Divine Omnipotence.  Why would people be concerned to specify the nature of the divine?  What are they relating it to?  What does it have to do with.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
FATE v. FREE WILL. Fatalism The idea of fatalism coincides with destiny. This means that everything in our lives is predestined by fate. In other words,
Advertisements

Believing Where We Cannot Prove Philip Kitcher
General Argument from Evil Against the Existence of God The argument that an all-powerful, all- knowing, and perfectly good God would not allow any—or.
The Fine-Tuning Argument One common response to this argument goes thus: Of course the universe is of a sort suitable for life. If it were not, no one.
Recent versions of the Design Argument So far we have considered the classical arguments of Aquinas and Paley. However, the design argument has attracted.
Criticisms of the Cosmological Argument
The Euthyphro dilemma.
Descartes’ rationalism
Two puzzles about omnipotence
“… if (the best philosophy) doesn ’ t seem peculiar you haven ’ t understood it ” Edward Craig.
WHO IS GOD? 1 John 1 April 3, Background Author –Not identified in the text –John, the Apostle –Another John? Date –Latter part of 1 st Century.
LOCKE ON SUBSTANCE (Part 1 of 2) Text source: Essay Concerning Human Understanding, bk. 2 ch. 23.
PHIL/RS 335 The Evidential Challenge. Flew, “The Presumption”  Flew begins with a distinction fundamental to his understanding of the stakes.  It’s.
Philosophy 220 Corvino on the ‘Naturalness’ of Homosexuality.
Lincoln-Douglas Debate An Examination of Values. OBJECTIVES: The student will 1. Demonstrate understanding of the concepts that underlie Lincoln-Douglas.
The Cosmological Argument. Aquinas’s Cosmological Argument Cosmological Argument is ‘a posteriori’ Attempts to prove the existence of God There are three.
Summa Theologica Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
Goals Define “God” by the Judeo-Christian definition Define omnipotence, omniscience, omni- benevolence, and omni-presence Be able to list and defend several.
The Perfect God Anselm’s clever trick.
Omnipotence, etc Philosophy of Religion 2008 Lecture 1.
Sinnott-Armstrong’s ‘argument from ignorance’
The Problem of Evil The Logical Problem. Epicurus Greek philosopher who founded the Epicurean School of philosophy in Athens. Epicurus’ formulation of.
The Ontological Proof (II) We have seen that, if someone wishes to challenge the soundness of the Modal Ontological, he denies the truth of the second.
PHIL/RS 335 Arguments for God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Cosmological Argument.
The Cosmological Argument (Causation or ‘first cause’ theory)
Natural Law Theory and Homosexuality. NLT and Homosexuality  As Catholic social teaching exemplifies, homosexuality is frequently condemned by adherents.
PHIL/RS 335 The Problem of Evil Pt. 2. Hick, “Soul-Making Theodicy”  Hick begins by owning up. Unlike Cleanthes, Hick is willing to testify to the vast.
Aquinas’ Proofs The five ways.
Proofs For God’s Existence (or are they really proofs?)
Making a Claim Grounds for Claim Evaluation Beyond Brainstorm.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
The Problem of Evil: McCabe, “The Statement of the Problem”
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons: Broad on Personal Belief.
Philosophy 224 Responding to the Challenge. Taylor, “The Concept of a Person” Taylor begins by noting something that is going to become thematic for us.
David Hume By Richard Jones and Dan Tedham. Biographical Details Born in 1711 in Scotland. Major work: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779) Contains.
THE EVIDENTIAL CHALLENGE: FLEW’S A-THEISM PHIL/RS 335.
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons Pt. 2. Legenhausen, “Is God a Person?” Legenhausen uses the little observed fact that Islam is a religion in which the majority.
PHIL/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Ontological Argument.
LECTURE 19 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT CONTINUED. THE QUANTUM MECHANICAL OBJECTION DEPENDS UPON A PARTICULAR INTERPRETATION WE MIGHT REASONABLY SUSPEND.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Morality in the Modern World. Where does morality come from?
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence or how come we all exist? Is there a rational basis for belief in God?
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
HUME’S ASSESSMENT OF NATURAL RELIGION --Summing up Text source: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part 12.
Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.
Thomas Aquinas Mrs. Tucker 7 th Grade World History Honors Cobalt Institute of Math and Science.
PHIL/RS 335 Divine Nature Pt. 2: Divine Omniscience.
The Ontological Argument for the Existence of God August 15, 2015 George Cronk, J.D., Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy & Religion Bergen Community College.
Phil/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 2: The Moral Argument.
Thomas Aquinas “On Being and Essence”. Saint Thomas Aquinas born ca. 1225; died 7 March 1274 Dominican.
Scholasticism St. Thomas Aquinas. Scholasticism System used by medieval intellectuals to apply reason or logical analysis to the Church's basic theological.
What are the strengths and weaknesses of Descartes’ Trademark Argument? StrengthsWeaknesses p , You have 3 minutes to read through the chart you.
Anselm & Aquinas. Anselm of Canterbury ( AD) The Ontological Argument for the Existence of God (Text, pp )
This week’s aims To practise planning and writing answers to past questions To set out written work in a clear, integrated, logical form To explain and.
Argument. What is Argument? It is NOT: --An absolute truth. --A revelation or brand new insight. --The last word. --Bad-tempered complaining. --An exercise.
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
Introduction to Logic Lecture 3 Formalizing an argument By David Kelsey.
Aquinas’ Proofs The five ways. Thomas Aquinas ( ) Joined Dominican order against the wishes of his family; led peripatetic existence thereafter.
The Cosmological Argument
ASPECTS OF GOD OMNIPOTENCE.
Challenges to the OAs The different versions of OA are challenged by:
Concept Innatism.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil
Descartes’ Ontological Argument
The Problem of Evil.
Cosmological Argument: Philosophical Criticisms
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
Recap – Match the terms:
2) Who said ‘you can’t cross the same river twice?’
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 3a Evaluating an argument
Presentation transcript:

Divine Omnipotence

 Why would people be concerned to specify the nature of the divine?  What are they relating it to?  What does it have to do with belief? Worthiness?  Traditional theism has tended to take up the issue of Divine nature through an analysis of God’s capacities and/or qualities and the relationship between these and the various dimensions of our experience.

 Aquinas was born in 1225 in Roccasecca, Italy. At the age of five, he was entered in the Benedictine abbey at Montecassino. It was there that he was introduced to the recently rediscovered works of Aristotle, and to the new mendicant order of the Dominicans, which he eventually joined.  He spent most of his adult life working on behalf of the order and the Church as one of its predominant theologians, defending his increasingly influential Aristotelian-oriented theology from critics and the church from heresies of various sorts.  He died in 1274.

 Aquinas ’ s major work was a collection of questions on the major philosophical and theological issue of his time.  Each of the articles of the Summa Theologica is focused on answering a specific question.  Aquinas insists that clear questions can be answered in two ways - in the affirmative or in the negative.  An answer to a question is not complete until it considers both sides.  Step 1: Ask the question (the issue to be considered).  Step 2: State the objection(s) and give the best arguments for it. The objection is the position on the question opposite to the one that Aquinas is out to prove.  Step 3: State the position to be argued for and give the best arguments for it.  Step 4: Refute each of the arguments objection(s) by a strong counter argument. These are called replies to the objections.

 The question that Aquinas is addressing in the article in front of us concerns God’s omnipotence.  As is typical of the procedure of the Summa, Aquinas first reviews some common objections to the claim that God is omnipotent. 1. There are powers and acts that God seems not to possess (movement). 2. God lacks the power to sin. 3. God’s powers characteristically manifest in ‘unimpressive’ ways (mercy). 4. If God is omnipotent, then nothing is impossible, but since necessity makes necessary reference to impossibility, God’s omnipotence would effectively deny necessity.

 Aquinas recognizes that these objections seem to stem from an ambiguity. What does it mean to say that “All things are possible in God?” (6c1).  To resolve this ambiguity, Aquinas looks (as he typically does) to “The Philosopher,” which is what he calls Aristotle.  For Aristotle a thing can be said to be possible in one of two ways.  In act (what a thing is capable of).  In (a non-self-contradictory) conception.

 As Aquinas makes clear, it is in the second of these senses that it is reasonable to say that all things are possible in God (6C1).  The first sense merely authorizes us to say that God can do what God can do.  So, God can do anything that is not conceptually impossible to do, for those things cannot be done (6c2).  Using this account, Aquinas then goes on to demonstrate why the various objections considered above don’t hold against the claim of God’s omnipotence.

 Mavrodes, taking up Aquinas’s account of divine omnipotence, demonstrates that certain types of arguments against the assertion of divine omnipotence don’t work.  The sorts of arguments in question are like “The Paradox of the Stone” (8).  Mavrodes doesn’t seem to think that this type of paradox can be dissolved as easily as Frankfurt suggests because to deny it’s force seems at the same time to deny God’s omnipotence (8c1).  He also doesn’t think that it is obviously resolved by Aquinas’s insistence on conceptual possibility (not the same as a square circle).

 With regard to this latter point, however, Mavrodes insists that we shouldn’t let appearances deceive us.  The idea that the paradox of the stone is not a conceptual impossibility akin to the square circle is false.  Though in posing the dilemma, no conceptual contradiction is apparent, there is a hidden contradiction operating in the conception of the divine on which the paradox rests (9c1).

 Mavrodes’s discussion is interesting primarily because of what it highlights.  Both Aquinas and Mavrodes are examining arguments against a claim, not providing arguments in favor of a claim.  This can be a subtle difference but it’s an important one. At the very least it suggests that there is a strong presumption operating here that we should interrogate.  Why might we think that God is omnipotent? What are the stakes in the assertion and what are the costs in maintaining it?