Module #1 - Logic Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c)2001-2004, Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 1 Module.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Discrete Mathematics University of Jazeera College of Information Technology & Design Khulood Ghazal Mathematical Reasoning Methods of Proof.
Advertisements

Discrete Math Methods of proof 1.
Introduction to Proofs
Announcements Grading policy No Quiz next week Midterm next week (Th. May 13). The correct answer to the quiz.
1 Section 1.5 Rules of Inference. 2 Definitions Theorem: a statement that can be shown to be true Proof: demonstration of truth of theorem –consists of.
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
February 26, 2015Applied Discrete Mathematics Week 5: Mathematical Reasoning 1 Addition of Integers Example: Add a = (1110) 2 and b = (1011) 2. a 0 + b.
CSE115/ENGR160 Discrete Mathematics 01/26/12 Ming-Hsuan Yang UC Merced 1.
Valid Arguments An argument is a sequence of propositions. All but the final proposition are called premises. The last statement is the conclusion. The.
2009/91 Methods of Proof (§1.7) Methods of mathematical argument (proof methods) can be formalized in terms of rules of logical inference. Mathematical.
Discrete Structures & Algorithms Propositional Logic EECE 320 : UBC : Spring
CSE115/ENGR160 Discrete Mathematics 01/31/12 Ming-Hsuan Yang UC Merced 1.
So far we have learned about:
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications
Fall 2002CMSC Discrete Structures1 Let’s proceed to… Mathematical Reasoning.
1 Basic Proof Methods Rosen 6 th ed., § Nature & Importance of Proofs In mathematics, a proof is:In mathematics, a proof is: –A sequence of.
CSI 2101 / Rules of Inference (§1.5)
Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications, 5e Prepared by (c) Michael P. Frank Modified by (c) Haluk Bingöl 1/18 Module.
Methods of Proof & Proof Strategies
February 25, 2002Applied Discrete Mathematics Week 5: Mathematical Reasoning 1 Addition of Integers How do we (humans) add two integers? Example: 7583.
Introduction to Proofs
1 Georgia Tech, IIC, GVU, 2006 MAGIC Lab Rossignac Lecture 03: PROOFS Section 1.5 Jarek Rossignac CS1050: Understanding.
CS 103 Discrete Structures Lecture 07b
Proofs1 Elementary Discrete Mathematics Jim Skon.
1 Basic Proof Methods I Basic Proof Methods II Proofs Involving Quantifiers.
1 Methods of Proof. 2 Consider (p  (p→q)) → q pqp→q p  (p→q)) (p  (p→q)) → q TTTTT TFFFT FTTFT FFTFT.
10/17/2015 Prepared by Dr.Saad Alabbad1 CS100 : Discrete Structures Proof Techniques(1) Dr.Saad Alabbad Department of Computer Science
1 Sections 1.5 & 3.1 Methods of Proof / Proof Strategy.
Discrete Structures (DS)
Fallacies The proposition [(p  q)  q]  p is not a tautology, because it is false when p is false and q is true. This type of incorrect reasoning is.
Chap 3 –A theorem is a statement that can be shown to be true –A proof is a sequence of statements to show that a theorem is true –Axioms: statements which.
Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications, 5e Prepared by (c) Michael P. Frank Modified by (c) Haluk Bingöl 1/18 Module.
Fall 2008/2009 I. Arwa Linjawi & I. Asma’a Ashenkity 11 The Foundations: Logic and Proofs Introduction to Proofs.
1 Discrete Structures – CNS2300 Text Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications Kenneth H. Rosen (5 th Edition) Chapter 3 The Foundations: Logic and Proof,
CS2013 Mathematics for Computing Science Adam Wyner University of Aberdeen Computing Science Slides adapted from Michael P. Frank ' s course based on the.
資訊科學數學 7 : Proof, Number and Orders 陳光琦助理教授 (Kuang-Chi Chen)
Rules of Inference Section 1.6. Arguments in Propositional Logic A argument in propositional logic is a sequence of propositions. All but the final proposition.
Today’s topics Proof techniques Reading: Section 1.5 Upcoming
Fall 2008/2009 I. Arwa Linjawi & I. Asma’a Ashenkity 11 The Foundations: Logic and Proofs Rules of inference.
CSci 2011 Discrete Mathematics Lecture 4 CSci 2011.
CS104:Discrete Structures Chapter 2: Proof Techniques.
Foundations of Discrete Mathematics Chapter 1 By Dr. Dalia M. Gil, Ph.D.
CSci 2011 Discrete Mathematics Lecture 5 CSci 2011.
Chapter 1, Part III: Proofs With Question/Answer Animations Copyright © McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without.
Section 1.7. Section Summary Mathematical Proofs Forms of Theorems Direct Proofs Indirect Proofs Proof of the Contrapositive Proof by Contradiction.
Nature & Importance of Proofs In mathematics, a proof is: –a correct (well-reasoned, logically valid) and complete (clear, detailed) argument that rigorously.
Chapter 1 Logic and proofs
CSE15 Discrete Mathematics 02/01/17
Applied Discrete Mathematics Week 5: Mathematical Reasoning
CSE15 Discrete Mathematics 01/30/17
Proof Techniques.
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications
Module #10: Proof Strategies
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications
Mathematical Reasoning
Methods of Proof. Methods of Proof Definitions A theorem is a valid logical assertion which can be proved using Axioms: statements which are given.
Week #6 – 30 September / 2/4 October 2002 Prof. Marie desJardins
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications
Applied Discrete Mathematics Week 1: Logic
Information Technology Department SKN-SITS,Lonavala.
Module #2: Basic Proof Methods
Module #10: Proof Strategies
September 9, 2004 Prof. Marie desJardins (for Prof. Matt Gaston)
Foundations of Discrete Mathematics
Mathematical Reasoning
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications
Introduction to Proofs
Module #2: Basic Proof Methods
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Presentation transcript:

Module #1 - Logic Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 1 Module 2: Basic Proof Methods

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 2 Nature & Importance of Proofs In mathematics, a proof is: a correct (well-reasoned, logically valid) and complete (clear, detailed) argument that rigorously & undeniably establishes the truth of a mathematical statement. Why must the argument be correct & complete? Correctness prevents us from fooling ourselves. Completeness allows anyone to verify the result. In this course (& throughout mathematics), a very high standard for correctness and completeness of proofs is demanded!!

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 3 Overview Methods of mathematical argument (i.e., proof methods) can be formalized in terms of rules of logical inference. Mathematical proofs can themselves be represented formally as discrete structures. We will review both correct & fallacious inference rules, & several proof methods.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 4 Applications of Proofs An exercise in clear communication of logical arguments in any area of study. The fundamental activity of mathematics is the discovery and elucidation, through proofs, of interesting new theorems. Theorem-proving has applications in program verification, computer security, automated reasoning systems, etc. Proving a theorem allows us to rely upon on its correctness even in the most critical scenarios.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 5 Proof Terminology Theorem A statement that has been proven to be true. Axioms, postulates, hypotheses, premises Assumptions (often unproven) defining the structures about which we are reasoning. Rules of inference Patterns of logically valid deductions from hypotheses to conclusions.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 6 More Proof Terminology Lemma - A minor theorem used as a stepping- stone to proving a major theorem. Corollary - A minor theorem proved as an easy consequence of a major theorem. Conjecture - A statement whose truth value has not been proven. (A conjecture may be widely believed to be true, regardless.) Theory – The set of all theorems that can be proven from a given set of axioms.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 7 Graphical Visualization … Various Theorems The Axioms of the Theory A Particular Theory A proof

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 8 Inference Rules - General Form An Inference Rule is A pattern establishing that if we know that a set of antecedent statements of certain forms are all true, then we can validly deduce that a certain related consequent statement is true. antecedent 1 antecedent 2 …  consequent “  ” means “therefore”

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 9 Inference Rules & Implications Each valid logical inference rule corresponds to an implication that is a tautology. antecedent 1 Inference rule antecedent 2 …  consequent Corresponding tautology: ((ante. 1)  (ante. 2)  …)  consequent

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 10 Some Inference Rules pRule of Addition  p  q p  qRule of Simplification  p pRule of Conjunction q  p  q

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 11 Modus Ponens & Tollens pRule of modus ponens p  q (a.k.a. law of detachment)  q  q p  q Rule of modus tollens  p “the mode of affirming” “the mode of denying”

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 12 Syllogism Inference Rules p  qRule of hypothetical q  rsyllogism  p  r p  qRule of disjunctive  psyllogism  q Aristotle (ca B.C.)

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 13 Formal Proofs A formal proof of a conclusion C, given premises p 1, p 2,…,p n consists of a sequence of steps, each of which applies some inference rule to premises or previously- proven statements (antecedents) to yield a new true statement (the consequent). A proof demonstrates that if the premises are true, then the conclusion is true.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 14 Formal Proof Example Suppose we have the following premises: “It is not sunny and it is cold.” “We will swim only if it is sunny.” “If we do not swim, then we will canoe.” “If we canoe, then we will be home early.” Given these premises, prove the theorem “We will be home early” using inference rules.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 15 Proof Example cont. Let us adopt the following abbreviations: sunny = “It is sunny”; cold = “It is cold”; swim = “We will swim”; canoe = “We will canoe”; early = “We will be home early”. Then, the premises can be written as: (1)  sunny  cold (2) swim  sunny (3)  swim  canoe (4) canoe  early

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 16 Proof Example cont. StepProved by 1.  sunny  cold Premise #1. 2.  sunnySimplification of swim  sunnyPremise #2. 4.  swimModus tollens on 2,3. 5.  swim  canoe Premise #3. 6. canoeModus ponens on 4,5. 7. canoe  earlyPremise #4. 8. earlyModus ponens on 6,7.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 17 Inference Rules for Quantifiers  x P(x)  P(o)(substitute any specific object o) P(g)(for g a general element of u.d.)  x P(x)  x P(x)  P(c)(substitute a new constant c) P(o) (substitute any extant object o)  x P(x)

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 18 Examples on Inference Rules for Quantifiers Ex1: “Everyone in discrete math class has taken a course in computer science” and Marla is a student in this class”. This statement implies the Marla has taken a course in computer science. Ex1: “Everyone in discrete math class has taken a course in computer science” and Marla is a student in this class”. This statement implies the Marla has taken a course in computer science. This is universal instantiation Let D(x) denote “x is in this discrete math class,” and let C(x) denote “x has taken a course in computer science”. Then the premises are  x (D(x)  C(x)) and D(Marla). The conclusion is C(Marla).

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 19 Examples on Inference Rules for Quantifiers (cont.) The following steps can be used to establish the conclusion from the premises. StepReason 1.  x (D(x)  C(x))Premise 2. D(Marla)  C(Marla)universal instantiation from (1) 3. D(Marla) Premise 4. C(Marla)Modus ponens from (2) and (3)

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 20 Examples on Inference Rules for Quantifiers (cont.) Ex2: “A student in this class has not read the book” and “Everyone in this class has passed the first exam” implies the conclusion “Someone who passed the first exam has not read the book.” Ex2: “A student in this class has not read the book” and “Everyone in this class has passed the first exam” implies the conclusion “Someone who passed the first exam has not read the book.” This is existential generalization Let C(x) be “x is in this class”, B(x) be “x has read the book”, and P(x) be “x passed the first exam.” The premises are:  x (C(x)   B(x)) and  x (C(x)  P(x)). The conclusion is  x (P(x)   B(x)).

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 21 Examples on Inference Rules for Quantifiers (cont.) The following steps can be used to establish the conclusion from the premises. StepReason 1.  x (C(x)   B(x)) Premise 2.C(a)   B(a)Existential instantiation from (1) 3.C(a)Simplification from (2) 4.  x (C(x)  P(x))Premise 5.C(a)  P(a)Universal instantiation from (4) 6.P(a)Modus ponens from (3) and (5) 7.  B(a)Simplification from (2) 8.P(a)   B(a)Conjunction from (6) and (7) 9.  x (P(x)   B(x))Existential generalization

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 22 Common Fallacies A fallacy is an inference rule or other proof method that is not logically valid. A fallacy may yield a false conclusion! Fallacy of affirming the conclusion: “p  q is true, and q is true, so p must be true.” (No, because F  T is true.) Ex1: Is the following statement valid? If you do every problem in this book, then you will get an A from this course. Now you got an A, so it means you did every problem in this book. NO

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 23 Common Fallacies (cont.) Fallacy of denying the hypothesis: “p  q is true, and p is false, so q must be false.” (No, again because F  T is true.) Ex2: Is the following statement valid? If you do every problem in this book, then you will get an A from this course. Since you did not all the problems in this book, so you will not get an A from this course. NO

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 24 Circular Reasoning The fallacy of (explicitly or implicitly) assuming the very statement you are trying to prove in the course of its proof. Example: Prove that if n 2 is even, then n is even,. Attempted proof: “Assume n 2 is even. Then n 2 =2k for some integer k. Dividing both sides by n gives n = (2k)/n = 2(k/n). So there is an integer j (namely k/n) such that n=2j. Therefore n is even.” Circular reasoning is used in this proof. Where? Begs the question: How do you show that j=k/n=n/2 is an integer, without first assuming that n is even?

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 25 Proof Methods for Implications For proving implications p  q, we have: Direct proof: Assume p is true, and prove q. Indirect proof: Assume  q, and prove  p.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 26 Direct Proof Example Definition: An integer n is called odd iff n=2k+1 for some integer k; n is even iff n=2k for some k. Axiom: Every integer is either odd or even. Theorem: (For all numbers n) If n is an odd integer, then n 2 is an odd integer. Proof: If n is odd, then n = 2k+1 for some integer k. Thus, n 2 = (2k+1) 2 = 4k 2 + 4k + 1 = 2(2k 2 + 2k) + 1. Therefore n 2 is of the form 2j + 1 (with j the integer 2k 2 + 2k), thus n 2 is odd. □

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 27 Indirect Proof Example Theorem: (For all integers n) If 3n+2 is odd, then n is odd. Proof: Suppose that the conclusion is false, i.e., that n is even. Then n=2k for some integer k. Then 3n+2 = 3(2k)+2 = 6k+2 = 2(3k+1). Thus 3n+2 is even, because it equals 2j for integer j = 3k+1. So 3n+2 is not odd. We have shown that ¬(n is odd)→¬(3n+2 is odd), thus its contra- positive (3n+2 is odd) → (n is odd) is also true. □

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 28 Proof by Contradiction A method for proving p. Assume  p, and prove both q and  q for some proposition q. (Can be anything!) Thus  p  (q   q) (q   q) is a trivial contradiction, equal to F Thus  p  F, which is only true if  p=F Thus p is true.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 29 Proof by Contradiction Example Theorem: is irrational. Proof: Assume 2 1/2 were rational. This means there are integers i,j with no common divisors such that 2 1/2 = i/j. Squaring both sides, 2 = i 2 /j 2, so 2j 2 = i 2. So i 2 is even; thus i is even. Let i=2k. So 2j 2 = (2k) 2 = 4k 2. Dividing both sides by 2, j 2 = 2k 2. Thus j 2 is even, so j is even. But then i and j have a common divisor, namely 2, so we have a contradiction. □

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 30 Proving Existentials A proof of a statement of the form  x P(x) is called an existence proof. If the proof demonstrates how to actually find or construct a specific element a such that P(a) is true, then it is a constructive proof. Otherwise, it is nonconstructive.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 31 Constructive Existence Proof Theorem: There exists a positive integer n that is the sum of two perfect cubes in two different ways: equal to j 3 + k 3 and l 3 + m 3 where j, k, l, m are positive integers, and {j,k} ≠ {l,m} Proof: Consider n = 1729, j = 9, k = 10, l = 1, m = 12. Now just check that the equalities hold.

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 32 Nonconstructive Existence Proof Show that there exist irrational numbers x and y such that x y is rational. Proof:

Based on Rosen, Discrete Mathematics & Its Applications. Prepared by (c) , Michael P. Frank. Modified By Mingwu Chen 33 Review: Proof Methods Direct, indirect proofs of statements of the form p  q. Proof by contradiction of any statements. Constructive and nonconstructive existence proofs.