Sentential Logic. One of our main critical thinking questions was: Does the evidence support the conclusion? How do we evaluate whether specific evidence.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Commentary on Katalin Balog, In defense of the phenomenal concept strategy Assistant Prof. István Aranyosi, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey.
Advertisements

Artificial Intelligence
Geometry Logic.
TRUTH TABLES Section 1.3.
Computing Truth Value.
Truth Tables The aim of this tutorial is to help you learn to construct truth tables and use them to test the validity of arguments. Go To Next Slide.
TRUTH TABLES The general truth tables for each of the connectives tell you the value of any possible statement for each of the connectives. Negation.
Truth-Tables. Recap Deductive Validity We say that an argument is deductively valid when it has the following property: If the premises of the argument.
Logic & Critical Reasoning
Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
Sentential Logic 2. REVIEW Deductive Validity We say that an argument is deductively valid when it has the following property: If the premises of the.
Probability Theory. Validity A bar is obeying the law when it has the following property: If any of the patrons are below the age of 18, then that person.
Formal Probability Theory
An Introduction to Propositional Logic Translations: Ordinary Language to Propositional Form.
DEDUCTIVE REASONING: PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC Purposes: To analyze complex claims and deductive argument forms To determine what arguments are valid or not.
An Introduction to Propositional Logic Translations: Ordinary Language to Propositional Form.
Today’s Topics n Review Logical Implication & Truth Table Tests for Validity n Truth Value Analysis n Short Form Validity Tests n Consistency and validity.
For Friday, read chapter 2, sections 1-2 (pp ). As nongraded homework, do the problems on p. 19. Graded homework #1 is due at the beginning of class.
PHIL 120: Jan 8 Basic notions of logic
1 Math 306 Foundations of Mathematics I Math 306 Foundations of Mathematics I Goals of this class Introduction to important mathematical concepts Development.
Through the Looking Glass, 1865
1 Arguments in Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy.
Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;
The Language of Propositional Logic The Syntax and Semantics of PL.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Homework 3.
Intro to Discrete Structures
Chapter 8 Logic DP Studies. Content A Propositions B Compound propositions C Truth tables and logical equivalence D Implication and equivalence E Converse,
Lecture for Week Spring.   Introduction to Propositional Logic  Types of Proposition  Operator and Truth table Agenda.
Truth-Tables. Midterm Grades Grade Distribution.
BY: MISS FARAH ADIBAH ADNAN IMK. CHAPTER OUTLINE: PART III 1.3 ELEMENTARY LOGIC INTRODUCTION PROPOSITION COMPOUND STATEMENTS LOGICAL.
CSci 2011 Textbook ^Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications,  Rosen  6th Edition  McGraw Hill  2006.
Logic and Philosophy Alan Hausman PART ONE Sentential Logic Sentential Logic.
1 Chapter 7 Propositional and Predicate Logic. 2 Chapter 7 Contents (1) l What is Logic? l Logical Operators l Translating between English and Logic l.
1 Propositional Logic Proposition 2 Propositions can be divided into simple propositions and compound propositions. A simple (or basic) proposition is.
Predicate Logic. TRUTH-TABLE REMINDERS The problem people had the most trouble with was 1e: construct a truth-table for: (P & (~Q & R)) Many of you only.
Logic Review. FORMAT Format Part I 30 questions 2.5 marks each Total 30 x 2.5 = 75 marks Part II 10 questions Answer only 5 of them! Total 5 x 5 marks.
Introductory Logic PHI 120 Presentation: “Basic Concepts Review "
LOGIC Lesson 2.1. What is an on-the-spot Quiz  This quiz is defined by me.  While I’m having my lectures, you have to be alert.  Because there are.
Chapter 3: Semantics PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning March 13, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University.
Chapter 3: Introduction to Logic. Logic Main goal: use logic to analyze arguments (claims) to see if they are valid or invalid. This is useful for math.
MLS 570 Critical Thinking Reading Notes for Fogelin: Propositional Logic Fall Term 2006 North Central College.
Chapter 8 – Symbolic Logic Professor D’Ascoli. Symbolic Logic Because the appraisal of arguments is made difficult by the peculiarities of natural language,
Propositional Logic. Propositions Any statement that is either True (T) or False (F) is a proposition Propositional variables: a variable that can assume.
Today’s Topics Introduction to Proofs Rules of Inference Rules of Equivalence.
1 Propositional Logic Introduction. 2 What is propositional logic? Propositional Logic is concerned with propositions and their interrelationships. 
Metalogic. TWO CONCEPTIONS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE.
Sentential Logic.
Chapter 7 Evaluating Deductive Arguments II: Truth Functional Logic Invitation to Critical Thinking First Canadian Edition.
Mathematics for Comter I Lecture 2: Logic (1) Basic definitions Logical operators Translating English sentences.
Section 1.1. Propositions A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or false. Examples of propositions: a) The Moon is made of green.
TRUTH TABLES Edited from the original by: Mimi Opkins CECS 100 Fall 2011 Thanks for the ppt.
More Proofs. REVIEW The Rule of Assumption: A Assumption is the easiest rule to learn. It says at any stage in the derivation, we may write down any.
Metalogic Soundness and Completeness. Two Notions of Logical Consequence Validity: If the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true. Provability:
1 Section 7.1 First-Order Predicate Calculus Predicate calculus studies the internal structure of sentences where subjects are applied to predicates existentially.
Logical functors and connectives. Negation: ¬ The function of the negation is to reverse the truth value of a given propositions (sentence). If A is true,
PHIL102 SUM2014, M-F12:00-1:00, SAV 264 Instructor: Benjamin Hole
Logic.
2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary
Deductive Arguments.
Identifying Counterexamples
Propositional Logic.
Truth Tables Hurley
Midterm Discussion.
TRUTH TABLES.
Validity.
ID1050– Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning
Propositional Logic Computational Logic Lecture 2
Validity and Soundness, Again
Starting out with formal logic
Presentation transcript:

Sentential Logic

One of our main critical thinking questions was: Does the evidence support the conclusion? How do we evaluate whether specific evidence supports a specific conclusion? How do we answer this question?

Arguments The word ‘argument’ as it is used normally in English, means something like this: “An exchange of diverging or opposite views, typically a heated or angry one: ‘I've had an argument with my father’.”

Arguments In philosophy, we use the word ‘argument’ differently. A philosophical argument: Is not an exchange of views Doesn’t need to present opposing or contrary views Is not typically heated or angry.

Arguments Instead, a philosophical argument consists of two parts: the premises and the conclusion. The premises are the ‘evidence’ that are given in support of the conclusion. The conclusion is the ‘claim’ that the premises are supposed to support.

Example Premise 1: Either the butler is the murderer, or the gardener is the murderer. Premise 2: The butler is not the murderer. Therefore, Conclusion: The gardener is the murderer.

Relevance There is no requirement that the premises of an argument have anything to do with the consequent. For example, this is an argument: Premise: There are exactly 117 hairs on my hand. Conclusion: It’s half past three o’clock.

Deductive Validity We say that an argument is deductively valid when it has the following property: If the premises of the argument are true, then the conclusion of the argument must be true. A valid argument is “truth-preserving”: the truth of the premises gets passed on to the conclusion.

Note In ordinary English, the meaning of ‘valid’ is slightly different. Deductive validity is a relation between premises and conclusion. ‘Validity’ ordinarily means something like “true or relevant.” A ‘valid criticism’ is a criticism that is true or relevant to some issue being discussed.

Inductive Validity We say that an argument is inductively valid when it has the following property: If the premises are true, then the conclusion is likely to be true. An inductive argument probably preserves truth.

Example Suppose I eat at McDonald’s. I eat there 100 times. The first time I eat there, I get sick. The second time I eat there I get sick. In fact, on every occasion, each of the 100 times I ate there, I got sick every time.

Example Premise 1: The first time I ate at McDonald’s I got sick. Premise 2: The second time I ate at McDonald’s I got sick. Premises 3-99:… Premise 100: The 100 th time I ate at McDonald’s I got sick. Conclusion: Next time I will get sick again!

Example This is an inductively valid argument. If the premises are true, the conclusion is likely to be true too. But it is not a deductively valid argument. (Why?)

Soundness A sound argument is one that (i) is valid and (ii) has true premises. [And we can distinguish between deductively and inductively sound arguments.] Every sound argument is valid (by definition), but the reverse is not true. Some valid arguments are not sound.

Example Consider the following argument: Premise 1: All dogs have eight legs. Premise 2: I am a dog. Therefore, Conclusion: I have eight legs.

Example This argument is valid. If the premises are true, then the conclusion must also be true. If all dogs truly have eight legs, and I am truly a dog, then it is true that I have eight legs! However, the argument is not sound. The premises are false (and so is the conclusion).

Comprehension Questions Can arguments that are deductively valid have false conclusions? False premises? Can arguments that are not deductively valid have true conclusions? True premises? Can deductively sound arguments have false conclusions? Can arguments that are not deductively sound still be deductively valid?

Deductive Logic Deductive logic (often just called ‘logic’) is the study of deductively valid argument forms.

Argument Forms Example Premise 1: If horses had wings, they could fly. Premise 2: Horses cannot fly. Therefore, Conclusion: Horses don’t have wings.

Argument Forms Example Premise 1: If the butler committed the murder, then the murder weapon is the candlestick. Premise 2: The murder weapon is not the candlestick. Therefore, Conclusion: The butler did not commit the murder.

Argument Forms Example Premise 1: If Sally is free this evening, George will take her to dinner. Premise 2: George did not take Sally to dinner. Therefore, Conclusion: Sally was not free this evening.

Argument Forms Example All of these arguments share a deductively valid argument form: Premise 1: if A, then B. Premise 2: not B. Conclusion: not A. Any argument with this form is valid, no matter what ‘A’ and ‘B’ are.

Argument Forms Example Premise: Everyone is happy. Conclusion: There is not someone who is not happy. Premise: Everyone is F. Conclusion: There is not someone who is not F.

Argument Forms Example Premise: You can’t be happy and succesful. Conclusion: If you’re happy, you’re not successful. Premise: not (A and B). Conclusion: if A then not B.

Argument Forms Example Premise: Either Fred took the train or he took the ferry. Premise 2: Fred did not take the ferry. Conclusion: Fred took the train. Premise: Either A or B. Premise: not B Conclusion: A

Deductive Logic The goal of deductive logic is to identify deductively valid argument forms. We can use these as a formal test for validity: if an argument has a certain form, then that argument is deductively valid.

Invalidity An argument that is not valid is called invalid. Valid: If the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true. Invalid: The premises can be true while the conclusion is false.

Invalidity Unfortunately, there is no formal test for (deductive) invalidity. There is no way of looking at the form of an argument and telling that the premises do not guarantee the conclusion.

Fallacies A fallacy is an invalid argument***, usually one that might mislead someone into thinking it’s valid. ***Exception: Circular reasoning. We’ve already encountered a number of fallacies in this course: the fallacy of quoting out of context, the regression fallacy, the conjunction fallacy, the base rate neglect fallacy, etc.

No Formal Fallacies We must remember, however, that there are no formal fallacies (Wikipedia, for instance, is wrong about this very fact). There is no way to tell, simply by looking at an argument’s form that it is a bad argument (invalid). Logic can tell us that certain arguments are good, but it can’t tell us that the rest are bad.

Sentential Logic Sentential Logic (SL, also known as Propositional Logic, or the Propositional Calculus) is a formal logical system that represents logical relations among sentences (or propositions).

Syntax Every formal logical system has a syntax (or grammar) that defines which sequences of symbols are well-formed expressions (called “well-formed formulas” or WFFs) and which are ill-formed.

Sentential Variables In SL, simple sentences are represented by capital letters A, B, C, D, etc. These are sometimes called “sentence letters” or “sentential variables”– they’re variables, because A can represent the sentence “snow is white” or the sentence “snow is green” or the sentence “turtles love noodles,” or whatever. By convention, we prefer the letters P, Q, R, S… for sentential variables.

Connectives In English (and most other languages, but not for example in Piraha) various words allow you to make new, complex sentences out of other sentences. For example, consider the sentences “snow is green” and “turtles love noodles.” The word “and” lets us make the complex sentence “snow is green and turtles love noodles” out of these two simple sentences.

Examples of Connectives Snow is white. Grass is green. It is false that snow is white. Michael believes that snow is white. It is possible that snow is white. Snow is white and grass is green. If snow is white, then grass is green.

Truth-functional Connectives A connective is truth-functional if the truth of sentences involving the connective depends only on the truth of the sentences they have as parts. For example “and” is truth-functional. Whether a sentence like “P and Q” is true depends only on whether P is true and whether Q is true.

Truth-Functional Connectives So the sentence “snow is white and grass is green” is true, because “snow is white” is true and “grass is green” is true. Replace “snow is white” with any other true sentence, and the result is still true. If all you know about “P and Q” is that P is true and Q is true, then you know that “P and Q” is also true. Or if you know that Q is false, you know that “P and Q” is false. You don’t have to know what P and Q are.

Non-Truth-Functional Connectives Some connectives are not truth-functional. You can replace true sentences in them with other true sentences, and this can change whether they are true. Or you can replace false sentences in them with other false sentences, and this can change whether they are true.

Example 1.CY Leung believes that illegal structures at his house are OK. 2.It’s false that illegal structures at CY Leung’s house are OK. 3.It’s false that dogs have 17 legs. 4.CY Leung believes that dogs have 17 legs. Even if (1) is true, substituting another false sentence (3) for its false part (2) results in a false sentence.

Truth-Functional Connectives Sentential logic only contains truth-functional connectives, not non-truth-functional connectives like “CY Leung believes that___” or “It’s possible that____.”

SL Connectives Each truth-functional English connective is given an SL counterpart: “not…”: ~ (called “tilde”) “…and…”: & (called “ampersand”) “…or…”: v (called “wedge”) “if…then…”: → (called “arrow”) “…if, and only if,…”: ↔ (called “double- arrow”)

Definition of WFF i.All sentence letters are WFFs. ii.If φ is a WFF, then ~φ is a WFF. iii.If φ and ψ are WFFs, then (φ & ψ), (φ v ψ), (φ → ψ), (φ ↔ ψ) are also WFFs. iv.Nothing else is a WFF. Question: why do we use φ and ψ here instead of, for example, P and Q?

Demonstration Using the definition we can show that certain sequences of symbols are WFFs. For example (P↔(Q&~R)) is a WFF By (i), P, Q, and R are all WFFs. By (ii) ~R is a WFF. By (iii), since Q and ~R are WFFs, (Q&~R) is a WFF By (iii), since P and (Q&~R) are WFFs, (P↔(Q&~R)) is a WFF.

Ill-Formed Formulas Some sequences of symbols are not well- formed. Some examples include: ))PQ((( (~P) P & Q (P and Q)

Grammatical Categories (φ&ψ) is a conjunction where φ and ψ are the first and second conjunct respectively. (φvψ) is a disjunction where φ and ψ are the two disjuncts. (φ→ψ) is a conditional sentence where φ is the antecedent and ψ the consequent. (φ↔ψ) is a biconditional sentence. ~φ is the negation of φ.

Examples "(P&Q)" is a conjunction. "((P&Q) ∨ (R↔Q))" is a disjunction. "~(P→(Q ∨ S))" is the negation of "(P→(QvS))". "~(P&Q)" is the antecedent of "(~(P&Q)→((P&S)↔Q))".

Scope Every occurrence of a connective in a WFF has a scope. The scope of that occurrence is the smallest WFF that contains it. For example The scope of “&” in “(~(~P&Q)→P)” is “(~P&Q)” “(~(~P&Q)→P)” is not a WFF. “(~(~P&Q)→P)” is a WFF, but is bigger than “(~P&Q)”

Occurrences Notice that the same symbol can occur different times in the same formula, and that its different occurrences can have different scopes. ~((~P&Q)&(R↔Q))

Main Connective The main connective in a formula is the occurrence of the connective whose scope is widest (the scope of the occurrence of the connective = the formula). A formula is a conditional if its main connective is →, a conjunction if it’s &, a negation if it’s ~, etc.

Since SL connectives are truth-functional, we can summarize the truth-functions they stand for in a truth-table.

Negation φ~φ~φ TF FT

Conjunction φψ(φ & ψ) TTT TFF FTF FFF

Disjunction φψ(φ v ψ) TTT TFT FTT FFF

Biconditional φψ(φ ↔ ψ) TTT TFF FTF FFT

The Material Conditional φψ(φ → ψ) TTT TFF FTT FFT