Hume’s Problem of Induction 2 Seminar 2: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 14 September 2011 1.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Frontiers of Western Philosophy Empiricism
Advertisements

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers.
Empiricism on a priori knowledge
Confirmation and the ravens paradox 1 Seminar 3: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 21 September
Today’s Outline Hume’s Problem of Induction Two Kinds of Skepticism
René Descartes ( ) Father of modern rationalism. Reason is the source of knowledge, not experience. All our ideas are innate. God fashioned us.
Chapter 1 Critical Thinking.
NOTE: CORRECTION TO SYLLABUS FOR ‘HUME ON CAUSATION’ WEEK 6 Mon May 2: Hume on inductive reasoning --Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, section.
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Fall 2007 Dr. Robert Barnard.
Charting the Terrain of Knowledge-1
© Michael Lacewing Hume’s scepticism Michael Lacewing
HUME, KANT, HEGEL, SCHOPENHAUER
The Problem of Induction Reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’ by W. Salmon.
Hume’s Problem of Induction. Most of our beliefs about the world have been formed from inductive inference. (e.g., all of science, folk physics/psych)
Introduction/Hume’s Problem of Induction Seminar 1: Philosophy of the Sciences 6 September
Knowledge empiricism Michael Lacewing
Science and induction  Science and we assume causation (cause and effect relationships)  For empiricists, all the evidence there is for empirical knowledge,
Empiricism: David Hume ( ) Our knowledge of the world is based on sense impressions. Such “matters of fact” are based on experience (i.e., a posteriori.
Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College
Logic. what is an argument? People argue all the time ― that is, they have arguments.  It is not often, however, that in the course of having an argument.
BASIC CONCEPTS OF ARGUMENTS
The Problem of Knowledge. What new information would cause you to be less certain? So when we say “I’m certain that…” what are we saying? 3 things you.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
The Problem of Induction Reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’ by W. Salmon.
The Problem of Induction
Lecture 7: Ways of Knowing - Reason. Part 1: What is reasoning? And, how does it lead to knowledge?
Can Big Questions Be Begged?. Fallacies are mistakes in inference, BUT Begging the question is not a mistake in inference. Is it a fallacy at all? Robinson.
 According to philosophical skepticism, we can’t have knowledge of the external world.
© Michael Lacewing Reason and experience Michael Lacewing
Knowledge Belief and Truth By Prof.Dr Shadia Abd Elkader Prof.Dr Shadia Abd Elkader.
INDUCTION. GENUS: General principle DIFFERENTIA: which states that events in nature are REGULAR, not RANDOM ANALYTIC DEF’N // The past, while not a carbon.
1 Chapter 7 Propositional and Predicate Logic. 2 Chapter 7 Contents (1) l What is Logic? l Logical Operators l Translating between English and Logic l.
MIDTERM EXAMINATION THE MIDTERM EXAMINATION WILL BE ON FRIDAY, MAY 2, IN THIS CLASSROOM, STARTING AT 1:00 P.M. BRING A BLUE BOOK. THE EXAM WILL COVER:
Chapter 3: Knowledge Kant’s Revolution Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
Jewish, Christian, and Islamic Theories of Knowledge.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Reason “Crime is common, logic is rare” - Sherlock Holmes.
Deductive vs. Inductive Logic This course is about deductive logic. But it is important to know something about inductive logic.
The Problem of Induction. Aristotle’s Inductions Aristotle’s structure of knowledge consisted of explanations such as: Aristotle’s structure of knowledge.
David Hume ( ) An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding Revised, 11/21/03.
Epistemology – Study of Knowledge
HOW TO CRITIQUE AN ARGUMENT
An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Knowledge rationalism Michael Lacewing
Knowledge No number of observations can tell us anything with certainty about what we have not observed Hume’s problem David Hume ( )
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 8 Epistemology #1 By David Kelsey.
Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning.
Certainty and Truths.
1 The Empiricists: Hume Induction, Causation, Skepticism Soazig Le Bihan - University of Montana.
Epistemology (How do you know something?)  How do you know your science textbook is true?  How about your history textbook?  How about what your parents.
HUME 2 SKEPTICISM ABOUT CAUSAL KNOWLEDGE. David Hume This book cannot cause me to see words, but its constant conjunction with seen words.
The problem of induction
I think therefore I am - Rene Descartes. REASON (logic) It has been said that man is a rational animal. All my life I have been searching for evidence.
Chapter 1: The cosmological argument AQA Religious Studies: Philosophy of Religion AS Level © Nelson Thornes Ltd 2008 Revision.
WEEK 4: EPISTEMOLOGY Introduction to Rationalism.
Philosophy of science What is a scientific theory? – Is a universal statement Applies to all events in all places and time – Explains the behaviour/happening.
From Pyrrhonian Skepticism to Justification for Belief.
The Cosmological Argument Today’s lesson will be successful if: You have revised the ideas surrounding the cosmological argument and the arguments from.
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
Knowledge Empiricism 2.
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
Skepticism David Hume’s Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding and John Pollock’s “Brain in a vat” Monday, September 19th.
Skepticism David Hume’s Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding
Chapter 3 Philosophy: Questions and theories
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
Philosophy April 19th Objective Opener
Critical Thinking Lecture 2 Arguments
Presentation transcript:

Hume’s Problem of Induction 2 Seminar 2: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 14 September

Readings Required reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’, Section I, Chapter 7 of Richard Feldman’s book Epistemology pp (on course website) Optional reading: ‘Popper: Conjectures and Refutation’, Chapter 4 of Peter Godfrey Smith’s book Theory and Reality (which can be downloaded from HKU library) 2

Extra readings Stroud, Barry. Hume chapter 3 (on course website) Skyrms, Brian. Choice and Chance. Chapters 2 and 3 (On course website) Hume, David. An enquiry concerning human understanding. Section 4. (Go to and click on Hume) 3

Tutorials Tutorials will start next Friday 23 September Class 1: 1 PM - 2 PM seminar room 305 Class 2: 4 PM – 5 PM seminar room 305 Required reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’, Section I, Chapter 7 of Richard Feldman’s book Epistemology pp (on course website) Required reading and seminar handouts must be brought along to tutorials 4

Deductively valid arguments Def: An argument is deductively valid iff, necessarily, if its premises are true then its conclusion is true Example: P P or Q 5

Probabilistically good arguments Def: An argument is probabilistically good iff its premises make its conclusion probable (that is, its premises provide a good reason for believing its conclusion). A prima facie plausible example: All examined As have been Bs The next examined A will be a B 6

Types of inference Def: A deductively valid inference is an inference that occurs in a deductively valid argument Def: A probabilistically good inference is an inference that occurs in a probabilistically good argument 7

Modes of Justification According to Hume, there are (at most) four ways we can know (or justifiably believe) a proposition p Way 1 (A priori deductive reasoning): By either intuiting that p or by engaging in a chain of reasoning, each step of which is intuitively certain 8

Modes of Justification (cont) Note: According to Hume (and many others), if P is known on the basis of a priori deductive reasoning, then P is necessary Way 2 (A priori probabilistic reasoning): Start with what is intuitively obvious, and then make probabilistically good inferences based on that to get a justified (and probably true) belief. 9

Modes of Justification (cont) Way 3 (A posterior deductive reasoning): Start with our experiences and what is known on the basis of intuition, and make deductively valid inferences from there. Way 4 (A posteriori probable reasoning): Start with experiences in what is known on the basis of intuition and make probabilistically good inferences to some probably true conclusion 10

Deductive justification vs probabilistic justification Def: A belief is deductively justified (DJ) iff it is believed on the basis of either a prori deductive reasoning or a posteriori deductive reasoning Def: A belief is probabilistically justified (PJ) iff it is believed on the basis of either a priori probabilistic reasoning or a posteriori probabilistic reasoning 11

Hume’s inductive scepticism Hume held that beliefs that are based on inductive arguments are neither deductively justified nor probabilistically justified He therefore held that these beliefs are not justified at all As a dramatic illustration: Imagine an inductive skeptic who uses some anti-inductive form of inference. What could we say to change their mind? 12

Hume’s argument for inductive scepticism The sunrise argument (SRA): A) All days examined up untill now have been days on which the sun has risen B) The next examined day (tomorrow) will be a day on which the sun rises 13

Hume’s argument for inductive scepticism (cont) H1 (Hume’s assumption claim): SRA (and other inductive arguments) assume PF PF) The future is like the past H2: Given H1, (B) can only be justifiably believed on the basis of (A) iff PF can be justifiably believed (prior to B) 14

Hume’s overall argument that PF cannot be justified (1)If PF can be justified then either i) it can be justified by a deductively valid argument or ii) it can be justified by a probabilistically good argument (2)PF cannot be justified by a deductively valid argument (3)PF cannot be justified by a probabilistically good argument (4) PF cannot be justified 15

Argument for (2) (2a*) If PF can be deductively justified than either PF is necessary, or PF is a necessary consequence of our experiences (2b*) PF is neither necessary nor a necessary consequence of our experiences (2) PF cannot be deductively justified 16

Argument for (3) How could we give a probabilistically good argument for PF? Plausibly, the best we could do is give an argument like (PFA). PFA: PF has been true in the past PF will be true in the future 17

Argument for (3) (cont) But by Hume’s assumption claim H1, PFA assumes PF, and hence is circular 18

Response 1: The inductive defence of induction Induction has worked in the past, so we have good reason to think it will work in the future Objection: This defence is assumes that beliefs based on induction are justified, which is the very thesis that needs a defence. See Feldman and Skyrms for more discussion 19

Response 2: The pragmatic defence of induction Induction is at least as good as any other method performing beliefs about the unobserved or the future Objection: Even if this is true, it does not show that we are better off using induction rather than some other (equally good) method See Feldman and Skyrms for more discussion 20

Response 3: Popper’s response Inductive skepticism is true, but this is okay since science doesn’t need induction. This is because science consist in falsifying theories, rather than in justifying theories. Objection: Given inductive skepticism, in building a bridge, why should we use a well-tested theory instead of a brand new untested (and non-falsified) theory? See Godfrey Smith Theory and Reality Sec 4.2 and 4.5 for more discussion 21

Response 4: An a priori defence of induction In what sense does SRA assume PF? Answer 1: SRA assumes PF in the sense that PF (or something similar) needs to be added to SRA in order to turn it into a deductively valid argument Given answer 1, H1 is true but there is no reason to think that H2 is true 22

Stroud’s charitable interpretation of Hume To justifiably believe (B), it is not good enough to believe (A) and then believe (B). One must also believe (A) is a good reason for believing (B). Moreover, this belief must itself be justified. Hence, in order for someone to justifiably believe (B) on the basis of (A), (C) must be justifiably believed. (C) (A) is a good reason to believe (B) 23

Hume’s new challenge How can someone justifiably believe (C)? The a priori answer to Hume’s challenge: We can know (C) is true by intuiting that it is true, just as we can intuit logical truths (such as D) and simple probabilistic claims (such as E). 24

Hume’s new challenge (cont) D) Knowing that snow is white is a good reason for believing that either snow is white or grass is green E) Knowing that 999 marbles out of 1000 in a jar are black is a good reason to believe that a randomly selected marble from the jar is black 25

A consequence of the a priori answer If (C) can be known by intuition, then it must be necessarily true Is this the case? Could (C) have been false? 26

Will the a priori defence convince an inductive skeptic? Depends on why they are an inductive skeptic. If the defense undermines the skeptic’s reasons for being a sceptic, then possibly yes. If the skeptic is simply crazy then presumably no. 27

28 A new Humean inspired argument for inductive scepticism Suppose I am rational but haven’t had any experience. Then H1 and H2 have the same probability H1 = (A) and (B) H2 = (A) and not (B) Now suppose I have all my experiences (eg I have E) Having this happen doesn’t provide any more support to H1 than it does to H2

29 A new Humean inspired argument for inductive scepticism (cont) Therefore: Given I have had E, H1 is no more likely than H2 Therefore: I cannot justifiably believe H1 on the basis of my experience Therefore: The inference from (A) to (B) is not justified Conclusion: All inductive inferences are unjustified