Nash Equilibrium: Illustrations

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Chapter Twenty-Five Monopoly Behavior. How Should a Monopoly Price? u So far a monopoly has been thought of as a firm which has to sell its product at.
Advertisements

Imperfect competition Monopoly, monopolistic competition and oligopoly
OLIGOPOLY Chapter 16 1.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 4 1.
The World of Oligopoly: Preliminaries to Successful Entry
ECON 100 Tutorial: Week 9 office: LUMS C85.
Part 8 Monopolistic Competition and Oligopoly
© 2009 Pearson Education Canada 16/1 Chapter 16 Game Theory and Oligopoly.
Static Games and Cournot Competition
Economic Analysis for Business Session XIII: Oligopoly Instructor Sandeep Basnyat
Introduction to Game Theory
OT Anticompetitive consequence of the nationalization of a public enterprise in a mixed duopoly.
Game Theory: An Introduction Text: An Introduction to Game Theory by Martin J. Osborne.
Managerial Economics & Business Strategy
ECON 201 OLIGOPOLIES & GAME THEORY 1. FIGURE 12.4 DUOPOLY EQUILIBRIUM IN A CENTRALIZED CARTEL 2.
Copyright©2004 South-Western 16 Oligopoly. Copyright © 2004 South-Western BETWEEN MONOPOLY AND PERFECT COMPETITION Imperfect competition refers to those.
Week 13 Managerial Economics. Order of Business Homework Assigned Lectures Other Material Lectures for Next Week.
Managerial Economics & Business Strategy Chapter 9 Basic Oligopoly Models.
Static Games and Cournot Competition
Monopolistic Competiton. Assumptions Many sellers and many buyers Slightly different products Easy entry and exit (low barriers)
Figure 12.1 Perfect Price Discrimination
EC941 - Game Theory Francesco Squintani Lecture 3 1.
This Week’s Topics  Review Class Concepts -Sequential Games -Simultaneous Games -Bertrand Trap -Auctions  Review Homework  Practice Problems.
Types of Market Structure
Perfect Competition Asst. Prof. Dr. Serdar AYAN. Types of Markets u u Pure Competition or Perfect Competition u u Monopoly u u Duopoly u u Oligopoly u.
1 Introduction to Game Theory (Deterministic Model) Non-cooperative Game Theory with Complete Information Prof. Dr. Jinxing Xie Department of Mathematical.
EC941 - Game Theory Francesco Squintani 1 Lecture 1.
Auction Seminar Optimal Mechanism Presentation by: Alon Resler Supervised by: Amos Fiat.
1 Monopoly and Antitrust Policy Chapter IMPERFECT COMPETITION AND MARKET POWER imperfectly competitive industry An industry in which single firms.
Monopolistic Competition and Oligopoly
Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium is defined in terms of strategies, not payoffs Every player is best responding simultaneously (everyone optimizes) This.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 5 1.
Chapter 9: Static Games and Cournot Competition 1 Static Games and Cournot Competition.
Oligopoly Theroy1 Oligopoly Theory (4) Market Structure and Competitiveness Aim of this lecture (1) To understand the concept of HHI. (2) To understand.
Perfect competition, with an infinite number of firms, and monopoly, with a single firm, are polar opposites. Monopolistic competition and oligopoly.
Today n Oligopoly Theory n Economic Experiment in Class.
Monopoly and Oligopoly Announcements See web page for all exam information. Please get to exam rooms on time and have your CU ID ready to show the proctor.
Lecture 6 Cournot oligopoly. Cournot’s Model of Oligopoly Single good produced by n firms Cost to firm i of producing q i units: C i (q i ), where C i.
The Economic Framework For our purposes two basic sets of agents: –Consumers –Firms Interact through markets Faced with some economic environment or market.
Oligopolies & Game Theory
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Every product is sold in a market that can be considered one of the above market structures. For example: 1.Fast Food Market 2.The Market for Cars 3.Market.
Pashigian, Chapter 10, Exercise 3. Since marginal cost is zero, I assume each firm can produce the entire market demand. This sounds to me like a "winner.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Extensive Form Games With Perfect Information (Illustrations)
CHAPTER 27 OLIGOPOLY.
Ch. 16 Oligopoly. Oligopoly Only a few sellers offer similar or identical products Actions of any seller can have large impact on profits of other sellers.
Incomplete Information and Bayes-Nash Equilibrium.
Oligopoly and Game Theory Topic Students should be able to: Use simple game theory to illustrate the interdependence that exists in oligopolistic.
Oligopoly Introduction Derived from Greek word: “oligo” (few) “polo” (to sell) A few dominant sellers sell differentiated.
Micro Review Day 3 and 4. Perfect Competition 14 A Perfectly Competitive Market For a market to be perfectly competitive, six conditions must be met:
Copyright©2004 South-Western 17 Oligopoly. Copyright © 2004 South-Western BETWEEN MONOPOLY AND PERFECT COMPETITION Imperfect competition includes industries.
Lecture 7 Price competition. Bertrand’s Model of Oligopoly Strategic variable price rather than output. Single good produced by n firms Cost to firm i.
INTERMEDIATE MICROECONOMICS Topic 9 Oligopoly: Strategic Firm Interaction These slides are copyright © 2010 by Tavis Barr. This work is licensed under.
Microeconomics 1000 Lecture 13 Oligopoly.
Markets with Only a Few Sellers
Managerial Economics Game Theory
Static Games and Cournot Competition
Ch. 16 Oligopoly.
Games Of Strategy Chapter 4 Dixit, Skeath, and Reiley
Today Oligopoly Theory Economic Experiment in Class.
CHAPTER 12 OUTLINE Monopolistic Competition Oligopoly Price Competition Competition versus Collusion: The Prisoners’ Dilemma 12.5.
Lecture 9 Static Games and the Cournot Model
Static Games and Cournot Competition
Market Structure Wrap-Up
© 2007 Thomson South-Western
CH12 :Perfect Competition Asst. Prof. Dr. Serdar AYAN
Oligopoly and Game Theory
Presentation transcript:

Nash Equilibrium: Illustrations

Cournot’s Model of Oligopoly Single good produced by n firms Cost to firm i of producing qi units: Ci(qi), where Ci is nonnegative and increasing If firms’ total output is Q then market price is P(Q), where P is nonincreasing Profit of firm i, as a function of all the firms’ outputs:

Cournot’s Model of Oligopoly Strategic game: players: firms each firm’s set of actions: set of all possible outputs each firm’s preferences are represented by its profit

Example: Duopoly two firms Inverse demand: constant unit cost: Ci(qi) = cqi, where c < a

Example: Duopoly

Example: Duopoly Recall for a perfectly competitive firm, P=MC, so a – Q = c, or Q = a – c. Recall for a monopolist, MR=MC, so a – 2Q = c, or Q = (a – c)/2.

Example: Duopoly

Example: Duopoly Best response function is: Same for firm 2: b2(q) = b1(q) for all q.

Example: Duopoly

q1 = ( a - c - q2)/2 and q2 = (a - c - q1)/2 Example: Duopoly Nash equilibrium: Pair (q*1, q*2) of outputs such that each firm’s action is a best response to the other firm’s action or q*1 = b1(q*2) and q*2 = b2(q*1) Solution: q1 = ( a - c - q2)/2 and q2 = (a - c - q1)/2 q*1 = q*2 = (a - c)/3

Example: Duopoly

(q*1, q*2) = (( a - c)/3, (a - c)/3) Example: Duopoly Conclusion: Game has unique Nash equilibrium: (q*1, q*2) = (( a - c)/3, (a - c)/3) At equilibrium, each firm’s profit is p = ((a - c)2)/9 Total output 2/3(a- c) lies between monopoly output (a - c)/2 and competitive output a - c.

Cournot’s Model of Oligopoly Comparison of Nash equilibrium with collusive outcomes. Can both firms do better than the Cournot Nash? Yes! (if they can collude) Exercise 60.2 in Osborne Dependence of Nash equilibrium on number of firms. What happens to the Nash quantity and price as the number of firms grows? Exercise 61.1 in Osborne

Bertrand’s Model of Oligopoly Strategic variable price rather than output. Single good produced by n firms Cost to firm i of producing qi units: Ci(qi), where Ci is nonnegative and increasing If price is p, demand is D(p) Consumers buy from firm with lowest price Firms produce what is demanded

Bertrand’s Model of Oligopoly Strategic game: players: firms each firm’s set of actions: set of all possible prices each firm’s preferences are represented by its profit

Example: Duopoly 2 firms Ci(qi) = cqi for i = 1, 2 D(p) = a - p

Nash Equilibrium (p1, p2) = (c, c) Example: Duopoly Nash Equilibrium (p1, p2) = (c, c) If each firm charges a price of c then the other firm can do no better than charge a price of c also (if it raises its price it sells no output, while if it lowers its price it makes a loss), so (c, c) is a Nash equilibrium.

Example: Duopoly No other pair (p1, p2) is a Nash equilibrium since If pi < c then the firm whose price is lowest (or either firm, if the prices are the same) can increase its profit (to zero) by raising its price to c If pi = c and pj > c then firm i is better off increasing its price slightly if pi ≥ pj > c then firm i can increase its profit by lowering pi to some price between c and pj (e.g. to slightly below pj if D(pj) > 0 or to pm if D(pj) = 0).

Example: Duopoly p2 45 pm P2 = BR2(p1) P1 = BR1(p2) c c pm p1

Hotelling’s Model of Electoral Competition Several candidates run for political office Each candidate chooses a policy position Each citizen, who has preferences over policy positions, votes for one of the candidates Candidate who obtains the most votes wins.

Hotelling’s Model of Electoral Competition Strategic game: Players: candidates Set of actions of each candidate: set of possible positions Each candidate gets the votes of all citizens who prefer her position to the other candidates’ positions; each candidate prefers to win than to tie than to lose. Note: Citizens are not players in this game.

Example Two candidates Set of possible positions is a (one-dimensional) interval. Each voter has a single favorite position, on each side of which her distaste for other positions increases equally. Unique median favorite position m among the voters: the favorite positions of half of the voters are at most m, and the favorite positions of the other half of the voters are at least m.

Example Direct argument for Nash equilibrium (m, m) is an equilibrium: if either candidate chooses a different position she loses. No other pair of positions is a Nash equilibrium: If one candidate loses then she can do better by moving to m (where she either wins or ties for first place) If the candidates tie (because their positions are either the same or symmetric about m), then either candidate can do better by moving to m, where she wins.

The War of Attrition Two parties involved in a costly dispute E.g. two animals fighting over prey Each animal chooses time at which it intends to give up Once an animal has given up, the other obtains all the prey If both animals give up at the same time then they split the prey equally. Fighting is costly: each animal prefers as short a fight as possible. Also a model of bargaining between humans.

The War of Attrition Strategic game players: the two parties each player’s set of actions is [0,∞) (set of possible concession times) player i’s preferences are represented by payoff function

The War of Attrition If t1 = t2 then either player can increase her payoff by conceding slightly later (in which case she obtains the object for sure, rather than getting it with probability 1/2 ). If 0 < ti < tj then player i can increase her payoff by conceding at 0. If 0 = ti < tj < vi then player i can increase her payoff (from 0 to almost vi - tj > 0) by conceding slightly after tj.

The War of Attrition Thus there is no Nash equilibrium in which t1 = t2, 0 < ti < tj, or 0 = ti < tj < vi (for i = 1 and j = 2, or i = 2 and j = 1). The remaining possibility is that 0 = ti < tj and tj ≥ vi for i = 1 and j = 2, or i = 2 and j = 1. In this case player i’s payoff is 0, while if she concedes later her payoff is negative; player j’s payoff is vj, her highest possible payoff in the game.

The War of Attrition In no equilibrium is there any fight There is an equilibrium in which either player concedes first, regardless of the sizes of the valuations. Equilibria are asymmetric, even when v1 = v2, in which case the game is symmetric.

Auctions

Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction Assume every bidder knows her own valuation and every other bidder’s valuation for the good being sold Model each person decides, before auction begins, maximum amount she is willing to bid person who bids most wins person who wins pays the second highest bid.

Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction Strategic game: players: bidders set of actions of each player: set of possible bids (nonnegative numbers) preferences of player i: represented by a payoff function that gives player i vi - p if she wins (where vi is her valuation and p is the second-highest bid) and 0 otherwise.

Second-Price Sealed-Bid Auction Simple (but arbitrary) tie-breaking rule: number players 1, . . . , n and make the winner the player with the lowest number among those that submit the highest bid. Assume that v1 > v2 > · · · > vn.

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction One Nash equilibrium (b1, . . . , bn) = (v1, . . . , vn) Outcome: player 1 obtains the object at price v2; her payoff is v1 - v2 and every other player’s payoff is zero.

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction Reason: Player 1: If she changes her bid to some x ≥ b2 the outcome does not change (remember she pays the second highest bid) If she lowers her bid below b2 she loses and gets a payoff of 0 (instead of v1 - b2 > 0).

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction Players 2, . . . , n: If she lowers her bid she still loses If she raises her bid to x ≤ b1 she still loses If she raises her bid above b1 she wins, but gets a payoff vi - v1 < 0.

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction Another Nash equilibrium (v1, 0, . . . , 0) is also a Nash equilibrium Outcome: player 1 obtains the object at price 0; her payoff is v1 and every other player’s payoff is zero.

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction Reason: Player 1: any change in her bid has no effect on the outcome Players 2, . . . , n: if she raises her bid to x  v1 she still loses if she raises her bid above v1 she wins, but gets a negative payoff vi - v1.

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction For each player i the action vi weakly dominates all her other actions That is: player i can do no better than bid vi no matter what the other players bid.

Nash equilibria of second-price sealed-bid auction b’i < vi b’i = vi b’’i > vi I Payoff if b^-i  b’i vi - b^-i + II b’i < b^-i  vi III vi < b^-i  b’’i - IV b’’i < b^-i

First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction Strategic game: players: bidders actions of each player: set of possible bids (nonnegative numbers) preferences of player i: represented by a payoff function that gives player i vi - p if she wins (where vi is her valuation and p is her bid) and 0 otherwise.

Nash Equilibria of First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction (b1, . . . , bn) = (v2, v2, v3, . . . , vn) is a Nash equilibrium Reason: If player 1 raises her bid she still wins, but pays a higher price and hence obtains a lower payoff. If player 1 lowers her bid then she loses, and obtains the payoff of 0. If any other player changes her bid to any price at most equal to v2 the outcome does not change. If she raises her bid above v2 she wins, but obtains a negative payoff.

Nash Equilibria of First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction Property of all equilibria In all equilibria the object is obtained by the player who values it most highly (player 1) Argument: If player i ≠ 1 obtains the object then we must have bi > b1. But there is no equilibrium in which bi > b1 : If bi > v2 then i’s payoff is negative, so she can do better by reducing her bid to 0 If bi ≤ v2 then player 1 can increase her payoff from 0 to v1 - bi by bidding bi.

First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction As in a second-price auction, any player i’s action of bidding bi > vi is weakly dominated by the action of bidding vi : If the other players’ bids are such that player i loses when she bids bi, then it makes no difference to her whether she bids bi or vi If the other players’ bids are such that player i wins when she bids bi, then she gets a negative payoff bidding bi and a payoff of 0 when she bids vi

First-Price Sealed-Bid Auction Unlike a second-price auction, a bid bi < vi of player i is NOT weakly dominated by any bid. It is not weakly dominated by a bid bi’ < bi Neither by a bid bi’ > bi

Revenue Equivalence The price at which the object is sold, and hence the auctioneer’s revenue, is the same in the equilibrium (v1, v2, . . . , vn) of the second-price auction as it is in the equilibrium (v2, v2, v3, . . . , vn) of the first-price auction.