Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Computational Game Theory Amos Fiat Spring 2012
Advertisements

6.896: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture 18 Constantinos Daskalakis.
6.896: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture 20 Yang Cai.
(More on) characterizing dominant-strategy implementation in quasilinear environments (see, e.g., Nisan’s review: Chapter 9 of Algorithmic Game Theory.
Algorithmic Game Theory Uri Feige Robi Krauthgamer Moni Naor Lecture 10: Mechanism Design Lecturer: Moni Naor.
The Computational Difficulty of Manipulating an Election Tetiana Zinchenko 05/12/
VOTING. BINARY METHODS Choosing between only two alternatives at time Majority Rule Pairwise voting Condorcet Method Agenda Paradox.
Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Algorithmic Game Theory Uri Feige Robi Krauthgamer Moni Naor Lecture 9: Social Choice Lecturer: Moni Naor.
Math 1010 ‘Mathematical Thought and Practice’ An active learning approach to a liberal arts mathematics course.
Voting and social choice Looking at a problem from the designers point of view.
The Voting Problem: A Lesson in Multiagent System Based on Jose Vidal’s book Fundamentals of Multiagent Systems Henry Hexmoor SIUC.
NOTE: To change the image on this slide, select the picture and delete it. Then click the Pictures icon in the placeholder to insert your own image. CHOOSING.
Computational Democracy: Algorithms, Game Theory, and Elections Steven Wolfman 2011/10/27.
How “impossible” is it to design a Voting rule? Angelina Vidali University of Athens.
IMPOSSIBILITY AND MANIPULABILITY Section 9.3 and Chapter 10.
CS 886: Electronic Market Design Social Choice (Preference Aggregation) September 20.
Voting Theory.
Complexity of manipulating elections with few candidates Vincent Conitzer and Tuomas Sandholm Carnegie Mellon University Computer Science Department.
Arrow’s impossibility theorem EC-CS reading group Kenneth Arrow Journal of Political Economy, 1950.
Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010 Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010.
What is your favorite food?. Preference Schedule A Preference Schedule is a way to represent the order in which people like (prefer) certain items. The.
Motivation: Condorcet Cycles Let people 1, 2 and 3 have to make a decision between options A, B, and C. Suppose they decide that majority voting is a good.
Arrow's Impossibility Theorem Kevin Feasel December 10, 2006
Preference elicitation Vincent Conitzer
Alex Tabarrok Arrow’s Theorem.
CPS Voting and social choice
Social Choice Theory By Shiyan Li. History The theory of social choice and voting has had a long history in the social sciences, dating back to early.
Social Choice Theory By Shiyan Li. History The theory of social choice and voting has had a long history in the social sciences, dating back to early.
Common Voting Rules as Maximum Likelihood Estimators Vincent Conitzer and Tuomas Sandholm Carnegie Mellon University, Computer Science Department.
1 Manipulation of Voting Schemes: A General Result By Allan Gibbard Presented by Rishi Kant.
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = truthful voting Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University.
Social Welfare, Arrow + Gibbard- Satterthwaite, VCG+CPP 1 TexPoint fonts used in EMF. Read the TexPoint manual before you delete this box.: AAA A A A A.
A Fourier-Theoretic Perspective on the Condorcet Paradox and Arrow ’ s Theorem. By Gil Kalai, Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University Presented by:
Social choice (voting) Vincent Conitzer > > > >
Arrow’s Theorem The search for the perfect election decision procedure.
CPS Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Mechanism design for computationally limited agents (previous slide deck discussed the case where valuation determination was complex) Tuomas Sandholm.
Elections and Strategic Voting: Condorcet and Borda E. Maskin Harvard University.
Mechanism design. Goal of mechanism design Implementing a social choice function f(u 1, …, u |A| ) using a game Center = “auctioneer” does not know the.
1 Elections and Manipulations: Ehud Friedgut, Gil Kalai, and Noam Nisan Hebrew University of Jerusalem and EF: U. of Toronto, GK: Yale University, NN:
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan An Introduction to Manipulability Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method The Manipulability.
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 2 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 2 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Math for Liberal Studies.  We have seen many methods, all of them flawed in some way  Which method should we use?  Maybe we shouldn’t use any of them,
Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science.
Mechanism design (strategic “voting”) Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University.
6.853: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Fall 2011 Constantinos Daskalakis Lecture 22.
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem. Question: Is there a public decision making process, voting method, or “Social Welfare Function” (SWF) that will tell us.
How Should Presidents Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan Voting and Social Choice Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Other Voting Systems for Three.
11/24/2008CS Common Voting Rules as Maximum Likelihood Estimators - Matthew Kay 1 Common Voting Rules as Maximum Likelihood Estimators Vincent Conitzer,
Social Choice Lectures 14 and 15 John Hey. Lectures 14 and 15: Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem and other matters Plan of lecture: Aggregation of individual.
Social Choice Lecture 16 John Hey. More Possibility/Impossibility Theorems Sen’s Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal Gibbard’s theory of alienable rights.
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Applied Mechanism Design For Social Good
Algorithmic Analysis of Elections: Voting Rules and Manipulability (minicourse) Piotr Faliszewski AGH University Kraków, Poland.
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Alex Tabarrok Arrow’s Theorem.
Voting systems Chi-Kwong Li.
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Voting and social choice
CPS Voting and social choice
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Presentation transcript:

Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University

Social choice Collectively choosing among outcomes –E.g. presidents –Outcome can also be a vector E.g. allocation of money, goods, tasks, and resources Agents have preferences over outcomes Center knows each agent’s preferences –Or agents reveal them truthfully by assumption Social choice function aggregates those preferences & picks outcome Outcome is enforced on all agents CS applications: Multiagent planning [Ephrati&Rosenschein], computerized elections [Cranor&Cytron], accepting a joint project, collaborative filtering, rating Web articles [Avery,Resnick&Zeckhauser], rating CDs...

Condorcet paradox [year 1785] Majority rule Three voters: 1.x > z > y 2.y > x >z 3.z > y > x x > z > y > x Under some preferences there is a Condorcet winner.

Agenda paradox Binary protocol (majority rule) = cup Three types of agents: x x y y z z x xyy z z xx y y z z Power of agenda setter (e.g. chairman) Vulnerable to irrelevant alternatives (z) Plurality protocol For each agent, most preferred outcome gets 1 vote Would result in x 1.x > z > y(35%) 2.y > x > z(33%) 3.z > y > x(32%)

Pareto dominated winner paradox Voters: 1.x > y > b > a 2.a > x > y > b 3.b > a > x > y

Inverted-order paradox Borda rule with 4 alternatives –Each agent gives 4 points to best option, 3 to second best... Agents: x=22, a=17, b=16, c=15 Remove x: c=15, b=14, a=13 1.x > c > b > a 2.a > x > c > b 3.b > a > x > c 4.x > c > b > a 5.a > x > c > b 6.b > a > x > c 7.x > c > b > a

Borda rule also vulnerable to irrelevant alternatives 1.x > z > y(35%) 2.y > x > z(33%) 3.z > y > x(32%) Three types of agents: Borda winner is x Remove z: Borda winner is y

Majority-winner paradox Agents: Majority rule with any binary protocol: a Borda protocol: b=16, a=15, c=11 1.a > b > c 2.a > b > c 3.a > b > c 4.b > c > a 5.b > c > a 6.b > a > c 7.c > a > b

Is there a desirable way to aggregate agents’ preferences? Set of alternatives A Each agent i in {1,..,n} has a ranking < i of A Social welfare function F: L n -> L To avoid unilluminating technicalities in proof, assume < i and < are strict total orders Some possible (weak) desiderata of F –1. Unanimity: If all voters have the same ranking, then the aggregate ranking equals that. Formally, for all < in L, F(<,…,<) =<. –2. Nondictatorship: No voter is a dictator. Voter i is a dictator if for all < 1,…,< n, F(< 1,…,< n ) = < i –3. Independence of irrelevant alternatives: The social preference between any alternatives a and b only depends on the voters’ preferences between a and b. Formally, for every a, b in A and every a a < ’ b. Arrow’s impossibility theorem [1951]: If |A| ≥ 3, then no F satisfies desiderata 1-3.

Proof (follows logic of Nisan’s proof in Algorithmic Game Theory book, but fixes errors and includes missing part) Assume F satisfies unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives Lemma. Any function F : L n -> L that satisfies unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives also satisfies pairwise unanimity. That is, if for all i, a < i b, then a < b. –Proof. Let a < * b, and so by independence of irrelevant alternatives, for <' = F(< 1,...,< n ), we have a <' b. ■ Lemma (pairwise neutrality). Let > 1,…,> n and >’ 1,…, >’ n be two player profiles such that a > i b c >’ i d. Then a > b c >’ d. –Proof. Assume wlog that a > b and c not equal to d. We merge each > i and >’ i into a single preference > i by putting c just above a (unless c = a) and d just below b (unless d = b) and preserving the internal order within the pairs (a,b) and (c,d). –By pairwise unanimity, c > a and b > d. Thus, by transitivity, c > d. ■ Take any a not equal to b in A, and for every i in {0,…,n} define a preference profile P i in which exactly the first i players rank b above a. By pairwise unanimity, in F(P 0 ) we have a > b, while in F(P n ) we have b > a. Thus, for some i* the ranking of a and b flips: in F(P i*-1 ) we have a > b, while in F(P i* ) we have b > a. We conclude the proof by showing that i* is a dictator: Lemma. Take any c not equal to d in A. If c > i* d then c > d. –Proof. Take some alternative e that is different from c and d. For i i, for i > i* move e to the bottom in > i, and for i* move e so that c > i* e > i* d. By independence of irrelevant alternatives, we have not changed the social ranking between c and d. –Notice that the players’ preferences for the ordered pair (d,e) are identical to their preferences for (a,b) in P i*, but the preferences for (c,e) are identical to the preferences for (a,b) in P i*-1, and thus using the pairwise neutrality claim, socially e > d and c > e, and thus by transitivity c > d in the preferences where e was moved. By independence of irrelevant alternatives, moving e does not affect the relative ranking of c and d; thus c > d also under the original preferences. ■ ■

Stronger version of Arrow’s theorem In Arrow’s theorem, social welfare function F outputs a ranking of the outcomes The impossibility holds even if only the highest ranked outcome is sought: Thm. Let | A | ≥ 3. If a social choice function f: L n -> A is monotonic and Paretian, then f is dictatorial. –Definition. f is monotonic if [ x = f(>) and x maintains its position in >’ ] => f(>’) = x –Definition. x maintains its position whenever x > i y => x > i ’ y Proof. From f we construct a social welfare function F that satisfies the conditions of Arrow’s theorem –For each pair x, y of outcomes in turn, to determine whether x > y in F, move x and y to the top of each voter’s preference order don’t change their relative order (order of other alternatives is arbitrary) Lemma 1. If any two preference profiles >’ and >’’ are constructed from a preference profile > by moving some set X of outcomes to the top in this way, then f(>’) = f(>’’) –Proof. Because f is Paretian, f(>’)  X. Thus f(>’) maintains its position in going from >’ to >’’. Then, by monotonicity of f, we have f(>’) = f(>’’) –Note: Because f is Paretian, we have f = x or f = y (and, by lemma 1, not both) –F is transitive (total order) (we omit proving this part) –F is Paretian (if everyone prefers x over y, then x gets chosen and vice versa) –F satisfies independence of irrelevant alternatives (immediate from lemma 1) –By earlier version of the impossibility, F (and thus f) must be dictatorial. ■

Voting rules that avoid Arrow’s impossibility (by changing what the voters can express) Approval voting –Each voter gets to specify which alternatives he/she approves –The alternative with the largest number of approvals wins –Avoids Arrow’s impossibility Unanimity Nondictatorial Independent of irrelevant alternatives Range voting –Instead of submitting a ranking of the alternatives, each voter gets to assign a value (from a given range) to each alternative –The alternative with the highest sum of values wins –Avoids Arrow’s impossibility Unanimity Nondictatorial Independent of irrelevant alternatives (one intuition: one can assign a value to an alternative without changing the value of other alternatives) –More information about range voting available at These still fall prey to strategic voting (e.g., Gibbard-Satterthwaite impossibility, discussed in the next lecture)