability How valuable one item is to a bidder may depend on whether the bidder can get another item Items a and b are complementary if v({a, b}) > v({a}) + v({b}) superadditive E.g. Items a and b are substitutes if v({a, b}) < v({a}) + v({b}) subadditive E.g. e.g., Camera and tripod e.g., Milk or OJ

14 Strict substitutes – their combined value is the value of either one of the goods

15 Sequential auctions Suppose your valuation function is v( ) = $200, v( ) = $100, v( ) = $500 Now suppose that there are two (say, Vickrey) auctions, the first one for and the second one for What should you bid in the first auction? If you bid $200, you may lose to a bidder who bids $250, only to find out that you could have won the monitor for $200 If you bid anything higher, you may pay more than $200, only to find out that the computer sells for $1000 Sequential (and parallel) auctions are inefficient

16 What do we mean by inefficient in this context? runtime? outcome desirability?

17 exposure problem exposure problem: a bidder might bid aggressively for a set of good in the hopes of winning a bundle, but succeed in winning only a subset (and therefore pay too much) So named as bidder is exposed to risk. In superadditive case, how does the “extra” get allocated in terms of bidding strategies?

18 Combinatorial auctions v( ) = $500 v( ) = $700 v( ) = $300 Simultaneously for sale:,, bid 1 bid 2 bid 3 used in truckload transportation, industrial procurement, radio spectrum allocation, …

19 Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanism The system charges a bidder for the harm they cause other bidders For example, suppose that we want to auction two apples, and we have three bidders. Bidder A wants one apple and bids $5 for that apple. Bidder B wants one apple and is willing to pay $2 for it. Bidder C wants two apples and is willing to pay $6 to have both of them, but is uninterested in buying only one without the other. A and B should have the apples – as they value them the most. But both A and B are thinking, the seller thinks the apples are worth more BECAUSE OF ME. The price shouldn’t be higher for me because of me. Currently, B has a payment of $2. If bidder A had not been present, C would have won, and had a utility of $6, so A pays $6 (price without me)-$2 (value to others if I win) = $4. (The real cost to the seller of A’s getting the apple.) For the payment of bidder B: currently A has a utility of $5 and C has a utility of 0. If bidder B had been absent, C would have won and had a utility of $6, so B pays $6-$5 = $1. C does not need to pay anything because he doesn’t get anything. W. Vickrey. Counterspeculation, Auctions, and Competitive Sealed Tenders. Journal of Finance, 16(1):8–37, 1961. E.H. Clarke. Multipart Pricing of Public Goods. Public Choice, 11(1):17–33, 1971. T. Groves. Incentives in Teams. Econometrica, 41(4):617–631, 1973. 19

20 Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanism The system charges a bidder for the harm they cause other bidders Two apples for sale. Bid are: A: (1,$5) - one apple for five dollars B: (1, $2) - one apple for two dollars C: (2, $6) - two apples for six dollars A: without me, revenue is $6, I should only have to pay $4 (as what I cost the system) 20

21 Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Mechanism The system charges a bidder for the harm they cause other bidders Two apples for sale A: (1,$5) - one apple for five dollars B: (1, $2) C: (2, $6) D: (1,$5) Who wins and what do they pay? 21

22 VCG Mechanism for Combinatorial Auctions I pay: The value of the best allocation possible without me minus the value to everyone else of the best allocation with me Consider the following example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 9) Agent 2: ({a}, 4), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 4: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a, b}, 2) Clearly agent 1 should win BUT he feels he shouldn’t be bidding against himself. He would like to pay only what it is worth to others: without agent 1 – worth 6 with agent 1 – nobody else gets any value so worth = 0 Agent 1 is happy to pay 6 22

23 Another Example The value of the best allocation possible without me minus the value to everyone else of the best allocation with me Consider the following example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 19) Agent 2: ({a}, 3), ({b}, 0), ({c}, 3) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({c}, 2) Agent 4: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a,b,c},13) Clearly agent 1 should win BUT he feels he shouldn’t be bidding against himself. He would like to pay only what it is worth to others: without agent 1 bidding – worth 13 with agent 1 – Agent 2 still gets 3 Agent 1 is happy to pay 10 What should agent 2 pay for c? 23

24 Argue for or against: Changing my bid does not change what I pay (though it may change whether or not I win and it may change what others pay) 24 Consider the following example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 15) Agent 2: ({a}, 8), ({b}, 8), ({c}, 3) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 12), ({c}, 2) Agent 2 pays: 5 (for a and c) Agent 3 pays: 8 for b (19-11) Consider the changed example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 15) Agent 2: ({a}, 8), ({b}, 13), ({c}, 3) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 12), ({c}, 2)

25 Strategy-Proofness In the VCG mechanism, reporting their true valuation is a dominant strategy for each bidder – similar to the reasons that truthfulness is dominant with Vickrey 25

26 So, does it work well? Consider the following example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 4) Agent 2: ({a}, 1), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 4: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a, b}, 2) Best allocation is agent 1 ({a, b}, 4) Agent 1 pays: 3 – 0 = 3 So it works just like we thought it would Lots of the problems come from very few bidders – which would always be a problem for Vickrey auctions. 26

27 Another Example Consider the following example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 4) Agent 2: ({a}, 2), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 4: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 2), ({a, b}, 2) Best allocation is agent 1 ({a, b}, 4) Agent 1 pays: 4 – 0 = 4 So it works just like we thought it would In this case, second price bid is really the same as the first price bid 27

28 Collusion The VCG mechanism is not collusion-proof: if bidders work together they can manipulate the mechanism. Consider the following example: Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 4) Agent 2: ({a}, 1), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 1), ({a, b}, 0) Who wins? What do they pay? But if the two losing bidders collude and increase their two bids to ({a}, 4) and ({b}, 4), respectively, they can obtain the items for free. Agent 1: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 4) Agent 2: ({a}, 4), ({b}, 0), ({a, b}, 0) Agent 3: ({a}, 0), ({b}, 4), ({a, b}, 0) Who wins? What do they pay? 28

29 Problems with the VCG Mechanism Despite their nice game-theoretical properties, combinatorial auctions using VCG to determine payments have several problems: – Low (and possibly even zero) revenue for the auctioneer –Non-monotonicity: “better” bids can lower revenue – Collusion amongst (losing) bidders – False-name bidding: bidders may benefit from submitting bids using multiple identities. Can you give an example? –Shill bid – seller will submit a fake bid just below the high bid L.M. Asubel and P. Milgrom. The Lovely but Lonely Vickrey Auction. In P. Cramton et al. (eds.), Combinatorial Auction, MIT Press, 2006. 29

30 Conclusions Pros VCG processes have great theoretical appeal. Truth telling is a dominant strategy mechanism. This means that, in theory, a bidder’s decision to use a strategy does not depend on what the bidder thinks her competitors’ strategies are, and she need spend no effort in trying to find them out or to keep her competitors from learning her strategy. In some circumstances, they produce, expected revenue equivalent to other common auction forms. Cons However, VCG processes are just not practical. They do not work the way the (simple) theory says they should. So Why do we study VCG processes ? Because finding equilibrium strategies in combinatorial auctions is extraordinarily difficult except in VCG processes, there may well be useful insights to be had from such knowledge. For example, Mishra and Parkes (2007) analyze an iterative version of the VCG process. In addition, computerized bidding agents may be able to avoid some of the problems. Rothkopf: Thirteen Reasons Why the Vickrey-Clarke-Groves Process Is Not Practical Operations Research 55(2), pp. 191–197, ©2007 INFORMS 30

31 The winner determination problem (WDP) Choose a subset A (the accepted bids) of the bids B, v b is value of the bid to the person who received the items maximize Σ (b in A) v b (Value of accepted bids maximized ) under the constraint that every item occurs at most once in A –This is assuming free disposal, i.e., not everything needs to be allocated

32 WDP example Items A, B, C, D, E Bids: ({A, C, D}, 7) ({B, E}, 7) ({C}, 3) ({A, B, C, E}, 9) ({D}, 4) ({A}, 4) ({A, B}, 5) ({B, D}, 5) ({D,E},7) What’s an optimal solution? How can we prove it is optimal? (Important for NP-complete)

33 Price-based argument for optimality Items A, B, C, D, E Bids: ({A, C, D}, 7) ({B, E}, 7) ({C}, 3) ({A, B, C, E}, 9) ({D}, 4) ({A, B, C}, 5) ({B, D}, 5) Suppose we create “prices” (each item has the smallest price so that the sum of the prices is at least the bid price) for the items. Pick a set of prices. If our solution achieves the value indicated by the prices, we feel we have achieved optimal.

34 Price-based argument for optimality Items A, B, C, D, E Bids: ({A, C, D}, 7) ({B, E}, 7) ({C}, 3) ({A, B, C, E}, 9) ({D}, 4) ({A, B, C}, 5) ({B, D}, 5) Suppose we create “prices” (each item has the smallest price so that the sum of the prices is at least the bid price) for the items: p(A) = 0, p(B) = 7, p(C) = 3, p(D) = 4, p(E) = 0 Every bidder bids at most the sum of the prices of its items, so we can’t expect to get more than 14.

35 Create Price Based for this model Items A, B, C, D, E Bids: ({A, C, D}, 7) ({B, E}, 7) ({C}, 3) ({A, B, C, E}, 9) ({D}, 4) ({A}, 4) ({A, B}, 5) ({B, D}, 5) ({D,E},7)

36 Create Price Based for this model Items A, B, C, D, E Bids: ({A, C, D}, 7) ({B, E}, 7) ({C}, 3) ({A, B, C, E}, 9) ({D}, 4) ({A}, 4) ({A, B}, 5) ({B, D}, 5) ({D,E},7) Can you beat? A 4 B 4 C 3 D 4 E 3

37 Price-based argument Items A, B, C Bids: ({A, B}, 2) ({B, C}, 2) ({A, C}, 2) What would prices be here? What is actual upper bound on revenue?\ What if we allowed partial bid filling?

38 Price-based argument does not always give matching upper bound Items A, B, C Bids: ({A, B}, 2) ({B, C}, 2) ({A, C}, 2) Clearly can get at most 2 If we want to set prices that sum to 2, there must exist two items whose prices sum to < 2 But then there is a bid on those two items of value 2 –(Can set prices that sum to 3, so that’s an upper bound )

39 An integer program formulation x b equals 1 if bid b is accepted, 0 if it is not  maximize Σ b v b x b  subject to: for each item j, Σ b: j in b x b ≤ 1 _______________________________ If each x b can take any value in [0, 1], we say that bids can be partially accepted In this case, this is a linear program that can be solved in polynomial time This requires that –each item can be divided into fractions –if a bidder gets a fraction f of each of the items in his bundle, then this is worth the same fraction f of his value v b for the bundle –We would expect this to be easier – like fractional knapsack

40 Idea: Use weighted independent set to solve winner determination problem Build an intersection graph: nodes are bids, edges are conflicts between bids. Choose subset of the vertices with maximum total weight, such that no two vertices can have an edge between them NP-hard (generalizes regular independent set) 2 2 3 4 3 2 4

41 The winner determination problem as a weighted independent set problem Each bid is a vertex Draw an edge between two vertices if they share an item Optimal allocation = maximum weighted independent set Can model any weighted independent set instance as a CA (combinatorial auction) winner determination problem (1 item per edge (or clique)) Weighted independent set is NP-hard, even to solve approximately [Håstad 96] - hence, so is WDP: winner determination problem – [Sandholm 02] noted that this inapproximability applies to the WDP (can’t bound the error to any constant factor)

42 cannot be approximated uniformly – means there does not exist a polynomial time algorithm and a fixed constant k>0 such that the algorithm returns a solution that is at least s*/k where s* is the value of the optimal solution. (a higher s* is better)

43 Heuristic Approaches Complete heuristic – guaranteed to find an optimal solution if one exists – but may not be able to estimate amount of time it will take. incomplete heuristic - 1/  n of optimal (n is number of items), but often perform well in practice. Example of incomplete: greedy (allocates one bid at a time and never reconsiders)

44 Dynamic programming approach to WDP [Rothkopf et al. 98] Give a description of dynamic programming. For every subset S of I, compute w(S) = the maximum total value that can be obtained when allocating only items in S Then, w(S) = max {max i v i (S), max S’: S’ is a subset of S, and there exists a bid on S’ w(S’) + w(S \ S’)} Requires exponential time – because the set of all subsets is exponential

45 So… How do we approach the problem given that the solutions we have tried are NP- hard or NP-complete? Look for restricted set of problems for which we can find efficient solutions.

46 Bids on connected sets of items in a tree Suppose items are organized in a tree item A item B item C item D item E item F item G item H Suppose each bid is on a connected set of items –E.g. {A, B, C, G}, but not {A, B, G} Then the WDP can be solved in polynomial time (using dynamic programming) [Sandholm & Suri 03] Tree does not need to be given: can be constructed from the bids in polynomial time if it exists [Conitzer, Derryberry, Sandholm 04] More generally, WDP can also be solved in polynomial time for graphs of bounded treewidth [Conitzer, Derryberry, Sandholm 04] –Even further generalization given by [Gottlob, Greco 07]

47 Maximum weighted matching (not necessarily bipartite graphs – see next slide) If each bidder is only interested in winning one item. Choose subset of the edges with maximum total weight, Constraint: no two edges can share a vertex Still solvable in polynomial time 1 2 3 4 3 4 5 A B C 2 3

48 Bids with few items [Rothkopf et al. 98] If each bid is on a bundle of at most two items, then the winner determination problem can be solved in polynomial time as a maximum weighted matching problem. What is purpose of dummy nodes? –3-item example: item A item B item C A’s dummy B’s dummy C’s dummy Value of highest bid on {A} Value of highest bid on {B} Value of highest bid on {C} Value of highest bid on {A, B} Value of highest bid on {A, C} Value of highest bid on {B, C} If each bid is on a bundle of three items, then the winner determination problem is NP-hard again

49 Variants [Sandholm et al. 2002] : combinatorial reverse auction In a combinatorial reverse auction (CRA), the auctioneer seeks to buy a set of items, and bidders have values for the different bundles that they may sell to the auctioneer  minimize Σ b v b x b x b is 1 if bid is accepted  subject to  for each item j, Σ b: (j in b) x b ≥ 1 (get all items)

50 WDP example (as Combinatorial Reverse Auction ) Items A, B, C, D, E Bids: ({A, C, D}, 7) ({B, E}, 7) ({C}, 3) ({A, B, C, E}, 9) ({B,D}, 4) ({A, B, C}, 5) ({B, D}, 5) Buyer needs all items Can get two of same item

51 Variants: multi-unit CAs/CRAs Multi-unit variants of CAs and CRAs: multiple units of the same item are for sale/to be bought, bidders can bid for multiple units Let q bj be number of units of item j in bid b, q j total number of units of j available/demanded  maximize Σ b v b x b (CA)  subject to  for each item j, Σ b q bj x b ≤ q j  minimize Σ b v b x b (CRA)  subject to  for each item j, Σ b q bj x b ≥ q j

52 Variants: (multi-unit) combinatorial exchanges Combinatorial exchange (CE): bidders can simultaneously be buyers and sellers –Example bid: “If I receive 3 units of A and -5 units of B (i.e., I have to give up 5 units of B), that is worth $100 to me.”  maximize Σ b v b x b  subject to  for each item j, Σ b q b,j x b ≤ 0 cumulatively give up more than get

53 Exponentially many bundles In general, in a combinatorial auction with set of items I (|I| = m) for sale, a bidder could have a different valuation for every subset S of I –Implicit assumption: no externalities (bidder does not care what the other bidders win) Must a bidder communicate 2 m values? –Impractical –Also difficult for the bidder to evaluate every bundle Could require v i (Ø) = 0 –Does not help much We could require: if S is a superset of S’, v(S) ≥ v(S’) (free disposal) –Does not help in terms of number of values

54 Variants: no free disposal Change all inequalities to equalities

55 A bidder is single-minded if she only wants one subset of the goods. –Usually not the case Even restricting valuations to be single minded does NOT make the winner determination problem any easier.

56 Two sided auctions aka double auctions many buyers and sellers. Bid is price and quantity - positive (buyer) negative (seller). When do trades occur? continuous double – as soon as bid is received attempt to match periodic double (aka call market) – trades happen at predetermined times (called clearing the market) - rank sellers in order and buyers in order – find the point at which supply equals demand

57 Example of a double auction Sell5@$13@$26@$42@$64@$9 Buy6@$94@$56@$43@$35@$22@$1 Who should get the items and what should they pay? (Other views of same data) Sell11111222444444669999 Buy99999955554444443332222211 Sell99996644444422211111 Buy99999955554444443332222211

58 Result Sell5@$13@$26@$42@$64@$9 Buy6@$94@$56@$43@$35@$22@$1 Sell2@$64@$9 Buy2@$43@$35@$22@$1 After Before The amount paid to the seller could be less than the amount charged to the buyer, allowing a commission

59 Bidding Languages How do you expect to be able to express your bids in a combinatorial auction?

60 Bidding languages Bidding language = a language for expressing valuation functions A good bidding language allows bidders to concisely express natural valuation functions Example: the OR bidding language [Rothkopf et al. 98, DeMartini et al. 99] Bundle-value pairs are ORed together, auctioneer may accept any number of these pairs (assuming no overlap in items) E.g. ({a}, 3) OR ({b, c}, 4) OR ({c, d}, 4) implies what values for the following: –{a} –{b, c, d} –{a, b, c}

61 Bidding languages Bidding language = a language for expressing valuation Can we express the valuation function v({a, b}) = v({a}) = v({b}) = 1 using the OR bidding language? subadditive issue ({a, b},1) OR ({a},1) OR ({b},1)?

62 XORs If we use XOR instead of OR, that means that only one of the bundle-value pairs can be accepted Can express any valuation function (simply XOR together all bundles) E.g. ({a}, 3) XOR ({b, c}, 4) XOR ({c, d}, 4) implies –A value of 3 for {a} –A value of 4 for {b, c, d} –A value of 4 for {a, b, c} Can’t easily get additive values Sometimes not very concise E.g. suppose that for any S, v(S) = Σ s in S v({s}) –How can this be expressed in the OR language? –What about the XOR language? Can also combine ORs and XORs to get benefits of both [Nisan 00, Sandholm 02]

63 WDP and bidding languages Single-minded bidders bid on only one bundle –Valuation is v for any superset including that bundle, 0 otherwise If we can solve the WDP for single-minded bidders, how can we solve WDP for general OR problems? Bidder 1: ({a}, 3) OR ({a, b}, 4) OR ({c},2) Bidder 2: ({a,b}, 6) OR ({c}, 1)

64 WDP and bidding languages Single-minded bidders bid on only one bundle –Valuation is v for any superset including that bundle, 0 otherwise Suppose we have an OR language but wanted XOR. Can we make that work? For example, express the following with an OR language: ({a}, 3) XOR ({b, c}, 4)

65 Iterative Mechanisms Probe valuations only as necessary Benefit to bidders who want to reveal as little as possible about their valuations Helpful if difficult to determine valuation Agents may gain by waiting for others to reveal information – especially if determining own valuation is costly What would auctioneer queries look like?

66 Iterative Mechanisms Auctioneer can query the bidders with: –value query: suggest a bundle and ask how much is worth –demand query: ask how many would buy good for a specific price –order query: which of two bundles is preferred. –bounding query: is a give bundle worth more or less than amt

67 As a bidder, what is your expected profit in a first price auction? (assume only two bidders) It seems natural to try to maximize your expected profit. If you are trying to maximize profit, what should you bid? A little (so reward is great)? A lot (so chance of winning is good)? What is profit a function of? 67

68 What is your expected profit in a first price auction? (assume only two bidders) Expected profit (as a function of a specific bid) is the probability that you will win the bid times the amount of your profit at that price. Let p be the price you bid for an item. v be your valuation. [a,b] be the uniform range of others bid. The probability that you win the bid at this price is the fraction of the time that the other person bids lower than p. (p-a)/(b-a) The profit you make at p is v-p Expected profit as a function of p is the function = (v-p)*(p-a)/(b-a) + 0*(1- (p-a)/(b-a)) 68

69 Finding maximum profit is a simple calculus problem Expected profit as a function of p is the function (v-p) * (p-a)/(b-a) amount of profit * prob of winning So what is next? 69

70 Finding maximum profit is a simple calculus problem Take the derivative with respect to p and set that value to zero. Where the slope is zero, is the maximum value. (as second derivative is negative) f(p) = 1/(b-a) * (vp -va -p 2 +pa) f’(p) = 1/(b-a) (v-2p+a) = 0 p=(a+v)/2 (half the distance between your valuation and the min range value) Notice that the upper value (b) doesn’t matter – as you don’t care about anything higher than v. 70

71 Are you surprized? The results make sense. You never bid higher than your valuation. You can’t win these cases, so we’ll ignore them. Of the remaining cases, if you bid halfway between the low evaluation and your valuation, you expect to win half the time and lose half the time [in the cases where you have a chance]. When you do win, you pay considerably less than your valuation, and hence make a handsome profit. You have to bid more often as you won’t get everything you bid on – but this is a good plan. BUT As there are more bidders, how would that affect your bid? 71

72 In general, n agents with uniform distribution on range [0,Max] what should each agent bid? For simplicity, lets assume a=0. In order to win the bid at price p, every other person would need to bid below p. What is the chance of that? Since we want bidder 1 to bid below p and bidder 2 (and so forth), we multiply the probabilities for each of the other n-1 bidders: Expected valued = (p/b) n-1 * (p-v) = (1/b n-1 )*(p (n) – vp n-1 ) derivative wrt p = (1/b n-1 *((n)p (n-1) – (n-1)vp (n-2) ) = 0 (n)p (n-1) – nvp (n-2) +vp (n-2) = p (n-2) (pn –nv + v) so either p = 0 (obviously a minimum) or p=((n-1)/n) * v When n=2, we get the results on the previous slide. Idea is that with more bidders (randomly bidding within the range), you have to bid closer to your valuation to win; the idea of competition. 72

73 Revenue for the Auctioneer Which protocol is best for the auctioneer? Revenue-equivalence Theorem (Vickrey, 1961): All four protocols give the same expected revenue for private value auctions amongst risk-neutral bidders with valuations independently drawn from a uniform distribution. Intuition: revenue second highest valuation: – Vickrey: clear – English: bidding stops just after second highest valuation – Dutch/FPSB: because of the uniform value distribution and counter speculation, top bid second highest valuation But: this applies only to an artificial and rather idealized situation; in reality there are many exceptions. 73

74 Revelation Principle You can transform any auction into an “equivalent” one which is direct and incentive compatible (i.e., bidder will bid the true valuation) Do you believe that? That is quite a statement. Rather than lie (bid less than your true valuation), the mechanism will “lie” for you Example: assume two bidders (with valuations drawn from a uniform distribution on a fixed interval [0,max]). The optimal strategy is to bid ½ your true value. How could you change the rules so the bidder was motivated to bid true valuation? 74

75 Revelation Principle Example: assume two bidders (with valuations drawn from a uniform distribution on a fixed interval [0,max]). The optimal strategy is to bid ½ your true value. But if the rule is changed so that the winner only pays half his bid, it is optimal to bid your true value. 75


Download ppt "Auctions & Combinatorial Auctions Adapted from notes by Vincent Conitzer."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google