Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December 2009.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Joe Levines Purple Haze. Physical/Phenomenal Gaps P = the complete microphysical truth Q = a phenomenal truth Q1: Is there an epistemic gap between.
Advertisements

65,536 Definitions of Physicalism David J. Chalmers.
TBA David Chalmers. Contingentism Can metaphysical truths be contingent? If so, which, and why?
Hyperintensionality and Impossible Worlds: An Introduction
The Subject-Matter of Ethics
The Necessity of God’s Existence Daniel von Wachter
© Michael Lacewing A priori knowledge Michael Lacewing
Empiricism on a priori knowledge
The Cogito. The Story So Far! Descartes’ search for certainty has him using extreme sceptical arguments in order to finally arrive at knowledge. He has.
The Euthyphro dilemma.
The Liar and Dialetheism The Liar, the Strengthened Liar Dialetheism: Motivations and Problems Keith Allen Office Hour: Weds (D/140)
Hume’s Problem of Induction 2 Seminar 2: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 14 September
Kaplan’s Theory of Indexicals
Identity and Necessity
Today’s Outline Hume’s Problem of Induction Two Kinds of Skepticism
Philosophy of Mind Matthew Soteriou. Functionalism and Qualia Critics of functionalist accounts of the mental often appeal to thought experiments in which.
Ambiguous contents? Arvid Båve, Higher seminar in Theoretical Philosophy, FLoV, Gothenburg University, 8 May 2013.
Saul Kripke, “Identity and Necessity” Driving question: How are contingent identity statements possible? For example, we take it to be the case that it.
NOTE: CORRECTION TO SYLLABUS FOR ‘HUME ON CAUSATION’ WEEK 6 Mon May 2: Hume on inductive reasoning --Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, section.
Knowledge innatism Michael Lacewing
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Fall 2007 Dr. Robert Barnard.
Naturalism The world we live in. Supplementary Reading A Field Guide to Recent Species of Naturalism Alex Rosenberg The British Journal for the Philosophy.
Is there a rational basis for the belief in God..
Knowledge empiricism Michael Lacewing
CAS LX 502 Semantics 1b. The Truth Ch. 1.
Logic. what is an argument? People argue all the time ― that is, they have arguments.  It is not often, however, that in the course of having an argument.
Ontological arguments Concept of God: perfect being –God is supposed to be a perfect being. –That’s just true by definition. –Even an atheist can agree.
Epistemology Revision
Intentionalism and Representational Qualitative Character Intentionalism and Representational Qualitative Character 14 th Annual Meeting of the Association.
KNOWLEDGE What is it? How does it differ from belief? What is the relationship between knowledge and truth? These are the concerns of epistemology How.
The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)
9/18/2015 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant I Charles Manekin.
© Michael Lacewing Reason and experience Michael Lacewing
Knowledge Belief and Truth By Prof.Dr Shadia Abd Elkader Prof.Dr Shadia Abd Elkader.
2 March.
History of Philosophy Lecture 1-a What is philosophy? By David Kelsey.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
MIDTERM EXAMINATION THE MIDTERM EXAMINATION WILL BE ON FRIDAY, MAY 2, IN THIS CLASSROOM, STARTING AT 1:00 P.M. BRING A BLUE BOOK. THE EXAM WILL COVER:
Chapter 3: Knowledge Kant’s Revolution Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-a What is philosophy? By David Kelsey.
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
Entity Theories of Meaning. Meaning Talk Theory should make sense of meaning talk Theory should make sense of meaning talk What sorts of things do we.
© Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing co.uk.
11/26/2015 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant III Charles Manekin.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
© Michael Lacewing Kant on conceptual schemes Michael Lacewing osophy.co.uk.
10 December 2009 Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko
KANT ON THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI
1/9/2016 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant II Charles Manekin.
KNOWLEDGE IS A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI By: Fatima Fuad Azeem.
Knowledge rationalism Michael Lacewing
Narrow narrow content Narrow content is whatever is shared by physical duplicates. It is a function (in the mathematical sense) from environments to broad.
Transient Unterdetermination and the Miracle Argument Paul Hoyningen-Huene Leibniz Universität Hannover Center for Philosophy and Ethics of Science (ZEWW)
Learning objective: To understand the objection that even if a zombie world is conceivable it may not be possible, and to evaluate how convincing this.
Home.sandiego.edu/~baber/analytic/twodogmas.ppt. Meaning What is this thing called meaning? NOT reference: “creature with a heart” ≢ “creature with kidneys”
Knowledge LO: To understand the distinction between three different types of knowledge. To learn some basic epistemological distinctions. To understand.
CAS Managebac update CAS opportunity for someone with a scanner. Cambodia?
The Nature of God Nancy Parsons. Attributes- Nature of God Candidates should be able to demonstrate knowledge and understanding of: 1.God as eternal,
This week’s aims  To test your understanding of substance dualism through an initial assessment task  To explain and analyse the philosophical zombies.
Lecture 6 Modality: Possible worlds
Lecture 7 Modality: Metaphysics of possible worlds
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT 1
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
A new perspective on philosophical debates
The zombie argument: responses
Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
March, 26, 2010 EPISTEMOLOGY.
Daniel W. Blackmon Theory of Knowledge Coral Gables Senior High
March, 26, 2010 EPISTEMOLOGY.
Presentation transcript:

Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December 2009

Outline 1. The conceptualist account › Jackson, Chalmers 2. The essentialist account › Fine, Lowe Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

1. The conceptualist account  The view that we will examine in this section is best known from the work of David Chalmers (1996) and Frank Jackson (1998), but similar ideas have also been defended by Alan Sidelle (1989, 2002). › Recall the Kripkean picture, where metaphysical modality is a proper subset of conceptual modality.  What stops us from reducing metaphysical modality to conceptual modality? Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Metaphysical necessities, such as ‘Water is H 2 O’, are by and large a posteriori, whereas conceptual necessities, such as ‘All bachelors are unmarried’, are a priori. › But there is an argument available here for the conceptualist, who would rather see the Kripkean metaphysical modality to be reduced to conceptual modality altogether. › The details of the argument concern two- dimensional modal semantics, but we will not go into this topic here. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 An outline of the argument: › The sentence ‘Hesperus is Hesperus’ is clearly purely a priori and necessary, whereas the supposed metaphysical necessity, ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’, requires a posteriori information.  But is there anything else that separates it from sentences like ‘Hesperus is Hesperus’?  ‘The difference lies, not in the kind of necessity possessed, but rather where the labels “a priori” and “a posteriori” suggest it lies: in our epistemic access to the necessity they share’ (Jackson 1998: 69-70). Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 There is no difference between the modal statuses of trivial analytic truths and supposed metaphysical necessities. › The conceptualist picture of the relationship between conceptual possibility and metaphysical possibility is simply that they are co-extensive: Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko conceptual possibility = metaphysical possibility 17 December /22

 A crucial shortcoming of the conceptualist account is that it is too coarse-grained. › Since all modal truths are supposedly either analytic truths or a combination of an analytic principle and an empirical discovery, there is no way to distinguish the following:  ‘All water is water’  ‘Water has its molecular structure necessarily’ › Surely there is an important difference between these statements, how could the modal content be identical? Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

2. The essentialist account  Best known from the work of Kit Fine (1994), but has also been discussed by Lowe (1998), Correia (2006) and Shalkowski (1997). › The core of this account is that metaphysical modality reduces to essence, as Fine puts it: ‘we should view metaphysical necessity as a special case of essence’ (1994: 8). › More generally, we can reduce modality to the essences of the entities it concerns. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 A natural consequence of this view is that we can define conceptual and logical modality with reference to metaphysical modality: “Given the notion of metaphysical necessity, the various narrower notions of necessity – be it logical, mathematical, conceptual, or the like – can each be defined by restriction. Each of these other forms of necessity can, in other words, be regarded as a species of metaphysical necessity.” (Fine 2002.) Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Accordingly, a mathematical necessity is something that is metaphysically necessary in addition to being a mathematical truth.  But Fine thinks that natural and normative modality are not definable in terms of other types of modality. › There may be metaphysical possibilities, based on some alternative laws of physics, which are not natural possibilities, and hence natural necessities need not be meta- physically necessary. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 More generally: if there are propositions that are metaphysically contingent, yet necessary in terms of another type of modality, then the type of modality in question cannot be regarded as a species of metaphysical modality, but would be a distinct form of modality. › Let’s have a closer look at how this works in the cases of conceptual and logical modality. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 The case of conceptual modality seems unproblematic: › All necessities that are true in virtue of the essences of all concepts are also true in virtue of the essences of all things. › Compare with the principle of monotonicity:  If A is true in virtue of the nature of X and X is a subset of Y, then A is true in virtue of the nature of Y.  Given Hale’s (1996) argument for the absoluteness of logical necessity, the general consequence for the essentialist view is that logical necessity is at least as strong as conceptual necessity, which is at least as strong as metaphysical necessity. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

13 / 22 “One kind of necessity, □ 1, may be said to be stronger than another, □ 2, if ‘□ 1 p’ always entails ‘□ 2 p’ but not conversely. Assuming the usual relations between necessity and possibility, this relationship will obtain if and only if ◊ 1 is weaker than ◊ 2, i.e. ‘◊ 2 p’ always entails ‘◊ 1 p’ but not conversely. I shall also say that □ 1 is at least as strong as □ 2 if the first half of this condition is met, i.e. ‘□ 1 p’ always entails ‘□ 2 p’.” (Hale 1996: 94.) Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December 2009

 If p is logically necessary, then p is conceptually necessary, and if p is conceptually necessary, then p is metaphysically necessary. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko met. nec. con. nec. log. nec. log. pos. con. pos. met. pos. 17 December /22

 This would all seem to corroborate Fine’s (2002) analysis of logical and conceptual modality in terms of metaphysical modality. › But are there any counterexamples, i.e. logical or conceptual necessities which are metaphysically contingent?  It is difficult to see how there could be such counterexamples in the case of conceptual modality.  The case of logical modality is not so clear. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 If metaphysical necessities are true in virtue of the nature of all things, then surely all concepts can be subsumed under them. › The same might appear to be true in the case of logical modality, if logical necessities are true in virtue of the nature of all logical concepts.  But this is only plausible if all things that are true in virtue of logical concepts are metaphysically necessary.  Someone who takes the (metaphysical) possibility of alternative logics seriously will not accept it. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Fine’s picture works only if we have a One True Logic, and further, if this logic is metaphysically necessary. › If ‘p & not-p’ expresses a metaphysical possibility(cf. Priest 2006), yet it is logically necessary that ‘p & not-p’ is false (in the model of classical logic), then logical necessities cannot be subsumed under metaphysical necessities.  The upshot is that analogously to the case of natural necessities, logical necessities as well would seem to escape definition by restriction in terms of metaphysical necessity. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Further complications: › On this picture, difficult questions about the subject-matter of different types of modalities need to be answered before we can analyse their relationships. › Moreover, an intuitive distinction between narrower types of necessity and metaphysical necessity seems to have been lost.  We can say that all conceptual necessities are a proper subset of metaphysical necessities, but it may be misleading to say simply that all conceptual necessities are metaphysically necessary. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Conceptual necessity concerns only a proper subset of metaphysical necessity — it can make no claims outside its designated realm. › Perhaps we would be better off by reserving the term ‘metaphysical necessity’ for those necessities which are not also conceptually necessary, or logically necessary, or indeed necessary only in some narrower subset of metaphysical necessities (cf. Lowe 1998: 15).  Same goes for other types of necessity. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Quite independently of this confusion, there is a further problem concerning logical possibilities which are not metaphysically possible, e.g. ‘Cats are Demons’. › According to Fine’s picture, if logical necessity is to be subsumed under metaphysical necessity, then all logical necessities should also be metaphysically necessary.  Perhaps we can exclude metaphysical impossibilities from the modal space: they are pseudo-possibilities. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December /22

 Alternative picture: Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko metaphysical possibility classical logic intuitionist logic para- consistent logic 17 December /22

22 / 22 References: Chalmers, D. (1996). The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Chalmers, D. (2002a). ‘Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?’, in T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp Chalmers, D. (2002b). ‘On Sense and Intension’, in J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 16: Language and Mind (Oxford: Blackwell), pp Chalmers, D. (2006). ‘Two-Dimensional Semantics’, in E. Lepore & B. Smith (Eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp Correia, F. (2006) ‘Generic Essence, Objectual Essence, and Modality’, Noûs 40 (4): Fine, K. (1994). ‘Essence and Modality’, J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives 8: Logic and Language (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview), pp Fine, K. (1995). ‘Senses of Essence’, W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman & N. Asher (Eds.), Modality, Morality and Belief: Essays in Honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp Fine, K. (2002). ‘The Varieties of Necessity’, in T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp Hale, B. (1996). ‘Absolute Necessities’, J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives 10: Metaphysics (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview), pp Jackson, F. (1998). From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Lowe, E. J. (1998). The Possibility of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Priest, G. (2006). In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, 2nd expanded ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Shalkowski, S. (1997). ‘Essentialism and Absolute Necessity’, Acta Analytica 12 (2): Sidelle, A. (1989). Necessity, Essence and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press). Sidelle, A. (2002). ‘On the Metaphysical Contingency of Laws of Nature’, in T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp Tahko, T. E. (2009). ‘On the Modal Content of A Posteriori Necessities’, Theoria: A Swedish Journal of Philosophy 75 (4): 344–357. Vaidya, A. (2008) ‘The Epistemology of Modality’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). Ed. Zalta, Edward. URL =. Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 17 December 2009