4. EXTENSIVE-FORM GAMES.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Introduction to Game Theory
Advertisements

Oligopoly.
Ultimatum Game Two players bargain (anonymously) to divide a fixed amount between them. P1 (proposer) offers a division of the “pie” P2 (responder) decides.
Game Theory S-1.
1 On the Methodology of Inequity Aversion Theory.
Games With No Pure Strategy Nash Equilibrium Player 2 Player
Monetary Stakes and Socioeconomic Characteristics in Ultimatum Games: An Experiment with Nation-Wide Representative Subjects Tsu-Tan Fu Center for Survey.
Brandts and Solà: Reference Points and Negative Reciprocity in Simple Sequential Games Economics 328 Spring 2005.
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
Game Theory and Behavioral Economics. An Illustration: The 21 Coins Game Rules: In this two person game, the first mover can remove 1, 2, or 3 coins from.
Game Theory. Games Oligopolist Play ▫Each oligopolist realizes both that its profit depends on what its competitor does and that its competitor’s profit.
Fehr and Falk Wage Rigidity in a Competitive Incomplete Contract Market Economics 328 Spring 2005.
4 Why Should we Believe Politicians? Lupia and McCubbins – The Democratic Dilemma GV917.
Game Theory The study of rational behavior among interdependent agents Agents have a common interest to make the pie as large as possible, but Agents have.
Chapter 6 © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western Game Theory.
M. Bhatt & C. Camerer Games and Economic Behavior, 2005.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Review Midterm3/21 3/7.
B OUNDED R ATIONALITY in L ABORATORY B ARGAINING with A SSYMETRIC I NFORMATION Timothy N. Cason and Stanley S. Reynolds Economic Theory, 25, (2005)
Behavioral Game Theory: A Brief Introduction Networked Life CSE 112 Spring 2005 Prof. Michael Kearns Supplementary slides courtesy of Colin Camerer, CalTech.
Notes on Alesina and Angeletos on ‘Fairness and Redistribution’ Econ 594ER October 29, 2007.
Motivations and observed behaviour: Evidence from ultimatum bargaining experiment Elena Tougareva Laboratory of Social and Economic Psychology, Institute.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Review Midterm3/23 3/2.
Introduction to Game Theory and Behavior Networked Life CIS 112 Spring 2009 Prof. Michael Kearns.
Playing Unfair: Punishment in Bargaining and Negotiations Deborah Kay Elms IPES Conference November 14, 2008.
From transaction cost to transactional value analysis: Implications for the study of inter- organizational strategies Zajac, Edward J. & Olsen, Cyrus P.
January 29, 2004 Experimental Economics 1 Outline  In-class experiment on IPV First-Price Auctions  Data from Cox, Robertson, and Smith (1982)  Glenn.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Review Midterm3/19 3/5.
Introduction: Thinking Like an Economist 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 12 The Logic of Individual Choice: The Foundation of Supply and Demand The theory of economics.
Economics for Leaders The Ultimatum Game. Proposal Selection Form Proposer Identification Code __________________ Circle a proposal: 9/1 8/2 7/3 6/4 5/5.
13th International Conference on Social Dilemmas Kyoto, JAPAN, August 20-24, Your peers are watching you: Reputation sensitivity and in-group favoritism.
Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics 11 Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics All men can see the.
Proposal Selection Form Proposer Identification Code __________________ Circle a proposal: 19/1 18/2 17/3 16/4 15/5 14/6 13/7 12/8 11/9 10/10 9/11 8/12.
Coalition Formation between Self-Interested Heterogeneous Actors Arlette van Wissen Bart Kamphorst Virginia DignumKobi Gal.
Team Formation between Heterogeneous Actors Arlette van Wissen Virginia Dignum Kobi Gal Bart Kamphorst.
Course Behavioral Economics Alessandro InnocentiAlessandro Innocenti Academic year Lecture 14 Fairness LECTURE 14 FAIRNESS Aim: To analyze the.
Ultimatum bargaining: From synapse to society Colin F. Camerer, Caltech  Ultimatum game: –Proposer offers division of $10; responder accepts or rejects.
Bargaining Whoever offers to another a bargain of any kind, proposes to do this. Give me that which I want, and you shall have this which you want …; and.
Evolution of cooperation in Stackelberg games Raimo P. Hämäläinen Ilkka Leppänen Systems Analysis Laboratory Aalto University.
Reputational advantages and disadvantages of punishment toward norm-violators Yutaka Horita Toshio Yamagishi Hokkaido University 13th international conference.
Lecture 2 Economic Actors and Organizations: Motivation and Behavior.
Experimental Economics and Neuroeconomics. An Illustration: Rules.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. GAME THEORY, STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING, AND BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS.
THE “CLASSIC” 2 x 2 SIMULTANEOUS CHOICE GAMES Topic #4.
Inequity aversion in mice Whitney Swain Advisor: Dr. Lustofin Humans are a social species who often feel like they have been treated unfairly if they do.
Negotiation 101 Fairness and the importance of looking ahead.
Motivation This experiment was a public good experiment to see if groups contribute differently than individuals.  intermediate social structure This.
Theory of Mind Enhances Preference for Fairness Haruto Takagishi 1,2, Shinya Kameshima 3, Joanna Schug 1, Michiko Koizumi 1, Toshio Yamagishi 1 1 Hokkaido.
What games do economists play? To see more of our products visit our website at Tom Allen, Head of Economics, Eton College.
Dr. Asad Zaman Presentation at PIDE, 21 st April 2014 Based on “Empirical Evidence Against Utility Theory: A Survey of the Literature”
Proposal Selection Form Proposer Identification Code __________________ Circle a proposal: 19/1 18/2 17/3 16/4 15/5 14/6 13/7 12/8 11/9 10/10 9/11 8/12.
Explicit versus Implicit Contracts for Dividing the Benefits of Cooperation Marco Casari and Timothy Cason Purdue University.
Lecture 1 on Bargaining Setting the Agenda This lecture focuses on the well known problem of how to split the gains from trade or, more generally, mutual.
Testing theories of fairness— Intentions matter Armin Falk, Ernst Fehr, Urs Fischbacher February 26, 2015.
The Logic of Individual Choice: The Foundation of Supply and Demand 10 The Logic of Individual Choice: The Foundation of Supply and Demand The theory of.
UNSW | BUSINESS SCHOOL | SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS Calling the shots Experimental evidence on significant aversion to non-existing strategic risk Ben Greiner.
Theories and Methods in Social Psychology David Rude, MA, CPC Instructor 1.
Experiments and “Rational” Behavior, 5/1/07. Beauty Contest Game Each person choose a number from 0 to 100. We will average these numbers. The person.
Yu-Hsuan Lin Catholic University of Korea, Korea University of York, U.K. 5 th Congress of EAAERE, Taipei, 06 th – 07 th August 2015.
Management support systems II
Proposal Selection Form
Behavioral economics Chapter 30
Examples of Laboratory Experiments
THE ECONOMY: THE CORE PROJECT
Unit 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS.
Gönül Doğan, Marcel van Assen, Jan Potters Tilburg University
Alternative-offer bargainging
Behavioral economics Chapter 30
Game Theory: The Nash Equilibrium
Presentation transcript:

4. EXTENSIVE-FORM GAMES

The Ultimatum Game The proposer makes a single offer to a responder about how to split some amount of money (e.g., $10 in $1 units). The responder must either i) accept the proposed split or ii) reject the proposal, which results in zero earnings for both parties. Güth, W., Schmittberger, and Schwarze (1982). "An Experimental Analysis of Ultimatum Bargaining". Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization: 367–388.

Ultimatum game: Standard Prediction Proposer 010 x Responder 10-x, x0, 0 AcceptReject Goal: solve for proposer’s equilibrium offer x Start at the bottom What will Responder accept? Offer of 1, 2, … 10, but not 0

Ultimatum game: Standard Prediction Proposer Responder 9, 1 0, 0 AcceptReject If proposer offers 1 will responder accept? Yes, 1 is better than zero Does proposer have an incentive to deviate from this strategy? Could he do better by offering 2? No, while responder earnings rise to 2, the proposer does not need to make this offer to induce acceptance and with earnings of 8 the proposer is worse off.

Ultimatum game: Standard Prediction Proposer Responder 9, 1 0, 0 AcceptReject X = 1 is a Nash equilibrium. It is not fair to the responder, but shows the advantage of being the one who calls the equilibrium.

Prediction of Standard Economic Theory A “rational” proposer would offer $1 and keep $9 for him/herself. A “rational” responder would accept $1, reasoning that $1 is better than nothing, and not crash the deal. Findings to the contrary suggest that people do no have purely self-regarding preferences

Class Experiment I will pay two students, chosen at random, 1/0 of their cumulative earnings after 12 rounds of Treatments 1 and 2 run in Veconlab. Treatment #1 – Dictator Game run by hand. $10 (10 x $1) given to a student chosen at random who is then invited to share some with neighbor. Treatment #2 – Dictator Game run in Veconlab. Treatment #3 – Ultimatum Game run in Veconlab.

Standard Empirical Findings Results contradict predictions of standard game theory.  In Industrial cultures, irrespective of monetary sum, modal offers are around 50% of total amount.  Low offers (20%) have about a 50% chance of being rejected.

First Explanation – Low Stakes Unequal allocations are rejected only because the absolute amount of the offer is low. If the amount to be split were ten million dollars a 90:10, the split would probably be accepted rather than spurning a million dollar offer. Cameron and Hoffman et al. (1994) – the higher the stakes the closer offers approach an even split, even in a 100 USD game played in Indonesia, where average 1995 per-capita income was 670 USD. Rejections are reportedly independent of the stakes at this level, with 30 USD offers being turned down in Indonesia, as in the US, even though this equates to two week's wages in Indonesia.

Second Explanation Bolton (1991) - Utility includes social comparison U(x R, x R /x P ) x R = absolute earnings received by responder x R /x P = ratio of responder’s earning to proposer’s earning (1 if both get zero) Example: Responder rejects $2 out of $10 offer U($2, 0.25) < U($0, 1) ++

Problem with Second Explanation? Social comparison theory does not distinguish between: a) distaste for unequal allocations b) willingness to punish someone who has behaved “unfairly” Blount (1996): Subjects are more likely to accept small (uneven) offers it they come from a random device than from a person Conclusion: People are punishing unfairness, not rejecting inequality

Sanfey, et al. Science (2003).

Third Explanation: Intentions Matter Mathew Rabin (1993) Intentional acts of meanness Punish Unintentional acts of meanness Tolerate Fairness equilibrium - both parties will sacrifice to reward (punish) other player’s cooperative (uncooperative) act

Push-Pull Game: Prisoner’s Dilemma Column Player Row Player CooperateDefect Cooperate Nash Equilibrium Fairness Equilibrium (both parties punish uncooperative behavior of others) Fairness Equilibrium (both parties willing to sacrifice to reward other player’s cooperative act)

Implications If intentions matter we can explain… 1) Difference in results from ultimatum game when played with computer 2) Simultaneous,… Positive altruism (helping friends with gifts or trust) Negative altruism (punishing enemies at a cost to oneself)

Camerer and Thaler (1996) Rabin has it right - Manners Matter Findings: People share in dictator games, but sharing shrinks when a) the relationship with the other player is made less personal or 2) when proposer “earned” the right to the $10. Conclusion: “Manors” require you to share a windfall with a friend, do not require that you give up a hard-earned bonus to a stranger.” Findings: Responders reject low (but greater than $1) offers. Conclusion: Responders in ultimatum game are willing to turn down rude offers at a cost to themselves.

More Evidence for Rabin’s “Manners Matter” Finding: When Responders must compete with one another to take an offer from single Proposer, minimal acceptable offers fell to 10% (Roth et al. 1991). Conclusion: Individual Responders don’t have the ability to single-handedly punish unfair offers. Since the Proposer is not suggesting an offer in these games – he is taking the best offer from competing Responders – the prospect of unfair offers is removed. These findings are consistent with idea that manners about fairness norms matter.

Is a sense of fairness learned? Murnighan and Saxon (1994) Kindergartners accept minimal offers (e.g., one M&M out of a pile) about 70% of the time 3 rd and 6 th graders accept minimal offers about 40% of the time learned behavior

Is a sense of fairness genetic? Wallace, Cesarini, Lichtenstein and Johannesson, “Heritability of Ultimatum Game Responder Behavior” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, October Abstract: Experimental evidence suggests that many people are willing to deviate from materially maximizing strategies to punish unfair behavior. Even though little is known about the origins of such fairness preferences, it has been suggested that they have deep evolutionary roots and that they are crucial for maintaining and understanding cooperation among non-kin. Here we report the results of an ultimatum game, played for real monetary stakes, using twins recruited from the population-based Swedish Twin Registry as our subject pool. Employing standard structural equation modeling techniques, we estimate that >40% of the variation in subjects' rejection behavior is explained by additive genetic effects. Our estimates also suggest a very modest role for common environment as a source of phenotypic variation. Based on these findings, we argue that any attempt to explain observed ultimatum bargaining game behavior that ignores this genetic influence is incomplete.

Fig. 2. Scatter plot of ultimatum game acceptance thresholds for twin pairs. (A) Scatter plot for MZ twin pairs. The acceptance thresholds are highly correlated. (B) Scatter plot for DZ twin pairs. There was no significant correlation in acceptance thresholds. Identical Twins (share all genes) Fraternal Twins (share 50% of genes)

Sanfey, et al. Science (2000) A fundamental adaptive mechanism by which we assert and maintain a social reputation. Unfair treatment causes people to sacrifice monetary gain to punish partners for slight. What is the evolutionary explanation for this behavior?

Sanfey, et al. Science (2003) Subjects whose brains were scanned by MRI while receiving an unfair offer in an ultimatum game ($1 or $2 out of $10 available) showed greater activity in the bilateral anterior insula of the brain. Overall, work emphasizes importance of emotional influences on human decision making. The anterior cingulate (ACC), a region of the brain that detects cognitive conflict, also showed greater activity during presentation of unfair offers. This area mediates conflict between earning money and feeling bad.

Neuroeconomics

What about Chimpanzees? Abstract: Traditional models of economic decision-making assume that people are self-interested rational maximizers. Empirical research has demonstrated, however, that people will take into account the interests of others and are sensitive to norms of cooperation and fairness. In one of the most robust tests of this finding, the ultimatum game, individuals will reject a proposed division of a monetary windfall, at a cost to themselves, if they perceive it as unfair. Here we show that in an ultimatum game, humans' closest living relatives, chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes), are rational maximizers and are not sensitive to fairness. These results support the hypothesis that other-regarding preferences and aversion to inequitable outcomes, which play key roles in human social organization, distinguish us from our closest living relatives. Jensen, Call and Tomasello, “Chimpanzees Are Rational Maximizers in an Ultimatum Game,” Science Magazine, 2007.

Fig. 1. Illustration of the testing environment. The proposer, who makes the first choice, sits to the responder's left. The apparatus, which has two sliding trays connected by a single rope, is outside of the cages. (A) By first sliding a Plexiglas panel (not shown) to access one rope end and by then pulling it, the proposer draws one of the baited trays halfway toward the two subjects. (B) The responder can then pull the attached rod, now within reach, to bring the proposed food tray to the cage mesh so that (C) both subjects can eat from their respective food dishes (clearly separated by a translucent divider)

Camerer and Thaler Conclusion In repeated encounters, it is rational to treat others fairly and punish those who behave unfairly, because long-run concerns outweigh the short-run costs How do we explain behavior in one-shot games (e.g., tips in restaurants) People cannot curb their repeated –game impulse

5. IMPERFECT INFORMATION