1 Economics 776 Experimental Economics First Semester 2007 Topic 5: Coordination Games Assoc. Prof. Ananish Chaudhuri Department of Economics University.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Nash’s Theorem Theorem (Nash, 1951): Every finite game (finite number of players, finite number of pure strategies) has at least one mixed-strategy Nash.
Advertisements

M9302 Mathematical Models in Economics Instructor: Georgi Burlakov 3.1.Dynamic Games of Complete but Imperfect Information Lecture
Game Theory Assignment For all of these games, P1 chooses between the columns, and P2 chooses between the rows.
ECON 100 Tutorial: Week 9 office: LUMS C85.
This Segment: Computational game theory Lecture 1: Game representations, solution concepts and complexity Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie.
Game Theory S-1.
15 THEORY OF GAMES CHAPTER.
Congestion Games with Player- Specific Payoff Functions Igal Milchtaich, Department of Mathematics, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, 1993 Presentation.
The Stag Hunt Game. Introduction The stag hunt, first proposed by Rousseau, is a game which describes a conflict between safety and social cooperation.
Game Theory “I Used to Think I Was Indecisive - But Now I’m Not So Sure” - Anonymous Mike Shor Lecture 5.
Tacit Coordination Games, Strategic Uncertainty, and Coordination Failure John B. Van Huyck, Raymond C. Battalio, Richard O. Beil The American Economic.
Non-Cooperative Game Theory To define a game, you need to know three things: –The set of players –The strategy sets of the players (i.e., the actions they.
Operations Research Assistant Professor Dr. Sana’a Wafa Al-Sayegh 2 nd Semester ITGD4207 University of Palestine.
1 Game Theory. By the end of this section, you should be able to…. ► In a simultaneous game played only once, find and define:  the Nash equilibrium.
Game Theory and Computer Networks: a useful combination? Christos Samaras, COMNET Group, DUTH.
 1. Introduction to game theory and its solutions.  2. Relate Cryptography with game theory problem by introducing an example.  3. Open questions and.
EC941 - Game Theory Lecture 7 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Game Theory: Inside Oligopoly
Short introduction to game theory 1. 2  Decision Theory = Probability theory + Utility Theory (deals with chance) (deals with outcomes)  Fundamental.
4 Why Should we Believe Politicians? Lupia and McCubbins – The Democratic Dilemma GV917.
ECO290E: Game Theory Lecture 4 Applications in Industrial Organization.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
Chapter 12 Choices Involving Strategy McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All Rights Reserved.
Objectives © Pearson Education, 2005 Oligopoly LUBS1940: Topic 7.
Outline  In-Class Experiment on a Coordination Game  Test of Equilibrium Selection I :Van Huyck, Battalio, and Beil (1990)  Test of Equilibrium Selection.
BEE3049 Behaviour, Decisions and Markets Miguel A. Fonseca.
Outline  In-Class Experiment on a Coordination Game  Test of Equilibrium Selection I :Van Huyck, Battalio, and Beil (1990)  Test of Equilibrium Selection.
Outline  In-Class Experiment on a Coordination Game  Test of Equilibrium Selection I :Van Huyck, Battalio, and Beil (1990)  Test of Equilibrium Selection.
THE PROBLEM OF MULTIPLE EQUILIBRIA NE is not enough by itself and must be supplemented by some other consideration that selects the one equilibrium with.
An Introduction to Game Theory Part III: Strictly Competitive Games Bernhard Nebel.
An introduction to game theory Today: The fundamentals of game theory, including Nash equilibrium.
An introduction to game theory Today: The fundamentals of game theory, including Nash equilibrium.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
Extensive Game with Imperfect Information Part I: Strategy and Nash equilibrium.
QR 38, 2/22/07 Strategic form: dominant strategies I.Strategic form II.Finding Nash equilibria III.Strategic form games in IR.
EC941 - Game Theory Francesco Squintani Lecture 3 1.
Two-Stage Games APEC 8205: Applied Game Theory Fall 2007.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
Game Theory.
GAMES AGAINST NATURE Topic #3. Games Against Nature In game theory, for reasons that will be explained later, the alternatives (e.g., LEFT and RIGHT)
Reading Osborne, Chapters 5, 6, 7.1., 7.2, 7.7 Learning outcomes
Social Choice Session 7 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics 11 Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics All men can see the.
Chapter 12 Choices Involving Strategy Copyright © 2014 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written.
Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium is defined in terms of strategies, not payoffs Every player is best responding simultaneously (everyone optimizes) This.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Game theory (and a bit of bargaining theory) A homage to John Nash. Born Still alive (as far as Google knows). Spent.
Standard and Extended Form Games A Lesson in Multiagent System Based on Jose Vidal’s book Fundamentals of Multiagent Systems Henry Hexmoor, SIUC.
Game Theory Part 2: Zero Sum Games. Zero Sum Games The following matrix defines a zero-sum game. Notice the sum of the payoffs to each player, at every.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. GAME THEORY, STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING, AND BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS.
THE “CLASSIC” 2 x 2 SIMULTANEOUS CHOICE GAMES Topic #4.
Chapters 29, 30 Game Theory A good time to talk about game theory since we have actually seen some types of equilibria last time. Game theory is concerned.
Negotiation 101 Fairness and the importance of looking ahead.
Lecture 5 Introduction to Game theory. What is game theory? Game theory studies situations where players have strategic interactions; the payoff that.
1 What is Game Theory About? r Analysis of situations where conflict of interests is present r Goal is to prescribe how conflicts can be resolved 2 2 r.
Strategic Behavior in Business and Econ Static Games of complete information: Dominant Strategies and Nash Equilibrium in pure and mixed strategies.
1. 2 You should know by now… u The security level of a strategy for a player is the minimum payoff regardless of what strategy his opponent uses. u A.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Trust Signaling Maroš Servátka (University of Canterbury, NZ) Steven Tucker (University of Canterbury, NZ) Radovan Vadovič (ITAM, Mexico) June 2007 ESA,
Double Coordination in Small Groups Luigi Mittone, Matteo Ploner, Ivan Soraperra Computable and Experimental Economics Laboratory – University of Trento,
Dynamic Game Theory and the Stackelberg Model. Dynamic Game Theory So far we have focused on static games. However, for many important economic applications.
Yu-Hsuan Lin Catholic University of Korea, Korea University of York, U.K. 5 th Congress of EAAERE, Taipei, 06 th – 07 th August 2015.
OVERCOMING COORDINATION FAILURE THROUGH NEIGHBORHOOD CHOICE ~AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY~ Maastricht University Arno Riedl Ingrid M.T. Rohde Martin Strobel.
Chapter 12 Game Theory Presented by Nahakpam PhD Student 1Game Theory.
Correlated equilibria, good and bad: an experimental study
Mixed Strategies Keep ‘em guessing.
Tools for Decision Analysis: Analysis of Risky Decisions
Simultaneous Move Games: Discrete Strategies
Communication Complexity as a Lower Bound for Learning in Games
Chapter 6 Game Theory (Module 4) 1.
Chapter 29 Game Theory Key Concept: Nash equilibrium and Subgame Perfect Nash equilibrium (SPNE)
Presentation transcript:

1 Economics 776 Experimental Economics First Semester 2007 Topic 5: Coordination Games Assoc. Prof. Ananish Chaudhuri Department of Economics University of Auckland

2 Battle of the Sexes OperaBoxing Opera2, 10, 0 Boxing0, 01, 2 Three equilibria A third equilibrium in mixed strategies

3 Stag-Hunt Games ( Rousseau – A Discourse on Inequality, 1755 ) StagRabbit Stag8, 80, 5 Rabbit5, 05, 5 Three equilibria Payoff Dominant Secure/Risk Dominant A third equilibrium in mixed strategies

4 Examples of Coordination Problems Work norms Location of industries – economic geography Development of urban neighbourhoods Adoption of technology/diffusion of innovations –QWERTY keyboard Contributions to public goods –high contributions “efficient” equilibria while low contributions “inefficient equilibria” (Rabin, 1993) Bryant’s (1983) Keynesian model with a continuum of underemployment equilibria Diamond and Dybvig (1983) model of bank runs

5 Selection Criteria in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1990) Is the Nash equilibrium selected? Is the Payoff-dominant Nash Equilibirum selected? Do dominated strategies make a difference?

6 Selection Criteria in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1990) Hypotheses: The Pareto-dominant Nash equilibrium will be selected Dominated strategies are irrelevant to equilibrium selection The outcome will be a Nash equilibrium

, , , , , , , , , 420 Column Player Row Player Game 1 Symmetric game; strategy 2 is a dominant strategy for both players; Nash equilibrium (2, 2)

, 20555, 60585, , , , , , , 720 Column Player Row Player Game 2 Unique Nash equilibrium at (2, 3)

9

10

, , , ,350550, 5500, 0 30, 10000, 0600, 600 Column Player Row Player Game 3 Two Nash Equilibria at (1, 1) and (2, 2); latter is Payoff dominant; Joint maximum at (3, 3) but strategy 3 is dominated by strategy 1

, , , ,350550, 5500, 0 30, 7000, 0600, 600 Column Player Row Player Game 4 Two Nash Equilibria at (1, 1) and (2, 2); latter is Payoff dominant; Joint maximum at (3, 3) but strategy 3 is dominated by strategy 1

, , , ,350550, , 0 30, 7000, , 600 Column Player Row Player Game 5 Two Nash Equilibria at (1, 1) and (2, 2); latter is Payoff dominant; Joint maximum at (3, 3) but strategy 3 is dominated by both 1 and 2

, , , ,350550, , 0 30, 7000, , 600 Column Player Row Player Game 6 Two Nash Equilibria at (1, 1) and (2, 2); latter is Payoff dominant; Joint maximum at (3, 3) but strategy 3 is dominated by both 1 and 2

15 In Games 5 and 6 the threat of getting zero from failed coordination has been removed –In Games 3 and 4 if one player chooses 2 while the other chooses 3 then both players get zero In Games 5 and 6 the risk of a bad payoff from choosing strategy 2 (the strategy that is commensurate with the payoff dominant outcome) has been eliminated This might make the play of strategy 2 and the (2, 2) outcome more likely in Games 5 and 6.

16

17

18 Interpretation These results provide evidence against Pareto-dominance as a selection criteria for coordination games Indicate that cooperative, dominated strategies influence equilibrium selection At some point during the play of these games, some participants placed positive probability on an opponent playing the cooperative, dominated strategy

19 Interpretation Is strategy 3 important because it is the cooperative strategy or do players place prior probability on a dominated strategy even when it does not support the cooperative joint maximum? That is a player might believe that his opponent will be “cooperative” or will be “irrational” where the latter term refers to the play of a dominated strategy by a self-interested player

, , , ,350550, 5500, 0 30, 7000, 0500, 500 Column Player Row Player Game 7 Two Nash Equilibria at (1, 1) and (2, 2); latter is Payoff dominant; similar to Game 4

, , , ,350550, 5500, 0 30, 10000, 0500, 500 Column Player Row Player Game 8 Two Nash Equilibria at (1, 1) and (2, 2); latter is Payoff dominant; similar to Game 3

22 Interpretation The cooperative outcome now is (2, 2) If players place the same prior probability on their opponent playing the dominated strategy in Game 7 (8) as they did in Game 4 (3) the outcome observed in these two games should be the same If players place positive probability on their opponent playing the cooperative strategy rather than the dominated strategy players should expect that their opponent is more likely to play strategy 2 in Game 7 (8) as opposed to Game 4 (3).

23

24 Thus, when strategy 3 no longer supports the cooperative outcome players evidently place a lower probability on its paly by their rival. In Games the cooperative dominated strategy is chosen 11% of the time while in Games 7 – 8 it is played only 1.8% of the time.

25 The Minimum Effort Game (Van Huyck, Battalio and Beil, AER, 1990) Smallest Value of X Chosen Your Choice Of X

26 The Minimum Effort Game (Van Huyck, Battalio and Beil, AER, 1990) Coordination Game where each subject in a group of N subjects chooses an integer, c i from the set {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7}. Individual payoffs are determined for each subject by the payoff function  i = k + a[ min {c 1 …c n } ] – bc i Choosing k = $0.60, a = $0.20 and b = $0.10 defines the game depicted above Sometimes called a “weak-link” game

27 The Minimum Effort Game (Van Huyck, Battalio and Beil, AER, 1990) The Nash equilibria are located along the diagonal They are Pareto ranked with the highest payoff ($1.30) occurring when all players choose 7 But choosing 1 is the “secure” action since a player choosing 1 is guaranteed $0.70

28

29

30

31

32 Interpretation In large groups it seems subjects assign positive probability (albeit small) that someone will choose zero and this small probability results in coordination failure Because even if you think one person will choose “1” then your best response is clear – to choose “1” as well

33 Conclusions The inefficiency is primarily due to “strategic uncertainty” –Some subjects conclude that it is too risky to choose the strategy that leads to the payoff dominant outcome Deductive selection principles do not necessarily enable participants to coordinate to the payoff dominant equilibrium

34 Conclusions While participants seem able to coordinate to a Nash equilibrium, it is not given that they will be able to coordinate to the Payoff dominant outcome This then leads us to look for mechanisms that may facilitate such coordination This is what we turn to next

35 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) Explore the role of communication - “cheap talk” - in facilitating coordination Two games –Cooperative coordination game –Simple Coordination game

36 Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992)– Cooperative Coordination Game (CCG) , , , ,350550, 5500, 0 30, 10000, 0600, 600 Row player Column player

37 Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) – Simple Coordination Game (SCG) , , 0 20, , 1000 Row player Column player Risk dominant Payoff Dominant

38 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) Coordination failure results from the strategic uncertainty about the choices of others Thus allowing players to communicate might facilitate coordination by fostering optimistic beliefs about the play of a particular strategy.

39 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) If communication works to select an equilibrium then communication could resolve any coordination failures observed in games without cheap talk The coordination game with communication is a two-stage game between two players

40 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) In the first stage, player(s) communicate by sending messages to one another In the second stage actions are chosen Since the payoffs are independent of the actual messages, the messages are essentially “cheap talk”

41 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) Two alternative communication structures are examined –One way communication where only one of the two players can send a message –Two-way communication with both players being able to send messages, simultaneously

42 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) The equilibria of the two stage game can be complicated Let  i (m R,m C ) be the action chosen by player i = {R, C}, when the messages sent by the row and column players are respectively given by {m R,m C } For each pair of messages,  i (.) represents the mixed strategy over the possible actions

43 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) The equilibrium of this game is given by  * i (m R,m C ) for i = {R,C} coupled with a decision on what announcements to make in stage 1, {m R *,m C * } such that the announcements and the actions, conditional on the announcements, are best responses

44 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) Subjects play a sequence of one-shot games against anonymous opponents Actual game preceded by messages We look at the SCG first, followed by the CCG

45

46

47

48 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) Three conclusions: –In the game without communication, play of the (1, 1) equilibrium is observed –One way communication increases the frequency of the (2, 2) equilibrium, but a significant number of coordination failures were observed –Two-way communication resolves coordination failures; strategy 2 is played almost all the time

49 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) In the CCG, equilibrium (2, 2) is not always observed with one-way or two-way communication In the one-way communication treatments, strategy 2 is not always announced Announcements of 1 and 2 are generally followed by play of (1, 1) and (2, 2) respectively

50

51

52

53 Communication in Coordination Games - Cooper, Dejong, Forsythe and Ross (1992) Over half the announcements in two-way communication are different from strategy 2 Announcements of (2, 2) are generally followed by play of (2, 2)

54 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) A strict equilibrium in a game is defined as an assignment to each player of a strategy that is a unique best response for him when the others use the strategies assigned to them Equilibrium analysis often fails to determine a unique outcome in many games and fails to determine rational behaviour or predict the outcome

55 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) One conjecture is that players use deductive principles to solve the coordination problem A popular selction principle involves an appeal to pre-play communication An “arbitrator”/ “mediator”/ “referee” exists with the ability to make common information assignments to all the players in the game

56

57

58 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) Subjects divided into row and column players Each row and column pair meet only once Anonymous pairings An external arbiter makes “common knowledge” assignments –Announcements read out loud and also projected on the front wall of lab where all subjects could see the announcement

59 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) ROW CHOOSE ROW  AND COLUMN CHOOSE COLUMN . IF THE ROW PARTICIPANT CHOOSES ROW  THEN THE BEST THE COLUMN PARTICIPANT CAN DO IS TO CHOOSE COLUMN . IF THE COLUMN PARTICIPANT CHOOSES COLUMN  THEN THE BEST THAT THE ROW PARTICIPANT CAN DO IS TO CHOOSE ROW . NOTICE, from the payoff matrix, that if both the Row and Column participants follow the message then they both earn 8 experimental dollars. However, if one of the participants follows the message and the other does not, then both participants will earn a smaller amount.

60

61 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) Even without an arbiter a majority of the pairs implement the payoff dominant equilibrium Assignment to (1, 1) is implemented by 98% of the pairs Assignments to (2, 2) and (3, 3) are less credible and implemented by only 25% and 17% of the pairs

62 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) However one crucial difference between this paper and Cooper et al.’s (1990) finding is that is that in this paper the payoff-dominant outcome is also (probably?) risk dominant Thus the implementation of the (1, 1) equilibrium may not be terribly surprising

63

64 Credible Assignments In Coordination Games – Van Huyck, Gillette and Battalio (1992) Without an arbiter 70% of the pairs implemented the equal-payoff equilibrium in the asymmetric coordination game An assignment to (3, 3) – the preferred outcome for the column player – was credible to only 16% of the pairs Of the 58 row defections, 57 were to (2, 2) and of the 49 column defections, all 49 were to (2, 2) the equal-payoff outcome

65 Bangun, Chaudhuri, Prak and Zhou (2006) In the Van Huyck, Gillette, Battalio (1992) game there is no obvious conflict between payoff dominance and risk dominance The (1, 1) outcome is the most credible outcome in that game Will an assignment still work when there is a conflict between payoff and risk dominance?

66 Bangun, Chaudhuri, Prak and Zhou (2006) Payoff dominant Risk dominant

67 Bangun, Chaudhuri, Prak and Zhou (2006)

68 Bangun, Chaudhuri, Prak and Zhou (2006) Three treatments: 1.No assignment 2.Almost common knowledge of assignment 1.Announcement made public but not read aloud 3.Common Knowledge of assignment 1.Announcement made public and read aloud

69 Bangun, Chaudhuri, Prak and Zhou (2006)

70 Bangun, Chaudhuri, Prak and Zhou (2006)

71 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) Introduces new selection principle “loss avoidance” Players do not pick strategies that result in certain losses for them People only pick (and expect others to pick) strategies that will result in gains

72

73 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) Two important features of this game First, players’ payoff are decreasing with the (absolute) difference between their own action and the median. Hence a player’s best action is to choose the number the player believes will be the median Second, the seven pure strategy Nash equilibria are Pareto ranked

74 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) Now suppose the players have to pay a fee of 225 to play the game This is optional Subjects who opt out earn nothing In this case loss avoidance is coupled with a stronger selection principle – forward induction

75 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) In the presence of the “fee”, a subject’s decision to play the game, rather than opt out, implicitly communicates the subject’s expectations concerning the outcome of the game A subject will not choose an action than guarantees a lower payoff than what could be earned for sure by opting out Forward induction improves coordination because it shrinks the set of plausible equilibria in a game

76 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) Loss avoidance and forward induction are closely linked Loss avoidance applies if players assume that others will avoid certain losses Forward induction applies if players assume that others will avoid an opportunity loss by choosing an equilibrium which is better for them than an option they chose to forgo

77 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) In many games the two principles lead to the same set of selected strategies To isolate the effectiveness of loss avoidance C&C study two kinds of median action games In games with the option to opt out coordination improved which meant that the combination of forward induction and loss avoidance selected better equilibria

78 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) But improved coordination is also observed in games with no options and possible losses, where forward induction did not apply and loss avoidance did C&C conclude that loss avoidance could explain some of the improvement in coordination which previously had been attributed exclusively to forward induction

79 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) 9 subjects Publicly known cost to play the game Players can opt out –But this implies that number of players decrease which may itself facilitate coordination As the entry fee is increased, forward induction eliminates more and more of the 7 Nash equilibria facilitating coordination on the highest action equilibria

80 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) 4 sessions of “must play” 4 sessions of “opt out” 9 rounds First three rounds are indentical with zero entry cost and no “opt out” Entry fee raised to $1.85 in rounds 4 – 6 Entry fee further raised to $2.25 in rounds 7 - 9

81 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) Forward induction then suggests that subjects who opt to play in the “opt out” condition will then choose 6 or 7 (which pays $2.40 or $2.60 in equilibrium) when the entry fee is raised to $2.25 Forward induction predicts nothing in the “must play” condition Loss avoidance predicts that subjects will play 6 or 7 in both conditions since playing 5 yields only $2.20 in equilibrium not enough to cover the entry cost of $2.25

82

83 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) The crucial difference comes between round 6 and 7 in each session The null hypothesis that the distribution between actions differences between round 6 and 7 is the same can be rejected The differences however are not very strong

84 Loss Avoidance and Forward Induction in Coordination Games – Cachon and Camerer (1996) Conclusion: Loss Avoidance, absent forward induction, does not generate precisely the same changes in median actions (and improvement in coordination) that forward induction does but the changes are similar.