Logical Arguments. Strength 1.A useless argument is one in which the truth of the premisses has no effect at all on the truth of the conclusion. 2.A weak.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Basic Terms in Logic Michael Jhon M. Tamayao.
Advertisements

TRUTH TABLES The general truth tables for each of the connectives tell you the value of any possible statement for each of the connectives. Negation.
Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
Rules of Inferences Section 1.5. Definitions Argument: is a sequence of propositions (premises) that end with a proposition called conclusion. Valid Argument:
PHILOSOPHY 101 Maymester 2007 Day 2 Logic and Knowledge.
1 Section 1.5 Rules of Inference. 2 Definitions Theorem: a statement that can be shown to be true Proof: demonstration of truth of theorem –consists of.
1 Philosophy and Arguments. 2Outline 1 – Arguments: valid vs sound 2. Conditionals 3. Common Forms of Bad Arguments.
1 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Valid AND Invalid Arguments 2.3 Instructor: Hayk Melikya
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Yet, still, even further more, expanded, Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Dr. Robert Barnard.
Valid Arguments An argument is a sequence of propositions. All but the final proposition are called premises. The last statement is the conclusion. The.
Chapter 1 The Logic of Compound Statements. Section 1.3 Valid & Invalid Arguments.
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Yet, still, Even further More and yet more, etc., ad infinitum, Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Dr. Robert Barnard.
This is Introductory Logic PHI 120 Get a syllabus online, if you don't already have one Presentation: "Good Arguments"
Syllabus Every Week: 2 Hourly Exams +Final - as noted on Syllabus
Essential Deduction Techniques of Constructing Formal Expressions and Evaluating Attempts to Create Valid Arguments.
An Introduction to Propositional Logic Translations: Ordinary Language to Propositional Form.
Logic. what is an argument? People argue all the time ― that is, they have arguments.  It is not often, however, that in the course of having an argument.
Essential Deduction Techniques of Constructing Formal Expressions Evaluating Attempts to Create Valid Arguments.
Propositional Logic USEM 40a Spring 2006 James Pustejovsky.
Proof by Deduction. Deductions and Formal Proofs A deduction is a sequence of logic statements, each of which is known or assumed to be true A formal.
Copyright © Peter Cappello Logical Inferences Goals for propositional logic 1.Introduce notion of a valid argument & rules of inference. 2.Use inference.
Deductive reasoning.
Critical Thinking: A User’s Manual
Basic Argumentation.
Chapter 3 Section 4 – Slide 1 Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. AND.
CSCI 115 Chapter 2 Logic. CSCI 115 §2.1 Propositions and Logical Operations.
Conditional Statements and Material Implication. The Conditional: The Fourth Connective Conditional statement: when two statements are combined by placing.
Deduction, Proofs, and Inference Rules. Let’s Review What we Know Take a look at your handout and see if you have any questions You should know how to.
Reason and Argument Chapter 6 (2/3). A symbol for the exclusive ‘or’ We will use ұ for the exclusive ‘or’ Strictly speaking, this connective is not necessary.
Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning Consider the following two passages: Argument #1 Mr. Jones is a member of the Academy of Scholarly Fellows and only.
1 Sections 1.5 & 3.1 Methods of Proof / Proof Strategy.
The Science of Good Reasons
Deductive Arguments.
Chapter 3: MAKING SENSE OF ARGUMENTS
Lecture 4. CONDITIONAL STATEMENTS: Consider the statement: "If you earn an A in Math, then I'll buy you a computer." This statement is made up of two.
1 CMSC 250 Discrete Structures CMSC 250 Lecture 1.
Chapter 3: Introduction to Logic. Logic Main goal: use logic to analyze arguments (claims) to see if they are valid or invalid. This is useful for math.
Philosophical Method  Logic: A Calculus For Good Reason  Clarification, Not Obfuscation  Distinctions and Disambiguation  Examples and Counterexamples.
The construction of a formal argument
Propositional Logic A symbolic representation of deductive inference. Use upper case letters to represent simple propositions. E.g. Friday class rocks.
Apologetics: Other Syllogisms Presented by Eric Douma.
6.6 Argument Forms and Fallacies
Fun with Deductive Reasoning
Syllogisms and Three Types of Hypothetical Syllogisms
Chapter 7 Evaluating Deductive Arguments II: Truth Functional Logic Invitation to Critical Thinking First Canadian Edition.
Essential Deduction Techniques of Constructing Formal Expressions Evaluating Attempts to Create Valid Arguments.
Arguments Arguments: premises provide grounds for the truth of the conclusion Two different ways a conclusion may be supported by premises. Deductive Arguments.
Symbolic Logic ⊃ ≡ · v ~ ∴. What is a logical argument? Logic is the science of reasoning, proof, thinking, or inference. Logic allows us to analyze a.
Invitation to Critical Thinking Chapter 7 Lecture Notes Chapter 7.
The Art About Statements Chapter 8 “Say what you mean and mean what you say” By Alexandra Swindell Class Four Philosophical Questions.
Logic: The Language of Philosophy. What is Logic? Logic is the study of argumentation o In Philosophy, there are no right or wrong opinions, but there.
Discrete Mathematical Structures: Theory and Applications 1 Logic: Learning Objectives  Learn about statements (propositions)  Learn how to use logical.
Sound Arguments and Derivations. Topics Sound Arguments Derivations Proofs –Inference rules –Deduction.
Deductive Reasoning. Inductive: premise offers support and evidenceInductive: premise offers support and evidence Deductive: premises offers proof that.
THE NATURE OF ARGUMENT. THE MAIN CONCERN OF LOGIC Basically in logic we deal with ARGUMENTS. Mainly we deal with learning of the principles with which.
L = # of lines n = # of different simple propositions L = 2 n EXAMPLE: consider the statement, (A ⋅ B) ⊃ C A, B, C are three simple statements 2 3 L =
PHIL102 SUM2014, M-F12:00-1:00, SAV 264 Instructor: Benjamin Hole
Chapter 7. Propositional and Predicate Logic
Deductive reasoning.
2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary
What makes a Good Argument?
Deductive Arguments.
Principles of Computing – UFCFA3-30-1
Chapter 1 The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Functions
CS201: Data Structures and Discrete Mathematics I
Logical Forms.
Chapter 7. Propositional and Predicate Logic
TRUTH TABLES.
8C Truth Tables, 8D, 8E Implications 8F Valid Arguments
CS201: Data Structures and Discrete Mathematics I
Presentation transcript:

Logical Arguments

Strength 1.A useless argument is one in which the truth of the premisses has no effect at all on the truth of the conclusion. 2.A weak argument is one in which the likelihood of the conclusion’s being true is not much affected by the truth or falsity of the premisses. 3.A moderate argument is one in which the likelihood of the conclusion being false if the premisses are true is quite low. 4.A strong argument is one in which the likelihood of the conclusion being false if the premisses are true is very low. 5.A valid argument is one in which it is just impossible for the conclusion to be false if the premisses are true.

Validity D1.An argument is Valid if and only if it is impossible for the premisses to be true and the conclusion false D2.An argument is Invalid if and only if it is possible for the premisses to be true and the conclusion false All men are mortal Socrates is a man Socrates is mortal All men are mortal Socrates is mortal Socrates is a man

1.Valid arguments can have false premises. Socrates is a wombat All wombats are Greek Socrates is Greek 2.Valid arguments can have false conclusions. Socrates is a wombat All wombats are Spanish Socrates is Spanish

Soundness D3.An argument is Sound if and only if it is valid and has true premisses.

Form All men are mortal Socrates is a man Socrates is mortal is valid: and any argument that has the form All A are B X is an A X is a B is going to be valid This sort of form is called the Logical Form of the argument compare Socrates is a bachelor Socrates is unmarried. First kind of argument is Formally Valid.

Propositional Connectives The standard words that we consider are: 1.‘or’ for disjunction ‘Grass is green or snow is white’ is true if ‘grass is green’ is true or ‘snow is white is true’ Grass or leaves or mulch make a good compost. Grass makes a good compost or leaves make a good compost or mulch makes a good compost. 1. exclusive (xor)We’ll have hamburgers or pizza for dinner (but not both.) 2. inclusiveThere’s a pen or a pencil in that drawer (or both.)

Propositional Connectives 2.‘and’ (‘but’, ‘as well as’, …) for conjunction ‘Grass is green and snow is white’ is true if ‘grass is green’ is true and ‘snow is white is true’ ‘Grass and trees are plants’ 3.‘not’ (‘it is not the case that’, ‘no’, …) for negation ‘Grass is not green’ is true if ‘grass is green’ is not true. ‘It isn’t the case that grass is green’ 4.‘if … then ---’ for implication ‘If grass is green then snow is white’ is true if in any case that ‘grass is green’ is true it is also the case that ‘snow is white is true’.

Disjunctive Syllogism: P or Q Not Q P You are English or you are French. You are not French. So, you are English. Hypothetical Syllogism: If P then Q If Q then R If P then R If you are English then you like fish and chips. If you like fish and chips then you are fat. So, if you are English then you are fat.

Truth Tables Use the following definitions for the truth functions. 1. A B A or B T T T T F T F T T F F F 2. A B A and B T T T T F F F T F F F F 3. A not A T F F T 4. A B if A then B T T T T F F F T T F F T

We combine these functions in the truth tables. For the disjunctive syllogism A = You are English B = You are French A B A or B not B T T T F T F T T T F F T For the hypothetical syllogism D = You are English E = You like fish and chips F = You are fat D E F if D then E if E then F if D then F T T TT T T T T FT F F T F T F T T T F F F T F F T T T T T F T F T F T F F T T T T F F F T T T

Conditional Statements D4.a.A statement of the form ‘if P then Q’ is a Conditional Statement. b.In a statement of the form ‘if P then Q’ the constituent statement P is the Antecedent c.In a statement of the form ‘if P then Q’ the constituent statement Q is the Consequent The following are all equivalent If P then Q P only if Q If P, Q Q if P Unless Q, not P The conditional ‘if P then Q’ can be drawn as:

Necessity and Sufficiency A conditional statement claims that: a situation in which P is true is a sufficient condition for Q to be true, and a situation in which Q is true is a necessary condition for P to be true. If P is a necessary and sufficient condition for Q then Q is also a sufficient and necessary condition for P. If P then Q and if Q then P. This is a biconditional. P if and only if Q

Arguments Modus ponens: If P then Q P Q If you are English then you like fish and chips. You are English. So, you like fish and chips. Modus tollens: If P then Q Not Q Not P If you are English then you like fish and chips. You do not like fish and chips. So, you are not English.

formal fallacies result from an error in the form of the argument. Affirming the consequent: If P then Q Q P If you are English then you like fish and chips. You like fish and chips. So, you are English. Denying the antecedent: If P then Q Not P Not Q If you are English then you like fish and chips. You are not English. So, you do not like fish and chips.

Categorical Propositions The categorical propositions are of four possible forms: 1. All S are P Universal Affirmative A 2. No S are P Universal Negative E 3. Some S are P Particular Affirmative I 4. Some S are not P Particular Negative O where S and P are names of categories (standing for Subject and Predicate.)

Syllogistic Arguments Given two categorical propositions as premisses we can sometimes draw a conclusion in the form of another categorical proposition. Ex 1. No G are H All F are G No F are H No men are perfect All Greeks are men No Greeks are perfect Ex 2. No G are H Some F are G Some F are not H No philosophers are wicked Some Greeks are philosophers Some Greeks are not wicked

Showing Validity We shall simply suppose that: (i)there are some simple, uncontroversial cases of valid reasoning. And then: (ii)given any argument for consideration, we will consider it to be valid just in case we can show that its conclusion can be inferred from the premises by use of these simple steps or rules.

An Example Step 1 What is the argument to be analysed? Ned Kelly was either an outlaw or a political activist. If he was an outlaw or a killer, he deserved what he got. Only if he was fairly tried and justly hung did he deserve what he got. But he was not fairly tried. Therefore, he was a political activist.

Step 2 How are we to evaluate the argument? By attending to its structure or logical form. Using the following abbreviations: O - Ned Kelly was an outlaw; P - Ned Kelly was a political activist; K - Ned Kelly was a killer; D - Ned Kelly deserved what he got; T - Ned Kelly was fairly tried; H - Ned Kelly was justly hung. the argument can be formalized as follows: O or R if (O or K) then D if D then (T and H) not T R

Step 3 Is the argument above valid or invalid? Valid. I can prove it as follows:

Step 4: By assumption, if (O or K) then D, and if D then (T and H), so (1) if (O or K) then (T and H) [since the basic rule: 'If A then B, If B then C; hence If A then C' is valid]. But, by assumption, not-T, so (2) not-(T and H) [since the basic rule: 'not-A; hence not both (A and B)' is valid]. (3) So, by (1) and (2), not-(O or K) [since the basic rule of modus tollens is valid]. (4) So, neither O nor K [since the basic rule: 'not-(A or B); hence neither A nor B' is valid]. (5) So, by (4), not-O [since the basic rule: 'neither A nor B; hence not-A' is valid]. Yet, by assumption, O or R. (6) Hence, by (5), R [since the basic rule: 'not-O, O or P; hence P' is valid].

Showing Invalidity Method 1: Find a Counterexample To show that an argument is invalid, you should: (i) Determine the pattern of the argument to be criticised (ii) Construct a new argument with: (a) the same pattern; (b) obviously true premises; and (c) an obviously false conclusion.

If God created the universe then the theory of evolution is wrong The theory of evolution is wrong God created the universe But this is just like arguing: If Dominic is a wombat then Dominic is a mammal Dominic is a mammal Dominic is a wombat same structure and is obviously invalid. Premises are true, conclusion is false! So it’s invalid.

Method 2: Invalidating Possible Situations To show that an argument is invalid, you should: describe a possible situation in which the premises are obviously true and the conclusion is obviously false

E.g. Fallacy of affirming the consequent If my car is out of fuel, it won't start My car won't start My car is out of fuel. Consider the situation. My car will indeed not start without fuel (it is a fuel-driven car) and the electrical system needed to start the car has been taken out for repairs (so it won't start). Yet the car has a full tank of petrol. The premises are true and the conclusion is false. The situation is not impossible (i.e. it is possible). So, it is not impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. So, the argument is invalid.

E.g. Fallacy of denying the antecedent If the Committee addresses wilderness value then it must address naturalness. It will not address wilderness value. It need not address naturalness. Consider the following possible situation. Wilderness value involves, amongst other things, naturalness (Federal legislation actually defines 'wilderness value' this way). Moreover, the Committee's terms of reference do not include consideration of wilderness value (so it won't address it). Yet the Committee is explicitly formed to consider naturalness (to feed their findings into those of other committees, so that a joint finding can be made regarding wilderness values). The premises are obviously true in this situation and conclusion obviously false. The situation is not impossible (i.e. it is possible). So, it is not impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. So, the argument is invalid.