Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Department of Computer Science

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Department of Computer Science"— Presentation transcript:

1 Department of Computer Science
REASONING WITH CAUSE AND EFFECT Judea Pearl Department of Computer Science UCLA

2 OUTLINE Modeling: Statistical vs. Causal
Causal Models and Identifiability Inference to three types of claims: Effects of potential interventions Claims about attribution (responsibility) Claims about direct and indirect effects Robustness of Causal Claims

3 TRADITIONAL STATISTICAL
INFERENCE PARADIGM P Joint Distribution Q(P) (Aspects of P) Data Inference e.g., Infer whether customers who bought product A would also buy product B. Q = P(B|A)

4 THE CAUSAL INFERENCE PARADIGM M Data-generating Model Q(M)
(Aspects of M) Data Inference Some Q(M) cannot be inferred from P. e.g., Infer whether customers who bought product A would still buy A if we double the price.

5 FROM STATISTICAL TO CAUSAL ANALYSIS:
1. THE DIFFERENCES Data joint distribution inferences from passive observations Probability and statistics deal with static relations Probability Statistics

6 FROM STATISTICAL TO CAUSAL ANALYSIS:
1. THE DIFFERENCES Probability and statistics deal with static relations Statistics Probability inferences from passive observations joint distribution Data Causal analysis deals with changes (dynamics) i.e. What remains invariant when P changes. P does not tell us how it ought to change e.g. Curing symptoms vs. curing diseases e.g. Analogy: mechanical deformation

7 FROM STATISTICAL TO CAUSAL ANALYSIS:
1. THE DIFFERENCES Data joint distribution inferences from passive observations Probability and statistics deal with static relations Probability Statistics Causal Model Data assumptions Effects of interventions Causes of effects Explanations Causal analysis deals with changes (dynamics) Experiments

8 FROM STATISTICAL TO CAUSAL ANALYSIS: 1. THE DIFFERENCES (CONT)
Spurious correlation Randomization Confounding / Effect Instrument Holding constant Explanatory variables STATISTICAL Regression Association / Independence “Controlling for” / Conditioning Odd and risk ratios Collapsibility Causal and statistical concepts do not mix.

9 } FROM STATISTICAL TO CAUSAL ANALYSIS: 1. THE DIFFERENCES (CONT) 
Spurious correlation Randomization Confounding / Effect Instrument Holding constant Explanatory variables STATISTICAL Regression Association / Independence “Controlling for” / Conditioning Odd and risk ratios Collapsibility Causal and statistical concepts do not mix. No causes in – no causes out (Cartwright, 1989) statistical assumptions + data causal assumptions causal conclusions } Causal assumptions cannot be expressed in the mathematical language of standard statistics.

10 } FROM STATISTICAL TO CAUSAL ANALYSIS: 1. THE DIFFERENCES (CONT) 
Spurious correlation Randomization Confounding / Effect Instrument Holding constant Explanatory variables STATISTICAL Regression Association / Independence “Controlling for” / Conditioning Odd and risk ratios Collapsibility Causal and statistical concepts do not mix. No causes in – no causes out (Cartwright, 1989) statistical assumptions + data causal assumptions causal conclusions } Causal assumptions cannot be expressed in the mathematical language of standard statistics. Non-standard mathematics: Structural equation models (SEM) Counterfactuals (Neyman-Rubin) Causal Diagrams (Wright, 1920)

11 WHAT'S IN A CAUSAL MODEL? Oracle that assigns truth value to causal
sentences: Action sentences: B if we do A. Counterfactuals: B would be different if A were true. Explanation: B occurred because of A. Optional: with what probability?

12 ORACLE FOR MANIPILATION
FAMILIAR CAUSAL MODEL ORACLE FOR MANIPILATION X Y Here is a causal model we all remember from high-school -- a circuit diagram. There are 4 interesting points to notice in this example: (1) It qualifies as a causal model -- because it contains the information to confirm or refute all action, counterfactual and explanatory sentences concerned with the operation of the circuit. For example, anyone can figure out what the output would be like if we set Y to zero, or if we change this OR gate to a NOR gate or if we perform any of the billions combinations of such actions. (2) Logical functions (Boolean input-output relation) is insufficient for answering such queries (3)These actions were not specified in advance, they do not have special names and they do not show up in the diagram. In fact, the great majority of the action queries that this circuit can answer have never been considered by the designer of this circuit. (4) So how does the circuit encode this extra information? Through two encoding tricks: 4.1 The symbolic units correspond to stable physical mechanisms (i.e., the logical gates) 4.2 Each variable has precisely one mechanism that determines its value. Z INPUT OUTPUT

13 CAUSAL MODELS AND CAUSAL DIAGRAMS
Definition: A causal model is a 3-tuple M = V,U,F with a mutilation operator do(x): M Mx where: (i) V = {V1…,Vn} endogenous variables, (ii) U = {U1,…,Um} background variables (iii) F = set of n functions, fi : V \ Vi  U  Vi vi = fi(pai,ui) PAi  V \ Vi Ui  U

14 CAUSAL MODELS AND CAUSAL DIAGRAMS U1 I W U2 Q P PAQ
Definition: A causal model is a 3-tuple M = V,U,F with a mutilation operator do(x): M Mx where: (i) V = {V1…,Vn} endogenous variables, (ii) U = {U1,…,Um} background variables (iii) F = set of n functions, fi : V \ Vi  U  Vi vi = fi(pai,ui) PAi  V \ Vi Ui  U U1 I W U2 Q P PAQ

15 CAUSAL MODELS AND MUTILATION Definition: A causal model is a 3-tuple
M = V,U,F with a mutilation operator do(x): M Mx where: (i) V = {V1…,Vn} endogenous variables, (ii) U = {U1,…,Um} background variables (iii) F = set of n functions, fi : V \ Vi  U  Vi vi = fi(pai,ui) PAi  V \ Vi Ui  U (iv) Mx= U,V,Fx, X  V, x  X where Fx = {fi: Vi  X }  {X = x} (Replace all functions fi corresponding to X with the constant functions X=x)

16 CAUSAL MODELS AND MUTILATION U1 I W U2 Q P
Definition: A causal model is a 3-tuple M = V,U,F with a mutilation operator do(x): M Mx where: (i) V = {V1…,Vn} endogenous variables, (ii) U = {U1,…,Um} background variables (iii) F = set of n functions, fi : V \ Vi  U  Vi vi = fi(pai,ui) PAi  V \ Vi Ui  U (iv) U1 I W U2 Q P

17 CAUSAL MODELS AND MUTILATION U1 I W U2 Q P P = p0
Definition: A causal model is a 3-tuple M = V,U,F with a mutilation operator do(x): M Mx where: (i) V = {V1…,Vn} endogenous variables, (ii) U = {U1,…,Um} background variables (iii) F = set of n functions, fi : V \ Vi  U  Vi vi = fi(pai,ui) PAi  V \ Vi Ui  U (iv) Mp U1 I W U2 Q P P = p0

18 PROBABILISTIC CAUSAL MODELS Definition: A causal model is a 3-tuple
M = V,U,F with a mutilation operator do(x): M Mx where: (i) V = {V1…,Vn} endogenous variables, (ii) U = {U1,…,Um} background variables (iii) F = set of n functions, fi : V \ Vi  U  Vi vi = fi(pai,ui) PAi  V \ Vi Ui  U (iv) Mx= U,V,Fx, X  V, x  X where Fx = {fi: Vi  X }  {X = x} (Replace all functions fi corresponding to X with the constant functions X=x) Definition (Probabilistic Causal Model): M, P(u) P(u) is a probability assignment to the variables in U.

19 CAUSAL MODELS AND COUNTERFACTUALS
Definition: Potential Response The sentence: “Y would be y (in unit u), had X been x,” denoted Yx(u) = y, is the solution for Y in a mutilated model Mx, with the equations for X replaced by X = x. (“unit-based potential outcome”)

20 CAUSAL MODELS AND COUNTERFACTUALS
Definition: Potential Response The sentence: “Y would be y (in unit u), had X been x,” denoted Yx(u) = y, is the solution for Y in a mutilated model Mx, with the equations for X replaced by X = x. (“unit-based potential outcome”) Joint probabilities of counterfactuals:

21 CAUSAL MODELS AND COUNTERFACTUALS
Definition: Potential Response The sentence: “Y would be y (in unit u), had X been x,” denoted Yx(u) = y, is the solution for Y in a mutilated model Mx, with the equations for X replaced by X = x. (“unit-based potential outcome”) Joint probabilities of counterfactuals: In particular:

22 3-STEPS TO COMPUTING COUNTERFACTUALS Abduction TRUE TRUE U
S5. If the prisoner is dead, he would still be dead if A were not to have shot. DDA Abduction TRUE TRUE U (Court order) C (Captain) Consider now our counterfactual sentence S5: If the prisoner is Dead, he would still be dead if A were not to have shot. D ==> DA The antecedant {A} should still be treated as interventional surgery, but only after we fully account for the evidence given: D. This calls for three steps 1 Abduction: Interpret the past in light of the evidence 2. Action: Bend the course of history (minimally) to account for the hypothetical antecedant (A). 3.Prediction: Project the consequences to the future. A B (Riflemen) D (Prisoner)

23 3-STEPS TO COMPUTING COUNTERFACTUALS Abduction Action Prediction TRUE
S5. If the prisoner is dead, he would still be dead if A were not to have shot. DDA Abduction TRUE U D B C A FALSE TRUE Action TRUE U D B C A FALSE Prediction TRUE U C A B D

24 COMPUTING PROBABILITIES
OF COUNTERFACTUALS P(S5). The prisoner is dead. How likely is it that he would be dead if A were not to have shot. P(DA|D) = ? Abduction TRUE Action U D B C A FALSE P(u|D) Prediction U D B C A FALSE P(u|D) P(DA|D) P(u) U P(u|D) C Suppose we are not entirely ignorant of U, but can assess the degree of belief P(u). The same 3-steps apply to the computation of the counterfactual probability (that the prisoner be dead if A were not to have shot) The only difference is that we now use the evidence to update P(u) into P(u|e), and draw probabilistic instead of logical conclusions. A B D

25 CAUSAL INFERENCE MADE EASY (1985-2000)
Inference with Nonparametric Structural Equations made possible through Graphical Analysis. Mathematical underpinning of counterfactuals through nonparametric structural equations Graphical-Counterfactuals symbiosis

26 IDENTIFIABILITY P(M1) = P(M2) Þ Q(M1) = Q(M2) Definition:
Let Q(M) be any quantity defined on a causal model M, and let A be a set of assumption. Q is identifiable relative to A iff P(M1) = P(M2) Þ Q(M1) = Q(M2) for all M1, M2, that satisfy A.

27 IDENTIFIABILITY P(M1) = P(M2) Þ Q(M1) = Q(M2) Definition:
Let Q(M) be any quantity defined on a causal model M, and let A be a set of assumption. Q is identifiable relative to A iff P(M1) = P(M2) Þ Q(M1) = Q(M2) for all M1, M2, that satisfy A. In other words, Q can be determined uniquely from the probability distribution P(v) of the endogenous variables, V, and assumptions A.

28 IDENTIFIABILITY P(M1) = P(M2) Þ Q(M1) = Q(M2) Definition:
Let Q(M) be any quantity defined on a causal model M, and let A be a set of assumption. Q is identifiable relative to A iff P(M1) = P(M2) Þ Q(M1) = Q(M2) for all M1, M2, that satisfy A. In this talk: A: Assumptions encoded in the diagram Q1: P(y|do(x)) Causal Effect (= P(Yx=y)) Q2: P(Yx =y | x, y) Probability of necessity Q3: Direct Effect

29 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM
OF CAUSAL INFERENCE Causal Markov Theorem: Any distribution generated by Markovian structural model M (recursive, with independent disturbances) can be factorized as Where pai are the (values of) the parents of Vi in the causal diagram associated with M.

30 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM
OF CAUSAL INFERENCE Causal Markov Theorem: Any distribution generated by Markovian structural model M (recursive, with independent disturbances) can be factorized as Where pai are the (values of) the parents of Vi in the causal diagram associated with M. Corollary: (Truncated factorization, Manipulation Theorem) The distribution generated by an intervention do(X=x) (in a Markovian model M) is given by the truncated factorization

31 RAMIFICATIONS OF THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM
U (unobserved) X = x Z Y Smoking Tar in Lungs Cancer X Given P(x,y,z), should we ban smoking? Pre-intervention Post-intervention

32 RAMIFICATIONS OF THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM
U (unobserved) X = x Z Y Smoking Tar in Lungs Cancer X Given P(x,y,z), should we ban smoking? Pre-intervention Post-intervention

33 RAMIFICATIONS OF THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM
U (unobserved) X = x Z Y Smoking Tar in Lungs Cancer X Given P(x,y,z), should we ban smoking? Pre-intervention Post-intervention To compute P(y,z|do(x)), we must eliminate u. (Graphical problem.)

34 THE BACK-DOOR CRITERION
Graphical test of identification P(y | do(x)) is identifiable in G if there is a set Z of variables such that Z d-separates X from Y in Gx. G Gx Z1 Z1 Z2 Z2 Z Z3 Z3 Z4 Z5 Z5 Z4 X Z6 Y X Z6 Y

35 THE BACK-DOOR CRITERION
Graphical test of identification P(y | do(x)) is identifiable in G if there is a set Z of variables such that Z d-separates X from Y in Gx. G Gx Z1 Z1 Z2 Z2 Z Z3 Z3 Z4 Z5 Z5 Z4 X Z6 Y X Z6 Y Moreover, P(y | do(x)) = å P(y | x,z) P(z) (“adjusting” for Z) z

36 RULES OF CAUSAL CALCULUS
Rule 1: Ignoring observations P(y | do{x}, z, w) = P(y | do{x}, w) Rule 2: Action/observation exchange P(y | do{x}, do{z}, w) = P(y | do{x},z,w) Rule 3: Ignoring actions P(y | do{x}, do{z}, w) = P(y | do{x}, w)

37 DERIVATION IN CAUSAL CALCULUS
Genotype (Unobserved) Smoking Tar Cancer P (c | do{s}) = t P (c | do{s}, t) P (t | do{s}) Probability Axioms = t P (c | do{s}, do{t}) P (t | do{s}) Rule 2 = t P (c | do{s}, do{t}) P (t | s) Rule 2 = t P (c | do{t}) P (t | s) Rule 3 = st P (c | do{t}, s) P (s | do{t}) P(t |s) Probability Axioms Rule 2 = st P (c | t, s) P (s | do{t}) P(t |s) = s t P (c | t, s) P (s) P(t |s) Rule 3

38 OUTLINE Modeling: Statistical vs. Causal
Causal models and identifiability Inference to three types of claims: Effects of potential interventions, Claims about attribution (responsibility)

39 DETERMINING THE CAUSES OF EFFECTS (The Attribution Problem)
Your Honor! My client (Mr. A) died BECAUSE he used that drug.

40 DETERMINING THE CAUSES OF EFFECTS (The Attribution Problem)
Your Honor! My client (Mr. A) died BECAUSE he used that drug. Court to decide if it is MORE PROBABLE THAN NOT that A would be alive BUT FOR the drug! P(? | A is dead, took the drug) > 0.50

41 THE PROBLEM Theoretical Problems: What is the meaning of PN(x,y):
“Probability that event y would not have occurred if it were not for event x, given that x and y did in fact occur.”

42 THE PROBLEM Theoretical Problems: What is the meaning of PN(x,y):
“Probability that event y would not have occurred if it were not for event x, given that x and y did in fact occur.” Answer:

43 THE PROBLEM Theoretical Problems: What is the meaning of PN(x,y):
“Probability that event y would not have occurred if it were not for event x, given that x and y did in fact occur.” Under what condition can PN(x,y) be learned from statistical data, i.e., observational, experimental and combined.

44 WHAT IS INFERABLE FROM EXPERIMENTS?
Simple Experiment: Q = P(Yx= y | z) Z nondescendants of X. Compound Experiment: Q = P(YX(z) = y | z) Multi-Stage Experiment: etc…

45 CAN FREQUENCY DATA DECIDE LEGAL RESPONSIBILITY?
Experimental Nonexperimental do(x) do(x) x x Deaths (y) Survivals (y) 1,000 1,000 1,000 1,000 Nonexperimental data: drug usage predicts longer life Experimental data: drug has negligible effect on survival Plaintiff: Mr. A is special. He actually died He used the drug by choice Court to decide (given both data): Is it more probable than not that A would be alive but for the drug?

46 TYPICAL THEOREMS (Tian and Pearl, 2000)
Bounds given combined nonexperimental and experimental data Identifiability under monotonicity (Combined data) corrected Excess-Risk-Ratio

47 SOLUTION TO THE ATTRIBUTION PROBLEM (Cont)
WITH PROBABILITY ONE P(yx | x,y) =1 From population data to individual case Combined data tell more that each study alone

48 OUTLINE Modeling: Statistical vs. Causal
Causal models and identifiability Inference to three types of claims: Effects of potential interventions, Claims about attribution (responsibility) Claims about direct and indirect effects

49 QUESTIONS ADDRESSED What is the semantics of direct and indirect effects? Can we estimate them from data? Experimental data?

50 WHY DECOMPOSE EFFECTS? Direct (or indirect) effect may be more transportable. Indirect effects may be prevented or controlled. Direct (or indirect) effect may be forbidden Pill Pregnancy + + Thrombosis Gender Qualification Hiring

51 TOTAL, DIRECT, AND INDIRECT EFFECTS HAVE SIMPLE SEMANTICS
IN LINEAR MODELS b X Z z = bx + 1 y = ax + cz + 2 a c Y a + bc a bc

52 SEMANTICS BECOMES NONTRIVIAL IN NONLINEAR MODELS
(even when the model is completely specified) X Z z = f (x, 1) y = g (x, z, 2) Y Dependent on z? Void of operational meaning?

53 THE OPERATIONAL MEANING OF
DIRECT EFFECTS X Z z = f (x, 1) y = g (x, z, 2) Y “Natural” Direct Effect of X on Y: The expected change in Y per unit change of X, when we keep Z constant at whatever value it attains before the change. In linear models, NDE = Controlled Direct Effect

54 POLICY IMPLICATIONS (Who cares?) indirect
What is the direct effect of X on Y? The effect of Gender on Hiring if sex discrimination is eliminated. GENDER QUALIFICATION HIRING X Z IGNORE f Y

55 THE OPERATIONAL MEANING OF
INDIRECT EFFECTS X Z z = f (x, 1) y = g (x, z, 2) Y “Natural” Indirect Effect of X on Y: The expected change in Y when we keep X constant, say at x0, and let Z change to whatever value it would have under a unit change in X. In linear models, NIE = TE - DE

56 LEGAL DEFINITIONS TAKE THE NATURAL CONCEPTION
(FORMALIZING DISCRIMINATION) ``The central question in any employment-discrimination case is whether the employer would have taken the same action had the employee been of different race (age, sex, religion, national origin etc.) and everything else had been the same’’ [Carson versus Bethlehem Steel Corp. (70 FEP Cases 921, 7th Cir. (1996))] x = male, x = female y = hire, y = not hire z = applicant’s qualifications NO DIRECT EFFECT

57 SEMANTICS AND IDENTIFICATION OF NESTED COUNTERFACTUALS
Consider the quantity Given M, P(u), Q is well defined Given u, Zx*(u) is the solution for Z in Mx*, call it z is the solution for Y in Mxz Can Q be estimated from data?

58 GRAPHICAL CONDITION FOR EXPERIMENTAL IDENTIFICATION
OF AVERAGE NATURAL DIRECT EFFECTS Theorem: If there exists a set W such that Example:

59 HOW THE PROOF GOES? Proof:
Each factor is identifiable by experimentation.

60 GRAPHICAL CRITERION FOR COUNTERFACTUAL INDEPENDENCE
X Z X Z U1 Y U1 Y U3 U1 X Y U2 Z

61 GRAPHICAL CONDITION FOR NONEXPERIMENTAL IDENTIFICATION
OF AVERAGE NATURAL DIRECT EFFECTS Identification conditions There exists a W such that (Y Z | W)GXZ There exist additional covariates that render all counterfactual terms identifiable.

62 IDENTIFICATION IN MARKOVIAN MODELS Corollary 3:
The average natural direct effect in Markovian models is identifiable from nonexperimental data, and it is given by X Z Y

63 RELATIONS BETWEEN TOTAL, DIRECT, AND INDIRECT EFFECTS
Theorem 5: The total, direct and indirect effects obey The following equality In words, the total effect (on Y) associated with the transition from x* to x is equal to the difference between the direct effect associated with this transition and the indirect effect associated with the reverse transition, from x to x*.

64 GENERAL PATH-SPECIFIC
EFFECTS (Def.) X x* X W Z W Z z* = Zx* (u) Y Y Form a new model, , specific to active subgraph g Definition: g-specific effect Nonidentifiable even in Markovian models

65 ANSWERS TO QUESTIONS Graphical conditions for estimability from
experimental / nonexperimental data. Graphical conditions hold in Markovian models

66 ANSWERS TO QUESTIONS Graphical conditions for estimability from
experimental / nonexperimental data. Graphical conditions hold in Markovian models Useful in answering new type of policy questions involving mechanism blocking instead of variable fixing.

67 THE OVERRIDING THEME Define Q(M) as a counterfactual expression
Determine conditions for the reduction If reduction is feasible, Q is inferable. Demonstrated on three types of queries: Q1: P(y|do(x)) Causal Effect (= P(Yx=y)) Q2: P(Yx = y | x, y) Probability of necessity Q3: Direct Effect

68 OUTLINE Modeling: Statistical vs. Causal
Causal Models and Identifiability Inference to three types of claims: Effects of potential interventions Claims about attribution (responsibility) Claims about direct and indirect effects Actual Causation and Explanation Robustness of Causal Claims

69 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION u In linear systems: y = ax + e
Genetic Factors (unobserved) u In linear systems: y = ax + e a is non-identifiable. a x y Smoking Cancer The effect of smoking on cancer is, in general, non-identifiable (from observational studies).

70 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION Z u b a y x
Price of Cigarettes b Genetic Factors (unobserved) u a y Smoking Cancer Z – Instrumental variable; cov(z,u) = 0 a is identifiable

71 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION Z u b a y x
Genetic Factors (unobserved) Price of Cigarettes u b a y x Smoking Cancer Problem with Instrumental Variables: The model may be wrong!

72 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION Z1 u b a Z2 y x
Genetic Factors (unobserved) Price of Cigarettes u b a Peer Pressure Z2 g y x Smoking Cancer Solution: Invoke several instruments Surprise: a1 = a2 model is likely correct

73 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION Z1 u b a Z2 y x Z3
Genetic Factors (unobserved) Price of Cigarettes u b a Z2 g y x Peer Pressure Z3 Zn Smoking Cancer Anti-smoking Legislation Greater surprise: a1 = a2 = a3….= an = q Claim a = q is highly likely to be correct

74 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION u x a y s Symptoms do not act as instruments
Genetic Factors (unobserved) u x a y s Symptom Smoking Cancer Symptoms do not act as instruments remains non-identifiable Why? Taking a noisy measurement (s) of an observed variable (y) cannot add new information

75 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION Sn u S2 a x S1 y
Symptom S1 S2 Sn Genetic Factors (unobserved) u x a Smoking Cancer Adding many symptoms does not help. remains non-identifiable

76 ROBUSTNESS: MOTIVATION a x y a1 = a2 = …an
Given a parameter a in a general graph a x y Find if a can evoke an equality surprise a1 = a2 = …an associated with several independent estimands of a Formulate: Surprise, over-identification, independence Robustness: The degree to which a is robust to violations of model assumptions

77 ROBUSTNESS: FORMULATION
Bad attempt: Parameter a is robust (over identifies) f1, f2: Two distinct functions if:

78 ROBUSTNESS: FORMULATION ex ey ez x = ex y = bx + ey z = cy + ez b c x
constraint: (b) (c) Ryx = b Rzx = bc Rzy = c y → z irrelvant to derivation of b

79 RELEVANCE: FORMULATION
Definition Let A be an assumption embodied in model M, and p a parameter in M. A is said to be relevant to p if and only if there exists a set of assumptions S in M such that S and A sustain the identification of p but S alone does not sustain such identification. Theorem An assumption A is relevant to p if and only if A is a member of a minimal set of assumptions sufficient for identifying p.

80 ROBUSTNESS: FORMULATION Definition 5 (Degree of over-identification)
A parameter p (of model M) is identified to degree k (read: k-identified) if there are k minimal sets of assumptions each yielding a distinct estimand of p.

81 ROBUSTNESS: FORMULATION x y b z c Minimal assumption sets for c. x y z
G3 G2 G1 Minimal assumption sets for b. x y b z

82 FROM MINIMAL ASSUMPTION SETS TO MAXIMAL EDGE SUPERGRAPHS
FROM PARAMETERS TO CLAIMS Definition A claim C is identified to degree k in model M (graph G), if there are k edge supergraphs of G that permit the identification of C, each yielding a distinct estimand. e.g., Claim: (Total effect) TE(x,z) = q x y z TE(x,z) = Rzx TE(x,z) = Rzx Rzy ·x x y z

83 FROM MINIMAL ASSUMPTION SETS TO MAXIMAL EDGE SUPERGRAPHS
FROM PARAMETERS TO CLAIMS Definition A claim C is identified to degree k in model M (graph G), if there are k edge supergraphs of G that permit the identification of C, each yielding a distinct estimand. e.g., Claim: (Total effect) TE(x,z) = q x y z x z x z y y Nonparametric

84 SUMMARY OF ROBUSTNESS RESULTS
Formal definition to ROBUSTNESS of causal claims: “A claim is robust when it is insensitive to violations of some of the model assumptions relevant to substantiating that claim.” Graphical criteria and algorithms for computing the degree of robustness of a given causal claim.

85 CONCLUSIONS Structural-model semantics enriched
with logic + graphs leads to formal interpretation and practical assessments of wide variety of causal and counterfactual relationships.


Download ppt "Department of Computer Science"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google