0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises). 1 1. All dogs have two heads. 2. All tigers are dogs. ___________________________________ 3. All tigers have two.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Deductive Validity In this tutorial you will learn how to determine whether deductive arguments are valid or invalid. Go to next slide.
Advertisements

Formal Criteria for Evaluating Arguments
Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
1 Valid and Invalid arguments. 2 Definition of Argument Sequence of statements: Statement 1; Statement 2; Therefore, Statement 3. Statements 1 and 2 are.
Arguments, validity, soundness, persuasiveness
Welcome to Dave Penner’s Presentation on Inductive Reasoning!
 Assertions: unsupported declaration of a belief  Prejudice: a view without evidence for or against  Premises: explicit evidence that lead to a conclusion.
Logic and Reasoning Panther Prep North Central High School.
Deductive Validity In this tutorial you will learn how to determine whether deductive arguments are valid or invalid. Chapter 3.b.
Other Info on Making Arguments
BUS 290: Critical Thinking for Managers
Deductive and Inductive Arguments. All bats are mammals. All mammals are warm-blooded. So, all bats are warm-blooded. All arguments are deductive or.
Logos Formal Logic.
Deduction and Induction
This is Introductory Logic PHI 120 Get a syllabus online, if you don't already have one Presentation: "Good Arguments"
 Monty Python – Argument Clinic video  Monty Python Monty Python.
Today’s Topics n Review Logical Implication & Truth Table Tests for Validity n Truth Value Analysis n Short Form Validity Tests n Consistency and validity.
Logic. what is an argument? People argue all the time ― that is, they have arguments.  It is not often, however, that in the course of having an argument.
EE1J2 – Discrete Maths Lecture 5 Analysis of arguments (continued) More example proofs Formalisation of arguments in natural language Proof by contradiction.
Logical and Rule-Based Reasoning Part I. Logical Models and Reasoning Big Question: Do people think logically?
Artificial Intelligence Reasoning. Reasoning is the process of deriving logical conclusions from given facts. Durkin defines reasoning as ‘the process.
DEDUCTIVE & INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS
Basic Argumentation.
1.5 Rules of Inference.
Deduction, Induction, & Truth Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.
0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises) December 23, 2005.
1 Chapter 7 Propositional and Predicate Logic. 2 Chapter 7 Contents (1) l What is Logic? l Logical Operators l Translating between English and Logic l.
MA 110: Finite Math Lecture 1/14/2009 Section 1.1 Homework: 5, 9-15, (56 BP)
Deduction, Validity, Soundness Lecture II – 01/25/11.
FALSE PREMISE.
The Science of Good Reasons
Reasoning and Critical Thinking Validity and Soundness 1.
Question of the Day!  We shared a lot of examples of illogical arguments!  But how do you make a LOGICAL argument? What does your argument need? What.
READING #4 “DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS” By Robert FitzGibbons from Making educational decisions: an introduction to Philosophy of Education (New York & London:
Aerospace Engineering Laboratory I
DEDUCTIVE VS. INDUCTIVE REASONING. Problem Solving Logic – The science of correct reasoning. Reasoning – The drawing of inferences or conclusions from.
The construction of a formal argument
What is Reasoning  Logical reasoning is the process of drawing conclusions from premises using rules of inference.  These inference rules are results.
The Ontological Argument for the Existence of God August 15, 2015 George Cronk, J.D., Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy & Religion Bergen Community College.
Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning.
2.3 Methods of Proof.
What is an argument? An argument is, to quote the Monty Python sketch, "a connected series of statements to establish a definite proposition." Huh? Three.
Uniqueness Quantifier ROI for Quantified Statement.
DEDUCTIVE vs. INDUCTIVE REASONING
Valid and Invalid Arguments
What is Inductive Reasoning?
a valid argument with true premises.
WEEK 3 VALIDITY OF ARGUMENTS Valid argument: A deductive argument is valid if its conclusion is necessarily and logically drawn from the premises. The.
FALSE PREMISE.
CAS LX 502 3b. Truth and logic
Deductive and Inductive
Inductive / Deductive reasoning
Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning
Rules and fallacies Formal fallacies.
The Ontological Argument
Validity and Soundness
The Ontological Argument
TRUTH TABLE TO DETERMINE
Distinguish valid from invalid arguments and sound from unsound
Midterm Discussion.
Logic Problems and Questions
The Method of Deduction
Phil2303 intro to logic.
Validity.
Propositional Logic 1) Introduction Copyright 2008, Scott Gray.
ID1050– Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning
Evaluating Deductive Arguments
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Introducing Natural Deduction
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Presentation transcript:

0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises)

1 1. All dogs have two heads. 2. All tigers are dogs. ___________________________________ 3. All tigers have two heads. Valid If all members of the class of dogs are two-headed, and if all members of the class of tigers are also members of the class of dogs, then all members of the class of tigers must be two- headed. 2-Headed Things DogsTigers

2 1. All A is B. 2. All C is B. ___________________ 3. All C is A. Invalid Just because the members of A and the members of C are all members of B does not mean that all members of C are members of A. B AC

3 1. All cats are animals. 2. All tigers are cats. _______________________________ 3. All tigers are animals. Valid If all members of the class of cats are also members of the class of animals (as they are), and if all members of the class of tigers are also members of the class of cats (as they are), then all members of the class of tigers must be members of the class of animals (right?).

4 1. If Polly is a cat, then Polly is an animal. 2. Polly is an animal. ______________________________________________ 3. Polly is a cat. Invalid All cats are animals, but not all animals are cats. It's true that if Polly is a cat, then she is an animal (1st premise). However, the fact that Polly is an animal (2nd premise) does not prove that she is also a cat (conclusion).

5 1. Either it is raining or the sun is shining. 2. It is raining. ______________________________________________ 3. The sun is not shining. Invalid "Either p or q" (which is the logical form of the 1st premise) means "either p is true or q is true, and perhaps they are both true." It could be raining while the sun is shining. Thus, the fact that it is raining (2nd premise) does not rule out the possibility that the sun is shining. The conclusion does not follow necessarily from the premises.

6 1. If it rains, then Mary carries an umbrella. 2. It is raining now. _____________________________________________ 3. Mary is carrying an umbrella. Valid Assuming that Mary carries an umbrella whenever it rains (1st premise), and assuming that it is raining now (2nd premise), it follows necessarily that Mary is carrying an umbrella (conclusion). Do you see that?

7 1. Either John is a lawyer or Mary is a doctor. 2. John is not a lawyer. _______________________________________________ 3. Mary is a doctor. Valid "Either p or q" (the logical form of the 1st premise) means "either p is true or q is true, and perhaps they are both true." In this argument, the 1st premise says that either "John is a lawyer" is true or "Mary is a doctor" is true. One or the other is true, or they are both true, according to the 1st premise. The 2nd premise says that it is NOT TRUE that "John is a lawyer." So it follows necessarily that Mary is a doctor. Right?

8 1. All cats are animals. 2. Some cats are tigers. ______________________________ 3. Some animals are tigers. Valid If all cats are animals (as they are), and if some of them are tigers (which is also the case), then some animals must be tigers (namely, the animals that are cats that are tigers).

9 1. All dogs are animals. 2. Some dogs are tigers. ______________________________ 3. Some animals are tigers. Valid If all dogs are animals (which is true), and if some dogs are tigers (which is false), then some animals must be tigers (which is true). Remember, it is the logical FORM of an argument that makes it valid or invalid, not its truth content. In this argument, the second premise is false. However, *IF* it were true that some dogs are tigers, then it would follow from the two premises that some animals are tigers.

10 1. If Polly is a tiger, then Polly is a cat. 2. If Polly is a cat, then Polly is an animal. _________________________________________________ 3. If Polly is a tiger, then Polly is an animal. Valid If T, then C; if C, then A; therefore, if T, then A. Right? If tiger, then cat; if cat, then animal; therefore, if tiger, then animal.

11 1. If Polly is alive, then Polly is an animal. 2. If Polly is an animal, then Polly is a tiger. ________________________________________________ 3. If Polly is alive, then Polly is a tiger. Valid All of the statements in this argument (premises and conclusion) are false. Something that is alive might be a plant rather than an animal (contrary to the 1st premise); and something that is an animal might be other than a tiger (contrary to the 2nd premise). The conclusion is also false: there are living things that are not tigers. However, *IF* it were true that Polly's being alive made her an animal, and *IF* it were true that Polly's being an animal made her a tiger, then it would follow necessarily that Polly's being alive would make her a tiger. The argument is valid (but unsound).

12 1. If Polly is a tiger, then Polly is a cat. 2. If Polly is a cat, then Polly is an animal. _______________________________________________ 3. If Polly is an animal, then Polly is a tiger. Invalid The conclusion does not follow from the (true) premises. If tiger, then cat; and if cat, then animal; but there are animals that are not tigers (e.g., dogs, pigeons, etc.).

13 1. All cats are animals. 2. Some animals are not dogs. ___________________________________ 3. Some animals are not cats. Invalid All three statements in this argument are true, but the inference in the argument is invalid. The 1st premise (all cats are animals) leaves open the possibility that all animals are cats (which, of course, we know from our background experience to be false). The 1st premise does not tell us whether or not there are animals that are NOT cats. Similarly, the 2nd premise, which states that there are animals that are not dogs, does not tell us whether or not there are also animals that are not cats (conclusion). The 2nd premise does not mention cats at all. So we cannot draw the conclusion from the stated premises.

14 1. Some cats are black. 2. Some animals are not cats. ___________________________________ 3. Some animals are not black. Invalid All three statements in this argument are true, but the inference in the argument is invalid. The premises leave open the possibility that all animals are black. The 1st premise (some cats are black) does not tell us whether or not there are animals that are NOT black. The 2nd premise (some animals are not cats) does not tell us anything about the colors animals might or might not have. So we cannot validly deduce the conclusion (some animals are not black) from the stated premises. (Hint: Any two-premise argument with both premises beginning with "some" must be invalid. Can you figure out [or find out] why?)

15 1. If p, then q. 2. p. ___________________ 3. q. Valid This argument *form* says that if p is true, then q is true (1st premise). Then it goes on to say that p is true (2nd premise). Now, if p is true, as the 2nd premise says, and if q must be true if p is true, as the 1st premise says, then it follows necessarily that q is true (conclusion). Do you see that? (Notice that the actual truth or falsity of the statements in the argument is irrelevant on the question of whether the argument *FORM* is valid or invalid.)

16 1. If p, then q. 2. Not p. ___________________ 3. Not q. Invalid This argument *form* says that if p is true, then q is true (1st premise). Then it goes on to say that p is NOT true (2nd premise). Now, the 1st premise leaves open the logical possibility that q might be true even if p is false. So, on the basis of the premises, we cannot validly conclude that q is false.

17 1. If it rains, then Mary carries an umbrella. 2. Mary is not carrying an umbrella. ______________________________________________ 3. It is not raining. Valid Assuming that Mary carries an umbrella whenever it rains (1st premise), and assuming that she is not carrying an umbrella now (2nd premise), it follows necessarily that it is not raining now. The 1st premise asserts that if "it rains" is true, then "Mary carries an umbrella" must also be true. So if Mary is NOT carrying an umbrella, we can be sure that it is not raining.

18 1. If it rains, then Mary carries an umbrella. 2. Mary is carrying an umbrella now. ______________________________________________ 3. It is raining. Invalid Assuming that Mary carries an umbrella whenever it rains (1st premise), and assuming that she is carrying an umbrella now (2nd premise), it does NOT follow necessarily that it is raining now. The 1st premise asserts that if "it rains" is true, then "Mary carries an umbrella" must also be true; but the 1st premise does not rule out the logical possibility that Mary carries an umbrella even when it is NOT raining. It just says IF it rains, then she will carry an umbrella; it does NOT say what will happen if it is not raining. So if all we know is that Mary is carrying an umbrella, we cannot tell whether it is raining or not.

19 1. If pain exists, then God does not exist. 2. Pain exists. ___________________________________________ 3. God does not exist. Valid Valid, right? (1) If p is true, then q is true. (2) p is true. Therefore, (3) q is true. It does not matter what p and q stand for; and it does not matter whether the statements p and q stand for are either true or false (or unconvincing). It is the *FORM* of a deductive argument that is either valid or invalid (regardless of the argument's truth content).

20 1. Either p or q. 2. q. _____________________ 3. Not p. Invalid The 1st premise says that either p is true or q is true, and that maybe they are both true. So if q is true (2nd premise), we cannot conclude that p is false (conclusion), since they might both be true, according to the 1st premise.