Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2015 Lecture 2.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Thinking Like an Economist
Advertisements

Government Policy and Market Failures
Equity, Efficiency and Need
The Efficiency Standard. Introduction  Proponents of efficiency argue: balance the costs and benefits of pollution reduction and seek to achieve the.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 2.
Factor Markets and the Distribution of Income
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2010 Lecture 10.
1 Intermediate Microeconomics Equilibrium. 2 Partial Equilibrium We have now derived both the market demand curve (Q d (p)) and market supply curve (Q.
19.0 Conclusion Debate over intervention vs. non-intervention goes back two hundred years Jean-Baptiste Say (1803) – market system can and does.
16 CHAPTER Public Goods and Common Resources.
Economics and Economic Reasoning
What is Economics? Economics is the social science that study how individuals and societies choose to use the scarce resources. Example: When should it.
1 Externality Here we study the situation where production leads to not only private costs, but also social costs.
Externalities 1. An externality is a situation where actions of one have impacts on others. Here we focus on negative externalities, where the impact.
Understanding Monopoly 10. Natural Barriers to Entry Economies of scale –“Bigger is better” (more cost-efficient) –This is due to the ATC being downward-
1 Understanding more about Consumers. 2 Recall the law of demand was a statement that the price of a product and the quantity demanded of the product.
1 Civil Systems Planning Benefit/Cost Analysis Scott Matthews Courses: and Lecture 2 - 8/28/2002.
1 chapter: >> First Principles Krugman/Wells Economics
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2006 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. ECONOMICS AND ECONOMIC REASONING Chapter 1.
Thinking and working like an economist Today: Marginal benefit Marginal cost Graphing.
Consumer and Producer Surplus
Chapter 8 The Classical Long-Run Model Part 1 CHAPTER 1.
CHAPTER 1 First Principles. 2 What you will learn in this chapter:  Trade  Gains from trade  Specialization  Equilibrium  Efficiency and equity A.
POST GRADUATE DIPLOMA IN BUSINESS MANAGEMENT November 2013 Lesson 1.
Lesson 4: Percentage of Amounts.
Tax Incidence and Deadweight Loss
Homework – Day 1 Read all of Chapter 1. As you read, answer the following questions. 1. Define economics. 2. Explain the “economic way of thinking,” including.
Equity, Efficiency and Need
Market Failure.
CHAPTER 13 Efficiency and Equity. 2 What you will learn in this chapter: How the overall concept of efficiency can be broken down into three components—efficiency.
Overview Aggregating preferences The Social Welfare function The Pareto Criterion The Compensation Principle.
Consumer Choice 16. Modeling Consumer Satisfaction Utility –A measure of relative levels of satisfaction consumers enjoy from consumption of goods and.
1 Externalities. 2 Externalities  Externalities are a market failure (so Government intervention may be advisable).  Externalities imply that there.
General Equilibrium and the Efficiency of Perfect Competition
Homework – Day 1 Read p in Chapter 1. As you read, answer the following questions. 1. Define economics. 2. Identify and explain the three elements.
1 Intermediate Microeconomic Theory Externalities.
Introduction to Economics. Outline I. What is Economics A. Formal Definition B. Informal Definition.
Talk Back To Negative Thoughts
Market Failure Solutions A review of various approaches to address imperfections of the free market system.
What is Economics? Chapter 18.
Economic Health and Politics How does the state of the economy affect politics?
1 Privatization  Prices © Allen C. Goodman, 2015.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 2.
EFL: Lesson 3 Markets. Consumers in Markets Demand = Desire for a product Willingness and ability to pay for it.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 3.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 16.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2010 Lecture 2.
Remedies for Externalities Fees (Taxes) or Bonuses (Subsidies) Coase Approach (Private Solution) Command and Control Cap and Trade Yes  Is the state of.
Learning Objectives At the end of this section you should be able to
Copyright © 2011 McGraw-Hill Australia Pty Ltd PowerPoint slides to accompany Principles of Macroeconomics 3e by Bernanke, Olekalns and Frank 13-1 Chapter.
Economics for Leaders 2/25/15 BR: 1.Think about the law of demand. Why would consumers “substitute” a good or service. 2. What is income effect and give.
When you have completed your study of this chapter, you will be able to C H A P T E R C H E C K L I S T Distinguish between value and price and define.
Externalities 1. Recall the miracle of the market – It produces the outcome that is efficient, provided several conditions are satisfied – Here’s another.
Markets, Maximizers and Efficiency
Introduction to Economics. Outline I. What is Economics A. Formal Definition B. Informal Definition.
Chapter 10 Externalities. Market Failure Market failure is when the free market does not provide the best outcome for society. Monopoly is a form of market.
Lecture by: Jacinto Fabiosa Fall 2005 Consumer Choice.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 2.
TUI University Winter Basic Terminology in Economics ECO202 Macroeconomics TUI University.
Introduction to Economics What do you think of when you think of economics?
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 2.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2011 Lecture 2.
Economics 1 Introduction to Economics. My Introduction Instructor: Jason Lee Office: 376 COB Office Hours:
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2006 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. ECONOMICS AND ECONOMIC REASONING Chapter 1.
Logistics TA sections begin this Friday
Efficiency and Equity in a Competitive Market
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2013 Lecture 2.
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2013 Lecture 2.
ECONOMICS AND ECONOMIC REASONING
Presentation transcript:

Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2015 Lecture 2

1  TA sections begin this Friday  “Fake homework” for next Monday on website  First real homework also up, due next Thursday (Sept 17)  If you want to read ahead:  Richard Posner, “The Ethical and Political Basis of Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication”  For a counterpoint to Posner: Peter Hammond, “Review: The Economics of Justice and the Criterion of Wealth Maximization”  Both have links on syllabus, and both are on Logistics

2  defined law and economics  saw some brief history of the common law  and the civil law  and discussed ownership of dead whales Last week, we…

3  quick review of rational choice  what is efficiency?  is efficiency a good goal for the law? Today: efficiency

4 Rationality, optimization, revealed preference

5  People have preferences…  They understand their options, and how much they like each one  …and they optimize  They choose the option they like the best  This is what economists mean when we talk about rationality or rational behavior  Behavior that is consistent with someone having well-defined, consistent preferences  And this is what we’ll be assuming throughout the semester Most microeconomics is based on the premise of rational choice

6  If I see you choosing something…  …I infer you like it more than your other alternatives  We assume people succeeded in doing what they like, rather than screwing up and doing the wrong thing  And this allows us to learn peoples’ preferences from their choices (to some degree) This leads to the idea of revealed preference

7  If we assume that people have coherent preferences…  …and that we might be able to learn those preferences…  …then we can try to use those preferences to judge when one societal outcome is “better” than another All this is useful if we want to judge what are “good” outcomes

8  a Pareto improvement is any change to the economy which leaves…  everyone at least as well off, and  someone strictly better off  example  you prefer $3,500 to your car  I prefer your car to $3,500  I buy it for $3,500 – Pareto improvement  an outcome is Pareto superior to another, or Pareto dominates it, if the second is a Pareto improvement over the first One way to do this: Pareto criterion Vilfredo Pareto ( )

9  Pareto improvements are “win-win”  But most new laws create some winners and some losers  so the Pareto criterion usually can’t tell us whether one policy is “better” than another  even the car example might not be a true Pareto-improvement  So we need another way to compare outcomes Pareto superiority is not that useful a measure for evaluating a legal system

10 Kaldor-Hicks and Efficiency

11  Given any two options, I can figure out which one I like more (or else I truly don’t care)  Given two options – say, $4,000, or a 2002 Grand Am…  Maybe I prefer the money  Maybe I prefer the car  Maybe I’m exactly indifferent between the two  But one of these must be the case We generally assume preferences are complete

12  If you don’t like it, you can always burn it…  …but we generally assume everyone prefers more money to less money “Everybody needs money. That’s why they call it money.” -Danny DeVito, in Heist We also assume more money is better…

13  If I prefer your car to $3,000…  …but I prefer $5,000 to your car…  …then there must be some amount in between that makes me indifferent  We can say that’s my value for the car  If I’m exactly indifferent between $4,000 and your car…  …we can say I value your car at $4,000 And finally, we assume preferences are continuous

14  Informally: a K-H improvement is any change to the economy which increases the total value achieved by everyone in society…  …where the “value” someone gets from something is measured by their willingness to pay for it  Going back to the car example  Suppose your car is worth $3,000 to you and $4,000 to me  Government seizes your car and gives it to me  I’m better off, you’re worse off  But since I value the car more than you…  …this is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement Next, we define Kaldor-Hicks improvement

15  Unlike a Pareto improvement, a Kaldor-Hicks improvement can create some winners and some losers…  …as long as the winners gain more than the losers lose  If I get your car for free…  I end up better off by $4,000 (my value for the car)  You end up $3,000 worse off (your value for the car)  $4,000 > $3,000, so this is a K-H improvement  We can think of it as a net creation of value  We created $4,000 of value (me getting the car)  And destroyed $3,000 of value (you losing it) Another way to think about Kaldor-Hicks improvements

16  a change to the economy is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement if it could be turned into a Pareto improvement with monetary transfers  K-H improvements also called potential Pareto improvements  I get your car for free  If we combined this change with me giving you $3,500…  …then it would be a Pareto improvement  So even without the transfer, it’s a K-H improvement Formal definition of a Kaldor-Hicks improvement

17  You and I are neighbors, you want to throw a party  The party would make me $100 worse off…  …and make you $50 better off…  …and make each of your 30 guests $5 better off  Is the party a Pareto improvement?  No – can’t be, because it makes me worse off  Is the party a Kaldor-Hicks improvement?  Yes – it increases total value: $50 + $150 – $100 = $100 > 0  (Or: you could throw the party, plus you give me $40 and each of your guests gives me $3 – that would be a Pareto improvement, so just having the party is a K-H improvement) Another example

18  we will call a change to the economy efficient if it is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement  we’ll say law A is more efficient than law B if moving from B to A is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement  and we’ll say a situation is efficient if there are no available Kaldor-Hicks improvements  an efficient situation is when there’s no way to make some people better off, without making some others worse off by more  we’re already getting maximal value out of all available resources Efficiency

19 Pareto vs Kaldor-Hicks improvements “good for society as a whole” may make some people worse off, but increases total surplus/value “good for everyone” makes some people strictly better off, doesn’t make anybody worse off Kaldor-Hicks improvementPareto improvement not that interesting, because they wouldn’t be controversial we’ll often be looking for these

20 Pareto vs Kaldor-Hicks efficiency no available K-H improvements impossible to help someone without hurting someone else more (impossible to increase total payoffs realized by everyone) no available Pareto improvements impossible to help someone without hurting someone else efficiencyPareto efficiency kind of useless for comparing different policies what we’ll be focusing on this semester

21 We said it’s efficient for you to have the party  Makes you $50 better off  Makes 30 guests $5 better off  Makes me $100 worse off  $50 + $150 – $100 = 100 – party “creates $100 of value”  So it’s efficient for you to have the party  True whether you compensate me or not  Even if “my slice of the pie” is smaller, overall pie is bigger…  …which is all that efficiency measures

22 What we’ve really done here  In a sense, what we’ve done here is created a way to add up different peoples’ utility functions…  …by equating utility with willingness to pay  We said the party made me $100 worse off  We equated my disutility from you making noise with the amount of money that would replace the inconvenience – if you threw the party and gave me $100, I’d be just as well off as before  Once we’ve done that, what’s efficient is whatever configuration of the economy “creates the most value”

23 One more example: is it efficient for me to drive to work instead of taking the bus?  Bus to campus from where I live is free  Driving is more convenient, but costs me $1 (gas)  Driving also imposes costs on other people: there’s more traffic, less parking, more pollution  Suppose when I drive to work, it makes 1,000 other people worse off by $0.01 each  By driving to work, I create $11 of total costs  It’s efficient for me to drive to work if the benefit I get is more than $11  If the benefit is less than $11, it’s inefficient for me to drive

24  our definition of efficiency: actions are taken when total benefits outweigh total costs  “goal” is to achieve all Kaldor-Hicks improvements  Ellickson: efficiency is “minimizing the objective sum of (1) transaction costs, and (2) deadweight losses arising from failures to exploit potential gains from trade”  Posner: “wealth maximization”  Polinsky: “Efficiency corresponds to ‘the size of the pie’” Some other, similar measures

25 What forces lead to inefficiency

26 To see whether something’s efficient…  Compare gains to everyone in society (total social benefit)…  …to costs to everyone (total social cost)  Example we already saw (me driving to work):  Total social cost = $1 (gas) + 1,000 X $0.01 = $11  Total social benefit = whatever benefit I gain by driving to work  So we just said: it’s efficient for me to drive to campus whenever the value I get from driving is more than $11

27 How do we expect people to actually behave?  When people decide how to act…  …they consider the cost and benefit to themselves, not to everyone  private benefit and private cost  Driving only costs me $1  so I’ll drive whenever benefit to me is more than $1  On days when value I get from driving is more than $1 but less than $11, I drive to work even though that’s inefficient

28 So externalities cause inefficiency  I’ll do something whenever private benefit > private cost  Efficiency depends on whether social benefit > social cost  If I was the only one affected by my choices, then social benefit = private benefit and social cost = private cost  when I’m deciding which movie to watch on Netflix, nobody else is affected by my choice, so my choice will be efficient  But when my choices affect other peoples’ payoffs…  social benefit  private benefit, or social cost  private cost  so actions I choose to take may not be efficient

29 A classic example of this: the Tragedy of the Commons  Hardin (1968), “The Tragedy of the Commons”  Picture a small fishing village on a lake  The more fish I catch, the fewer fish are left in the lake…  …and the harder it is for everyone else in the village to catch fish  So my fishing imposes a cost (externality) on everyone else  So everyone ends up fishing more than the efficient amount

30 Tragedy of the Commons – example  10 fishermen  Cost of fishing is 12 fish per hour  Notation  h = how many hours I fish  H = combined hours everyone in the village fishes  Fishermen catch 100 – H fish per hour (a)What is the efficient level of fishing? How much utility would that give to each fisherman? 4.4 hours per day per fisherman; fish/day (b)Left to their own devices, how much will each person choose to fish? How much utility will each person get? Hours fishing, per day, per fisherman Total fish caught “Maximum Sustainable Yield” H (100 – H) Efficient Level of Fishing

31 Tragedy of the Commons – example  10 fishermen  Cost of fishing is 12 fish per hour  Notation  h = how many hours I fish  H = combined hours everyone in the village fishes  Fishermen catch 100 – H fish per hour (a)What is the efficient level of fishing? How much utility would that give to each fisherman? 4.4 hours per day per fisherman; fish/day (b)Left to their own devices, how much will each person choose to fish? How much utility will each person get? 8 hours per day per fisherman; 64 fish/day Hours fishing, per day, per fisherman Total fish caught “Maximum Sustainable Yield” Efficient Level of Fishing “Equilibrium” Level of Fishing H (100 – H)

32 What’s going on here?  Fishing imposes a negative externality on other fishermen  Each one ignores this externality when deciding how much to fish…  …so they all end up fishing more than the efficient amount  Same thing happens with other communal resources  Cattle grazing, whaling, overhunting, oyster beds  Aristotle: “That which is common to the greatest number has the least care bestowed upon it”  Elinor Ostrom, who shared the 2009 Nobel Prize in Economics, studies how different societies solve this problem  Positive externalities work the opposite way  Activities which create positive externalities are naturally done less than the efficient amount

33  Without some sort of regulation/intervention…  Activities which impose a negative externality will tend to happen more than the efficient amount…  …and activities which impose a positive externality will tend to happen less than the efficient amount  One recurring theme we’ll see in this class: if we want the law to lead to efficient outcomes, we can try to design the law to eliminate externalities!  “Internalization” So externalities can lead to inefficiency

34 Other forces which lead to inefficiency

35  Cuban cigars  Suppose I’d pay $15 each for Cohibas  They cost $2 each to make, and another $3 each to transport from Havana to Madison  Clearly, it’s efficient for me to smoke Cohibas  But trade embargo on Cuba makes it illegal for me to buy them  Anything that prevents me from buying something I want can be a source of inefficiency  One approach to property law: make it as easy as possible for people to trade among themselves  (This may seem like an obvious point; but then, there are lots of things we’re not allowed to sell…) Another thing that leads to inefficiency: barriers to trade

36  I value my free time at $40/hour  Working in a factory, I can build things worth $50/hour  Clearly, it’s efficient for me to work  Each hour I work creates $10 of new value  Doesn’t matter who gets it – it’s efficient for me to work  But suppose there’s a 25% income tax  Factory owner can’t pay me more than $50/hour  But $50/hour pre-tax is only $37.50 after-tax…  …and I’d rather stay home than earn $37.50 an hour  So I don’t get hired – which is inefficient Another thing that leads to inefficiency: taxes

37  This is a new BMW that’s been cut in half  Taxes distort behavior away from efficiency Another example of taxes leading to inefficiency

38 CS Profit  Example  Demand for some good given by P = 100 – Q  Monopolist can produce good for $40/unit  Monopoly price is 70, demand is 30  Deadweight loss is inefficiency  Customers willing to pay more than marginal cost but unable to trade Another thing that leads to inefficiency: monopoly P * = 70 P = 100 – Q Q * = 30 MC = 40 DWL (or private information)

39  For example  we just said taxes lead to inefficiency…  …but without taxes, there’s be far too few public goods, which is also inefficient  we just said monopoly leads to inefficiency…  …but we’ll study patents, which are legal monopolies used to encourage innovation  But also, we’ve defined “efficient”, but we haven’t claimed that “efficient = good”  Which brings us to… But, saying these things lead to inefficiency doesn’t automatically mean they’re bad

40 Is efficiency a good goal for the law? Jump

41  positive statements are statements of fact  can be descriptive: “2014 U.S. GDP was $17 trillion”  can be theoretical predictions: “if prices rise, demand will fall”  “economics of what is”  normative statements contain value judgments  for example, “less inequality is better”  or, “government should encourage innovation”  “economics of what ought to be” Important distinction: positive versus normative economics

42  Predicting behavior, and outcomes, that follow from a law or legal system is positive economics  “Law X will lead to more car accidents than law Y”  “Law X will lead to more efficient outcomes than law Y”  But in the background, we’d like some sense of what is the normative goal of the legal system  “Law X is better than law Y”  One candidate for that normative goal is efficiency Most of this class will be positive analysis

43 “The central question [in this book]… is a simple one: what set of rules and institutions maximize the size of the pie? What legal rules are economically efficient? There are at least three reasons why that is the question we ask. The first is that while economic efficiency… is not the only thing that matters to human beings, it is something that matters quite a lot to most human beings. The second reason is that there is evidence that considerable parts of the legal system we live in can be explained as tools to generate efficient outcomes… It is a lot easier to make sense out of a tool if you know what it is designed to do. A final reason is that figuring out what rules lead to… efficient outcomes is one of the things economists know how to do – and when you have a hammer, everything looks like a nail.” - Friedman, Law’s Order, p. 312 Friedman gives a few arguments for studying efficiency

44  All we care about is “final outcomes” – who ended up with what – not why  We can ignore the direct effect of monetary transfers  Suppose the law says if I hit you with my car, I owe you $3,119  Me paying you that money has no impact on efficiency  So we can ignore the transfer itself, and think only about its effects on our incentives Indeed, focusing on efficiency will make things much easier for us in some ways

Let’s first dispense with the straw man. I’ve never heard of an economist who believes that every efficient policy is good, and I’ve heard of very few who believe that every inefficient policy is bad. It’s true that most economists do seem to believe that any good policy analysis should start by considering efficiency. That doesn’t mean it should end there. I think economists are right to emphasize efficiency, and I think so for (at least) two reasons. First, emphasizing efficiency forces us to concentrate on the most important problems. Second, emphasizing efficiency forces us to be honest about our goals. – Steven Landsburg Another argument why policy evaluation should at least start with efficiency… 45

Politician: Here’s my program to make the health care system work better by subsidizing health care for the poor. Economist: Your program costs a billion dollars and delivers half a billion dollars worth of benefits. That’s inefficient. Politician: So what? Economist: Well, the “so what” is that maybe you could take that billion dollars and deliver a full billion dollars worth of benefits instead if you spent it a little differently. Why not just hand the cash out to poor people? Politician: Because I don’t want to help all poor people. I only want to help sick poor people – and this is the only way I can think of to do that. Economist: Ah. So your goal here is not to make the health care system work better at all. Instead it’s to transfer resources to sick poor people. Politician: I guess so. Economist: That’s fine. Now we can have a healthy debate about whether that’s what we want to do. “Emphasizing efficiency forces us to be honest about our goals” 46

47  This answers the question, “Why should we study efficiency?”  Not the question, “Should the law be designed with the goal of achieving efficiency?”  To answer this latter question… But… Jump

48  Where we’re headed next: Richard Posner, “The Ethical and Political Basis of Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication”  For a counterpoint to Posner: Peter Hammond, “Review: The Economics of Justice and the Criterion of Wealth Maximization”  After that, we’ll get to: Ronald Coase, “The Problem of Social Cost”  Monday, I’ll be showing an example of how “narrow taxes distort more than broad-based taxes” The example is online as a “fake homework”  See you next week! For next week