Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Logic, Infinite Computation, and Coinduction

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Logic, Infinite Computation, and Coinduction"— Presentation transcript:

1 Logic, Infinite Computation, and Coinduction
Gopal Gupta Neda Saeedloei, Brian DeVries, Kyle Marple Feliks Kluzniak, Luke Simon, Ajay Bansal, Ajay Mallya, Richard Min Applied Logic, Programming-Languages and Systems (ALPS) Lab The University of Texas at Dallas

2 Circular Phenomena in Comp. Sci.
Circularity has dogged Mathematics and Computer Science ever since Set Theory was first developed: The well known Russell’s Paradox: R = { x | x is a set that does not contain itself} Is R contained in R? Yes and No Liar Paradox: I am a liar Hypergame paradox (Zwicker & Smullyan) All these paradoxes involve self-reference through some type of negation Russell put the blame squarely on circularity and sought to ban it from scientific discourse: ``Whatever involves all of the collection must not be one of the collection” -- Russell 1908

3 Circularity in Computer Science
Following Russell’s lead, Tarski proposed to ban self-referential sentences in a language Rather, have a hierarchy of languages Kripke’s paper challenged this in a1975 paper: argued that circular phenomenon are far more common and circularity can’t simply be banned. Circularity has been banned from automated theorem proving and logic programming through the occurs check rule: An unbound variable cannot be unified with a term containing that variable (i.e., X = f(X) not allowed) What if we allowed such unification to proceed (as LP systems always did for efficiency reasons)?

4 Circularity in Computer Science
If occurs check is removed, we’ll generate circular (infinite) structures: X = [1,2,3 | X] X = f(X) Such structures, of course, arise in computing (circular linked lists), but banned in logic/LP. Subsequent LP systems did allow for such circular structures (rational terms), but they only exist as data-structures, there is no proof theory to go along with it. One can hold the data-structure in memory within an LP execution, but one can’t reason about it.

5 Circularity in Everyday Life
Circularity arises in every day life Most natural phenomenon are cyclical Cyclical movement of the earth, moon, etc. Our digestive system works in cycles Social interactions are cyclical: Conversation = (1st speaker, (2nd Speaker, Conversation) Shared conventions are cyclical concepts Numerous other examples can be found elsewhere (Barwise & Moss 1996)

6 Circularity in Computer Science
Circular phenomenon are quite common in Computer Science: Circular linked lists Graphs (with cycles) Controllers (run forever) Bisimilarity Interactive systems Automata over infinite strings/Kripke structures Perpetual processes Logic/LP not equipped to model circularity directly

7 Coinduction Circular structures are infinite structures
X = [1, 2 | X] is logically speaking X = [1, 2, 1, 2, ….] Proofs about their properties are infinite-sized Coinduction is the technique for proving these properties first proposed by Peter Aczel in the 80s Systematic presentation of coinduction & its application to computing, math. and set theory: “Vicious Circles” by Moss and Barwise (1996) Our focus: inclusion of coinductive reasoning techniques in LP and theorem proving

8 Induction vs Coinduction
Induction is a mathematical technique for finitely reasoning about an infinite (countable) no. of things. Examples of inductive structures: Naturals: 0, 1, 2, … Lists: [ ], [X], [X, X], [X, X, X], … 3 components of an inductive definition: (1) Initiality, (2) iteration, (3) minimality for example, the set of lists is specified as follows: [ ] – an empty list is a list (initiality) ……(i) [H | T] is a list if T is a list and H is an element (iteration) ..(ii) minimal set that satisfies (i) and (ii) (minimality)

9 Induction vs Coinduction
Coinduction is a mathematical technique for (finitely) reasoning about infinite things. Mathematical dual of induction If all things were finite, then coinduction would not be needed. Perpetual programs, automata over infinite strings 2 components of a coinductive definition: (1) iteration, (2) maximality for example, for a list: [ H | T ] is a list if T is a list and H is an element (iteration). Maximal set that satisfies the specification of a list. This coinductive interpretation specifies all infinite sized lists

10 Example: Natural Numbers
 (S) = { 0 }  { succ(x) | x  S } N =  where  is least fixed-point. aka “inductive definition” Let N be the smallest set such that 0  N x  N implies x + 1  N Induction corresponds to Least Fix Point (LFP) interpretation.

11 Example: Natural Numbers and Infinity
 (S) = { 0 }  { succ(x) | x  S }  unambiguously defines another set N’ =  = N  {  }  = succ( succ( succ( ... ) ) ) = succ(  ) =  + 1 where  is a greatest fixed-point Coinduction corresponds to Greatest Fixed Point (GFP) interpretation.

12 Mathematical Foundations
Duality provides a source of new mathematical tools that reflect the sophistication of tried and true techniques. Definition Proof tech. Mapping Least fixed point Induction Recursion Greatest fixed point Coinduction Corecursion Co-recursion: recursive def’n without a base case

13 Applications of Coinduction
model checking bisimilarity proofs lazy evaluation in FP reasoning with infinite structures perpetual processes cyclic structures operational semantics of “coinductive logic programming” Type inference systems for lazy functional languages

14 Inductive Logic Programming
is actually inductive logic programming. has inductive definition. useful for writing programs for reasoning about finite things: - data structures - properties

15 Infinite Objects and Properties
Traditional logic programming is unable to reason about infinite objects and/or properties. (The glass is only half-full) Example: perpetual binary streams traditional logic programming cannot handle bit(0). bit(1). bitstream( [ H | T ] ) :- bit( H ), bitstream( T ). |?- X = [ 0, 1, 1, 0 | X ], bitstream( X ). Goal: Combine traditional LP with coinductive LP

16 Overview of Coinductive LP
Coinductive Logic Program is a definite program with maximal co-Herbrand model declarative semantics. Declarative Semantics: across the board dual of traditional LP: greatest fixed-points terms: co-Herbrand universe Uco(P) atoms: co-Herbrand base Bco(P) program semantics: maximal co-Herbrand model Mco(P).

17 Operational Semantics: co-SLD Resolution
nondeterministic state transition system states are pairs of a finite list of syntactic atoms [resolvent] (as in Prolog) a set of syntactic term equations of the form x = f(x) or x = t For a program p :- p. => the query |?- p. will succeed. p( [ 1 | T ] ) :- p( T ). => |?- p(X) to succeed with X= [ 1 | X ]. transition rules definite clause rule “coinductive hypothesis rule” if a coinductive goal G is called, and G unifies with a call made earlier then G succeeds. ?-G …. G coinductive success

18 Correctness Theorem (soundness). If atom A has a successful co-SLD derivation in program P, then E(A) is true in program P, where E is the resulting variable bindings for the derivation. Theorem (completeness). If A  Mco(P) has a rational proof, then A has a successful co-SLD derivation in program P. Completeness only for rational/regular proofs

19 Implementation Search strategy: hypothesis-first, leftmost, depth-first Meta-Interpreter implementation. query(Goal) :- solve([],Goal). solve(Hypothesis, (Goal1,Goal2)) : solve( Hypothesis, Goal1), solve(Hypothesis,Goal2). solve( _ , Atom) :- builtin(Atom), Atom. solve(Hypothesis,Atom):- member(Atom, Hypothesis). solve(Hypothesis,Atom):- notbuiltin(Atom), clause(Atom,Atoms), solve([Atom|Hypothesis],Atoms). A complete meta-interpreter available Implementation on top of YAP, SWI Prolog available Implementation within Logtalk + library of examples

20 Example: Number Stream
:- coinductive stream/1. stream( [ H | T ] ) :- num( H ), stream( T ). num( 0 ). num( s( N ) ) :- num( N ). |?- stream( [ 0, s( 0 ), s( s ( 0 ) ) | T ] ). MEMO: stream( [ 0, s( 0 ), s( s ( 0 ) ) | T ] ) MEMO: stream( [ s( 0 ), s( s ( 0 ) ) | T ] ) MEMO: stream( [ s( s ( 0 ) ) | T ] ) stream(T) Answers: T = [ 0, s(0), s(s(0)) | T ] T = [ 0, s(0), s(s(0)), s(0), s(s(0)) | T ] T = [ 0, s(0), s(s(0)) | T ] T = [ 0, s(0), s(s(0)) | X ] (where X is any rational list of numbers.)

21 Example: Append :- coinductive append/3. append( [ ], X, X ).
append( [ H | T ], Y, [ H | Z ] ) :- append( T, Y, Z ). |?- Y = [ 4, 5, 6 | Y ], append( [ 1, 2, 3 ], Y, Z). Answer: Z = [ 1, 2, 3 | Y ], Y=[ 4, 5, 6 | Y] |?- X = [ 1, 2, 3 | X ], Y = [ 3, 4 | Y ], append( X, Y, Z). Answer: Z = [ 1, 2, 3 | Z ]. |?- Z = [ 1, 2 | Z ], append( X, Y, Z ). Answer: X = [ ], Y = [ 1, 2 | Z ] ; X = [1, 2 | X], Y = _ X = [ 1 ], Y = [ 2 | Z ] ; X = [ 1, 2 ], Y = Z; …. ad infinitum

22 Example: Comember member(H, [ H | T ]).
member(H, [ X | T ]) :- member(H, T). ?- L = [1,2 | L], member(3, L). succeeds. Instead: :- coinductive comember/2. %drop/3 is inductive comember(X, L) :- drop(X, L, R), comember(X, R). drop(H, [ H | T ], T). drop(H, [ X | T ], T1) :- drop(H, T, T1). ?- X=[ 1, 2, 3 | X ], comember(2,X) ?- X = [1,2 | X], comember(3, X). Answer: yes Answer: no ?- X=[ 1, 2, 3, 1, 2, 3], comember(2, X). Answer: no. ?- X=[1, 2, 3 | X], comember(Y, X). Answer: Y = 1; Y = 2; Y = 3;

23 Co-Logic Programming combines both halves of logic programming:
traditional logic programming coinductive logic programming syntactically identical to traditional logic programming, except predicates are labeled: Inductive, or coinductive and stratification restriction enforced where: inductive and coinductive predicates cannot be mutually recursive. e.g., p :- q. q :- p. Program rejected, if p coinductive & q inductive

24 Application of Co-LP Co-LP allows one to compute both LFP & GFP
Computable functions can be specified more elegantly Interepreters for Modal Logics can be elegantly specified: Model Checking: LTL interpreter elegantly specified Timed -automata: elegantly modeled and properties verified Modeling/Verification of Cyber Physical Systems/Hybrid automata Goal-directed execution of Answer Set Programs Goal-directed SAT solvers (Davis-Putnam like procedure) Planning under real-time constraints Operational semantics of the π-calculus (incl. timed π -calculus) infinite replication operator modeled with co-induction Co-LP allows systems to be modeled naturally & elegantly

25 Application: Model Checking
automated verification of hardware and software systems -automata accept infinite strings accepting state must be traversed infinitely often requires computation of lfp and gfp co-logic programming provides an elegant framework for model checking traditional LP works for safety property (that is based on lfp) in an elegant manner, but not for liveness .

26 Verification of Properties
Types of properties: safety and liveness Search for counter-example

27 Safety versus Liveness
“nothing bad will happen” naturally described inductively straightforward encoding in traditional LP liveness “something good will eventually happen” dual of safety naturally described coinductively straightforward encoding in coinductive LP

28 Finite Automata automata([X|T], St):- trans(St, X, NewSt), automata(T, NewSt). automata([ ], St) :- final(St). trans(s0, a, s1). trans(s1, b, s2) trans(s2, c, s3). trans(s3, d, s0). trans(s2, 3, s0) final(s2). ?- automata(X,s0). X=[ a, b]; X=[ a, b, e, a, b]; X=[ a, b, e, a, b, e, a, b]; ……

29 Infinite Automata automata([X|T], St):- trans(St, X, NewSt), automata(T, NewSt). trans(s0,a,s1). trans(s1,b,s2) trans(s2,c,s3). trans(s3,d,s0). trans(s2,3,s0) final(s2). ?- automata(X,s0). X=[ a, b, c, d | X ]; X=[ a, b, e | X ];

30 Verifying Liveness Properties
Verifying safety properties in LP is relatively easy: safety modeled by reachability Accomplished via tabled logic programming Verifying liveness is much harder: a counterexample to liveness is an infinite trace Verifying liveness is transformed into a safety check via use of negations in model checking and tabled LP Considerable overhead incurred Co-LP solves the problem more elegantly: Infinite traces that serve as counter-examples are produced as answers

31 Verifying Liveness Properties
Consider Safety: Question: Is an unsafe state, Su, reachable? If answer is yes, the path to Su is the counter-ex. Consider Liveness, then dually Question: Is a state, D, that should be dead, live? If answer is yes, the infinite path containing D is the counter example Co-LP will produce this infinite path as the answer Checking for liveness is just as easy as checking for safety

32 Nested Finite and Infinite Automata
:- coinductive state/2. state(s0, [s0,s1 | T]):- enter, work, state(s1,T). state(s1, [s1 | T]):- exit, state(s2,T). state(s2, [s2 | T]):- repeat, state(s0,T). state(s0, [s0 | T]):- error, state(s3,T). state(s3, [s3 | T]):- repeat, state(s0,T). work enter. repeat. exit. error. work :- work. |?- state(s0,X), absent(s2,X). X=[ s0, s3 | X ]

33 An Interpreter for LTL %--- nots have been pushed to propositions
:- tabled verify/2. verify(S, [S], A) :- proposition(A), holds(S,A) % p verify(S, [S], not(A)) :- proposition(A), \+holds(S,A) % not(p) verify(S,P, or(A,B)) :- verify(S, P, A) ; verify(S, P, B). %A or B verify(S,P, and(A,B)) :- verify(S,P1, A), verify(S,P2, B). %A and B (prefix(P2, P1), P=P1 ; prefix(P2,P1), P=P2) verify(S, [S|P], x(A)) :- trans(S, S1), verify(S1, P, A). % X(A) verify(S, P, f(A)) :- verify(S, P, A); verify(S, P, x(f(A))). % F(A) verify(S, P, g(A)) :- coverify(S, P, g(A)) % G(A) verify(S, P,u(A,B)) :- verify(S, P,B); verify(S, P,and(A, x(u(A,B)))) % A u B verify(S, r(A,B)) :- coverify(S, r(A,B)) % A r B :- coinductive coverify/2. coverify(S, g(A)) :- verify(S, P, and(A, x(g(A))). coverify(S, r(A,B)) :- verify(S, P, and(A,B)). coverify(S, r(A,B)) :- verify(S, P, and(B, x(r(A,B)))).

34 Verification of Real-Time Systems “Train, Controller, Gate”
Timed Automata -automata w/ time constrained transitions & stopwatches straightforward encoding into CLP(R) + Co-LP

35 Verification of Real-Time Systems “Train, Controller, Gate”
:- use_module(library(clpr)). :- coinductive driver/9. train(X, up, X, T1,T2,T2) % up=idle train(s0,approach,s1,T1,T2,T3) :- {T3=T1}. train(s1,in,s2,T1,T2,T3):-{T1-T2>2,T3=T2} train(s2,out,s3,T1,T2,T2). train(s3,exit,s0,T1,T2,T3):-{T3=T2,T1-T2<5}. train(X,lower,X,T1,T2,T2). train(X,down,X,T1,T2,T2). train(X,raise,X,T1,T2,T2).

36 Verification of Real-Time Systems “Train, Controller, Gate”
contr(s0,approach,s1,T1,T2,T1). contr(s1,lower,s2,T1,T2,T3):- {T3=T2, T1-T2=1}. contr(s2,exit,s3,T1,T2,T1). contr(s3,raise,s0,T1,T2,T2):-{T1-T2<1}. contr(X,in,X,T1,T2,T2). contr(X,up,X,T1,T2,T2). contr(X,out,X,T1,T2,T2). contr(X,down,X,T1,T2,T2).

37 Verification of Real-Time Systems “Train, Controller, Gate”
gate(s0,lower,s1,T1,T2,T3):- {T3=T1}. gate(s1,down,s2,T1,T2,T3):- {T3=T2,T1-T2<1}. gate(s2,raise,s3,T1,T2,T3):- {T3=T1}. gate(s3,up,s0,T1,T2,T3):- {T3=T2,T1-T2>1,T1-T2<2 }. gate(X,approach,X,T1,T2,T2). gate(X,in,X,T1,T2,T2). gate(X,out,X,T1,T2,T2). gate(X,exit,X,T1,T2,T2).

38 Verification of Real-Time Systems
:- coinductive driver/9. driver(S0,S1,S2, T,T0,T1,T2, [ X | Rest ], [ (X,T) | R ]) :- train(S0,X,S00,T,T0,T00), contr(S1,X,S10,T,T1,T10), gate(S2,X,S20,T,T2,T20), {TA > T}, driver(S00,S10,S20,TA,T00,T10,T20,Rest,R). |?- driver(s0,s0,s0,T,Ta,Tb,Tc,X,R). R=[(approach,A), (lower,B), (down,C), (in,D), (out,E), (exit,F), (raise,G), (up,H) | R ], X=[approach, lower, down, in, out, exit, raise, up | X] ; R=[(approach,A),(lower,B),(down,C),(in,D),(out,E),(exit,F),(raise,G), (approach,H),(up,I)|R], X=[approach,lower,down,in,out,exit,raise,approach,up | X] ; % where A, B, C, ... H, I are the corresponding wall clock time of events generated.

39 DPP – Safety: Deadlock Free
:- table reach/2. reach(Si, Sf) :- trans(_,Si,Sf). reach(Si, Sf) :- trans(_,Si,Sfi), reach(Sfi,Sf). ?- reach([1,1,1,1,1], [2,2,2,2,2]). no One potential solution Force one philosopher to pick forks in different order than others Checking for deadlock Bad state is not reachable Implemented using Tabled LP

40 DPP – Liveness: Starvation Free
Phil. waits forever on a fork One potential solution phil. waiting longest gets the access implemented using CLP(R) Checking for starvation once in bad state, is it possible to remain there forever? implemented using co-LP ?- starved(X). no

41 Other Applications Advanced -structures can also be modeled and reasoned about: -PTA and -grammars Non monotonic reasoning: CoLP allows goal-directed execution of Answer Set Programs (ASP) Abductive reasoners can be elegantly implemented Answer sets programming can be extended to predicates ASP can be elegantly extended with constraints: advanced applications such as planning under real-time constraints become possible SAT Solvers can be elegantly written Operational semantics of pi-calculus can be given (infinite replication operator modeled with co-induction)

42 Goal-directed execution of ASP
Answer set programming (ASP) is a popular formalism for non monotonic reasoning Applications in real-world reasoning, planning, etc. Semantics given via lfp of a residual program obtained after “Gelfond-Lifschitz” transform Popular implementations: Smodels, DLV, etc. No goal-directed execution strategy available ASP limited to only finitely groundable programs Co-logic programming solves both these problems. Also provides a goal-directed method to check if a proposition is true in some model of a prop. formula

43 Why Goal-directed ASP? Most of the time, given a theory, we are interested in knowing if a particular goal is true or not. Top down goal-directed execution provides operational semantics (important for usability) Execution more efficient. Tabled LP vs bottom up Deductive Databases Why check the consistency of the whole knowledgebase? Inconsistency in some unrelated part will scuttle the whole system Most practical examples anyway add a constraint to force the answer set to contain a certain goal. E.g. Zebra puzzle: :- not satisfied. Answer sets of non-finitely groundable programs computable & Constraints incorporated in Prolog style.

44 Negation in Co-LP: co-SLDNF Resolution
Given a clause such as p :- q, not p. ?- p. fails coinductively when not p is encountered To incorporate negation in coinductive reasoning, need a negative coinductive hypothesis rule: In the process of establishing not(p), if not(p) is seen again in the resolvent, then not(p) succeeds [co-SLDNF Resolution] Also, not not p reduces to p. Answer set programming makes the “glass completely full” by taking into account failing computations: p :- q, not p. is consistent if p = false and q = false However, this takes away monotonicity: q can be constrained to false, causing q to be withdrawn, if it was established earlier.

45 ASP Consider the following program, A:
p :- not q t r :- t, s. q :- not p s. A has 2 answer sets: {p, r, t, s} & {q, r, t, s}. Now suppose we add the following rule to A: h :- p, not h (falsify p) Only one answer set remains: {q, r, t, s} Gelfond-Lifschitz Method: Given an answer set S, for each p  S, delete all rules whose body contains “not p”; delete all goals of the form “not q” in remaining rules Compute the least fix point, L, of the residual program If S = L, then S is an answer set

46 Goal-directed ASP Consider the following program, A’:
p :- not q t r :- t, s. q :- not p, r s h :- p, not h. Separate into constraint and non-constraint rules: only 1 constraint rule in this case. Execute the query under co-LP, candidate answer sets will be generated. Keep the ones not rejected by the constraints. Suppose the query is ?- q. Execution: q  not p, r  not not q, r  q, r  r  t, s  s  success Ans = {q, r, t, s} Next, we need to check that constraint rules will not reject the generated answer set. (it doesn’t in this case)

47 Goal-directed ASP In general, for the constraint rules of p as head, p1:- B1. p2:- B pn :- Bn., generate rule(s) of the form: chk_p1 :- not(p1), B1. chk_p2 :- not(p2), B2. ... chk_pn :- not(p), Bn. Generate: nmr_chk :- not(chk_p1), ... , not(chk_pn). For each pred. definition, generate its negative version: not_p :- not(B1), not(B2), ... , not(Bn). If you want to ask query Q, then ask ?- Q, nmr_chk. Execution keeps track of atoms in the answer set (PCHS) and atoms not in the answer set (NCHS).

48 Goal-directed ASP Consider the following program, P1:
(i) p :- not q (ii) q:- not r (iii) r :- not p. (iv) q :- not p. P1 has 1 answer set: {q, r}. Separate into: 3 constraint rules (i, ii, iii) 2 non-constraint rules (i, iv). p :- not(q). q :- not(r). r :- not(p). q :- not(p). chk_p :- not(p), not(q). chk_q :- not(q), not(r). chk_r :- not(r), not(p). nmr_chk :- not(chk_p), not(chk_q), not(chk_r). not_p :- q. not_q :- r, p. not_r :- p. Suppose the query is ?- r. Expand as in co-LP: r  not p  not not q  q (  not r  fail, backtrack)  not p  success. Ans={r, q} which satisfies the constraint rules of nmr_chk.

49 Benchmark Results Top-Down Avg. (s) Smodels Avg. (s)
Smodels / Top-Down 13 Queens 0.0050 0.0185 3.70 15 Queens 0.0120 0.0760 6.33 19 Queens 0.0235 1.4820 63.06 20 Queens 0.8590 5.3015 6.17 21 Queens 0.0560 352.79 22 Queens 7.9100 79.50 10.05 23 Queens 0.1400 24 Queens 2.0500 49.39 8x7 Pigeons 0.0260 0.1515 5.83 11x10 Pigeons 6.22 10x10 Pigeons 0.0025 0.0055 2.20 20x20 Pigeons 0.0100 0.0790 7.90 30x30 Pigeons 0.0310 0.5155 16.63 40x40 Pigeons 0.0700 2.4340 34.77

50 Cyber-Physical Systems (CPS)
-- Networked/distributed Hybrid Systems -- Discrete digital systems with Inputs: continuous physical quantities e.g., time, distance, acceleration, temperature, etc. Outputs: control physical (analog) devices Elegantly modeled via co-LP extended with constraints Characteristics of CPS: -- perform discrete computations (modeled via LP) -- deal with continuous physical quantities (modeled via constraints) -- are concurrent (modeled via LP coroutining) -- run forever (modeled via coinduction) 50

51 CPS Example Reactor Temperature Control System θ = θm θ = θM θ = θM
r1 >= W rod1 no_rod rod2 add1 , c1 := 0 add2 , c2 := 0 θ = ― - 60 10 θ . r1 = W add1 θ = ― - 56 10 θ . θ = ― - 50 10 θ . out1 in1 r1 := 0 θ = θm θ = θm θm <= θ θ <= θM θm <= θ remove1 remove2 , c2 := 0 remove1 , c1 := 0 θ = θM r2 >= W r2 = W add2 out2 in2 r2 := 0 shutdown remove2

52 Rod1 & Rod2 trans_r1(out1, add1, in1, T, Ti, To, W) :- {T – Ti >= W, To = Ti}. trans_r1(in1, remove1, out1, T, Ti, To, W) :- {To = T}. trans_r2(out2, add2, in2, T, Ti, To, W) :- trans_r2(in2, remove2, out2, T, Ti, To, W) :- {To = T}. in1 r1 >= W add1 r1 := 0 remove1 out1 r1 = W in2 r2 >= W add2 r2 := 0 remove2 out2 r2 = W

53 Controller trans_c(norod, add1, rod1, Tetai, Tetao, T, Ti1, Ti2, To1, To2, F) :- (F == 1 -> Ti = Ti1; Ti = Ti2), {Tetai < 550, Tetao = 550, exp(e, (T - Ti)/10) = 5, To1 = T, To2 = Ti2}. trans_c(rod1, remove1, norod Tetai, Tetao, T, Ti1, Ti2, To1, To2, F) :- {Tetai > 510 Tetao = 510, exp(e, (T - Ti1)/10) = 5, trans_c(norod, add2, rod2, Tetai, Tetao, T, Ti1, Ti2, To1, To2, F) :- To1 = Ti1, To2 = T}. trans_c(rod2, remove2, norod, Tetai, Tetao, T, Ti1, Ti2, To1, To2, F) :- {Tetai > 510, Tetao = 510, exp(e, (T - Ti2)/10) = 9/5, trans_c(norod, _, shutdown, Tetai, Tetao, T, Ti1, Ti2, To1, To2, F) :- {Tetai < 550 Tetao = 550, exp(e, (T - Ti)/10) = 5, To1 = Ti1, To2 = Ti2}. no_rod θ <= θM θ = ― - 50 10 θ . θ = ― - 56 θ = ― - 60 rod2 rod1 θm <= θ θ = θM add1 , c1 := 0 add2 , c2 := 0 θ = θm remove1 , c1 := 0 remove2 , c2 := 0 shutdown

54 Controller | Rod1 | Rod2 :- coinductive(contr/7).
contr(X, Si, T, Tetai, Ti1, Ti2, Fi) :- (H = add1; H = remove1; H = add2; H = remove2; H = shutdown), {Ta > T}, freeze(X, contr(Xs, So, Ta, Tetao, To1, To2, Fo)), trans_c(Si, H, So, Tetai, Tetao, T, Ti1, Ti2, To1, To2, Fi), ((H=add1; H=remove1) -> Fo = 1; Fo = 2), ((H=add1; H=remove1; H=add2; H=remove2) -> X = [ (H, T) | Xs]; X = [ (H, T) ] ). :- coinductive(rod1/6). rod1([ (H, T)| Xs], Si1, Si2, Ti1, Ti2, W) :- H = add1 -> freeze(Xs,rod1(Xs, So1, Si2, To1, Ti2, W)); H = remove1 -> freeze(Xs,rod1(Xs, So1, Si2, To1, Ti2, W); rod2(Xs, So1, Si2, To1, Ti2, W)), trans_r1(Si1, H, So1, T, Ti1, To1, W); H = shutdown -> {T - Ti1 < A, T - Ti2 < A}. :- coinductive(rod2/6). rod2([ (H, T)| Xs], Si1, Si2, Ti1, Ti2, W) :- H = add2 -> freeze(Xs,rod2(Xs, Si1, So2, Ti1, To2, W)); H = remove2 -> freeze(Xs,rod1(Xs, Si1, So2, Ti1, To2, W); rod2(Xs, Si1, So2, Ti1, To2, W)), trans_r2(Si2, H, So2, T, Ti2, To2, W); H = shutdown -> {T - Ti1 < A, T - Ti2 < A}.

55 Controller || Rod1 || Rod2
main(S, T, W) :- {T - Tr1 = W, T - Tr2 = W}, freeze(S, (rod1(S, s0, s0, Tr1, Tr2, W); rod2(S, s0, s0, Tr1, Tr2, W))), contr(S, s0, T, 510, Tc1, Tc2, 1). With this elegant modeling, we were able to improve the bounds on W compared to previous work HyTech determines W < to prevent shutdown Subsequently, using linear hybrid automata with clock translation, HyTech improves to W < 37.8 Using our LP method, we refine it to W < 38.06

56 Related Publications L. Simon, A. Mallya, A. Bansal, and G. Gupta. Coinductive logic programming. In ICLP’06 . L. Simon, A. Bansal, A. Mallya, and G. Gupta. Co-Logic programming: Extending logic programming with coinduction. In ICALP’07. G. Gupta et al. Co-LP and its applications, ICLP’07 (tutorial) G. Gupta et al. Infinite computation, coinduction and computational logic. CALCO’11 R. Min, A. Bansal, G. Gupta. Co-LP with negation, LOPSTR 2009 R. Min, G. Gupta. Towards Predicate ASP, AIAI’09 N. Saeedloei, G. Gupta. Coinductive Constraint Programming FLOPS12. N. Saeedloei, G. Gupta, Timed π-Calculus N. Saeedloei, G. Gupta. Modeling/verification of CPS with coinductive coroutined CLP(R) K. Marple, A. Bansal, R. Min, G. Gupta. Goal-directed Execution of ASP. PPDP’12 K. Marple, G. Gupta, Galliwasp: A Goal-Directed Answer Set Solver . LOPSTR 2012

57 Conclusion Circularity is a common concept in everyday life and computer science: Logic/LP is unable to cope with circularity Solution: introduce coinduction in Logic/LP dual of traditional logic programming operational semantics for coinduction combining both halves of logic programming applications to verification, non monotonic reasoning, negation in LP, propositional satisfiability, hybrid systems, cyberphysical systems Goal-directed impl. of non-monotonic reasoning avail. Metainterpreter available:

58 Conclusion (cont’d) Computation can be classified into two types:
Well-founded, Based on computing elements in the LFP Implemented w/ recursion (start from a call, end in base case) Consistency-based Based on computing elements in the GFP (but not LFP) Implemented via co-recursion (look for consistency) Combining the two allows one to compute any computable function elegantly: Implementations of modal logics (LTL, etc.) Complex reasoning systems (NM reasoners) Combining them is challenging

59 LFP vs GFP COMPUTATION G L F P F P

60 LFP vs GFP COMPUTATION G F P L F P

61 Conclusions: Future Work
Design execution strategies that enumerate all rational infinite solutions while avoiding redundant solutions p([a|X]) :- p(X). p([b|X]) :- p(X). -- If X = [a|X] is reported, then avoid X = [a, a | X], X = [a,a,a|X], etc. -- A fair depth first search strategy that will produce X = [a,b|X] Combining induction (tabling) and co-induction: Stratified co-LP: equivalent to stratified Büchi tree automata (SBTAs) Non-stratified co-LP: inspired by Rabin automata; 3 class of predicates (i) coinductive, (ii) weakly coinductive and (iii) strongly coinductive

62 QUESTIONS?

63 Coinductive LP: An Example
Let P1 be the following coinductive program. :- coinductive from/ from(x) = x cons from(x+1) from( N, [ N | T ] ) :- from( s(N), T ). |?- from( 0, X ). co-Herbrand Universe: Uco(P1) = N    L where N=[0, s(0), s(s(0)), ... ], ={ s(s(s( ) ) ) }, and L is the the set of all finite and infinite lists of elements in N,  and L. co-Herbrand Model: Mco(P1)={ from(t, [t, s(t), s(s(t)), ... ]) | t  Uco(P1) } from(0, [0, s(0), s(s(0)), ... ])  Mco(P1) implies the query holds Without “coinductive” declaration of from, Mco(P1’)= This corresponds to traditional semantics of LP with infinite trees.


Download ppt "Logic, Infinite Computation, and Coinduction"

Similar presentations


Ads by Google