Ethical Theories: Conclusion Nanoethics Lecture III

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Introduction to Environmental Engineering Dr. Glass Environmental Ethics.
Advertisements

Non-Consequentialism
Ethical Theories: Introduction Nanoethics Lecture II
What matters is the motive
Why Ethics? Should I bring my personal beliefs into my organisation? Should not an employer determine standards of behaviour for all employees? Should.
Why Ethics? Should I bring my personal beliefs into my organisation? Should not my employer determine standards of behaviour for all employees? Should.
What is deontology?.
Ethics of Foreign Policy How can we judge our leaders’ actions?
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
Introduction to Ethics
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Ethical Theory.
Phil 160 Kant.
360 Business Ethics Chapter 4. Moral facts derived from reason Reason has three properties that have bearing on moral facts understood as the outcomes.
Ethics and Morality Theory Part 2 11 September 2006.
Kant’s deontological ethics
Michael Lacewing Deception and lies Michael Lacewing
Unit 4: Morality.
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Introduction to Ethical Theory I Last session: “our focus will be on normative medical ethics, i.e., how people should behave in medical situations” –
Chapter 4 Ethics, Law, Business. I. Ethics and Values Why Study Ethics? What is Ethics? Value Systems and Moral Beliefs 6 Influences That Shape Value.
Deontological Ethics Is saving someone from drowning a morally praiseworthy act? Do motives play any role in whether an act is morally praiseworthy?
THEORIES OF ETHICS PART 2 OF CHAPTER 12 (ETHICS).
Business Ethics Lecture Rights and Duties 1.
The Methodology of Moral Reasoning Nanoethics Lecture I Roderick T. Long Auburn Dept. of Philosophy.
Kantian ethics (& suicide): Kantian ethics (& suicide): Immanuel Kant ( ). A German philosopher. Ought implies Can Maxims Categorical Imperative.
Consequentialism Is it OK to inflict pain on someone else? Is it OK to inflict pain on someone else? What if it is a small amount of pain to prevent a.
Categorical and Practical Imperative
Ethical Principles: “Good” vs. “Right” Current Issues – LHS.
Objectives: SWBAT  Identify Immanuel Kant  Analyze Kantian Rationality  Identify and discuss the Categorical Imperative.
READING #1: “What This Book is About” Chapter One from The Ethics of Teaching.
Ethical Theories Unit 9 Ethical Awareness. What Are Ethical Theories? - Explain what makes an action right or wrong - Have an overview of major ethical.
Normative Ethical Theory: Utilitarianism and Kantian Deontology
Philosophy 2803 – Health Ethics Andrew Latus. Introduction Ethics Study of right and wrong/good and bad A Branch of Philosophy Central Question = “How.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant By David Kelsey.
The Sheriff’s Dilemma How to structure your answer.
Ethics.
AREA 1 GUIDING PRINCIPLES SECTION 3 Consequences (Utilitarian Ethics) Duty and Reason (Kantian Ethics)
From Last Time The good will is the only good thing in an ‘unqualified way” Acting from duty vs. acting in accord with duty Categorical vs. hypothetical.
Class 6 Kant. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) From Königsberg, Germany.
© Michael Lacewing Kant’s Categorical Imperative Michael Lacewing
Ethics and Morality Theory Part 3 30 January 2008.
The Moral Philosophy of Immanuel Kant The Ethics of Duty and Reason
Ethics Overview: Deontological and Teleological ( Consequentalist) Systems.
Jody Blanke, Professor Computer Information Systems and Law.
Utilitarianism Utilitarians focus on the consequences of actions.
Basic Framework of Normative Ethics. Normative Ethics ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’ or ‘controls’ ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’
Immanuel Kant: One More Time. The aim yesterday was to be able to.... Explain Kant’s theory on moral ethics Explain the term ‘categorical imperative’
A Study of Ethical Thinking You get to decide what works for You.
Introduction  Based on something other than the consequences of a person’s actions  Unlike Egoism  People should act in their own self-interest  Unlike.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
Immanuel Kant The Categorical Imperative. Part I. The Ethics of Duty More than any other philosopher, Kant emphasized the way in which the moral life.
Morality and the Moral Life. Ethics (moral philosophy): The study of morality using the methods of philosophy. Morality: Our beliefs about right and wrong.
Basic concepts in Ethics
Ethics: Theory and Practice
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant
Chapter 1: A Moral Theory Primer
Theory of Formalism.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Theory of Health Care Ethics
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Immanuel Kant
Kant’s Moral Theory.
Think Pair Share “Evaluating Kant’s Duties and Inclinations by Ranking Actions”
Intro to Philosophy Ethical Systems.
Deontology Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology.
History of Philosophy Lecture 17 Immanuel Kant’ Ethics
Professional Ethics (GEN301/PHI200) UNIT 2: NORMATIVE THEORIES OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS Handout # 2 CLO # 2 Explain the rationale behind adoption of normative.
Utilitarianism.
Presentation transcript:

Ethical Theories: Conclusion Nanoethics Lecture III Roderick T. Long Auburn Dept. of Philosophy

Utilitarianism A consequentialist theory: standard for the rightness of actions is beneficial consequences Differs from ethical egoism (another consequentialist theory) in appealing to beneficial consequences for everybody, not just oneself Claims the virtue of simplicity

Utilitarian Simplicity We ordinarily think beneficial results are one ethical consideration among others. Utilitarianism offers to explain the same range of ethical phenomena equally well by appealing solely to such results. This would make it a superior theory – IF in fact it explains them EQUALLY WELL. Does it?

Remember Our Problem Case for Utilitarianism Five patients need five different organ transplants Should we kill healthy patient and redistribute organs? Clash between ethical theory (might seem to say yes) and particular judgment (no)

Three Approaches to Solving Conflicts 1. Top-down: stick with the theory no matter what particular judgments it yields

Three Approaches to Solving Conflicts 2. Bottom-up: stick with particular judgments no matter what ethical theory they imply

Three Approaches to Solving Conflicts 3. Reflective equilibration: mutual adjustment Whatever they may say, in practice philosophers choose RE

Analogy With Science Top-down science (sticking with theory no matter what observations say) is bad science But bottom-up science is bad too: freshman chemist gets boiling water at 90º Mutual adjustment in science too Difference: philosophy conceptual, not empirical

Problem Case for Utilitarianism Three possible moves for utilitarian: 1. Reject utilitarianism (in favor of, say, Kantianism – respecting persons as ends) 2. Bite the bullet (accept killing the patient) 3. Reformulate utilitarianism so as to avoid the undesirable implication

Option 3 Distinguish act-utilitarianism from rule-utilitarianism Act-utilitarianism: choose each action in light of social utility Rule-utilitarianism: choose general rules in light of social utility; then choose each action in light of the rules

Rule-Utilitarianism Sometimes more effective to pursue goals indirectly Example: referees in sports – even if the purpose of the game is to give pleasure to the spectators, if the referee makes calls based on what will please the spectators, the spectators will soon be displeased

Rule-Utilitarianism Another example: Francis Bacon on “experiments of fruit” vs. “experiments of light” Value of science is technological goodies, not general insight for its own sake – but the best way to get the goodies is to pursue the insight Act as though the end doesn’t justify the means even though it does!

Rule-Utilitarian Solution to ODC A general policy of sacrificing few to many would make all of society nervous Make society better off by committing ourselves to a principle prohibiting such sacrifices We produce better results by acting as if we care about something other than results

Rule-Egoism Incidentally, Ethical Egoists can (and do) make this same move – which is why the conduct they recommend is usually not radically different from ordinary morality

Rule-Egoism Some ethical egoists combine rule-egoism with virtue ethics, advising us to choose the act that expresses the virtues that it is in our self-interest to cultivate

More Moves for the Anti-Utilitarian Is rule-utilitarianism stable? If you try to treat means as though they were ends – well, do you really regard them as ends, or don’t you? If you do, you’re no longer a utilitarian. If you don’t, what keeps you from sliding back into act-utilitarianism?

More Moves for the Anti-Utilitarian Does rule-utilitarianism identify the right reasons that killing the patient is wrong? Even if killing the patient would indirectly be bad for society, is that the main reason it’s wrong? Or is it what it does to the patient?

More Moves for the Anti-Utilitarian Does it even make sense for a benefit to some people to make up for a harm to others – when they’re different people? Does utilitarianism treat society as though it were on big person?

More Moves for the Anti-Utilitarian And so the dialectic continues ….

Immanuel Kant Perhaps the most influential philosopher of the 18th century A deontologist A leading opponent of all forms of consequentialism

Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant Morality is a set of imperatives (commands, instructions) There are two kinds of imperatives: hypothetical (“conditional”) and categorical (“unconditional”)

Hypothetical and Categorical Imperatives A hypothetical imperative is one that is rationally binding on you only if you happen to have a certain goal (example: recipes, driving directions) A categorical imperative is one that is rationally binding on you regardless of what goals you happen to have

Hypothetical and Categorical Imperatives It’s part of the concept of morality that moral imperatives are categorical: you can’t get off the hook for a moral duty because you happen not to care about a certain goal But if consequentialism were true, then morality would be a recipe for producing good consequences – and so there’d be no reason to care about morality if you happened not to care about those consequences

Hypothetical and Categorical Imperatives 1. If consequentialism were true, morality would be a hypothetical imperative. 2. But morality is a categorical imperative, not a hypothetical one. 3. Therefore: consequentialism is false. So concludes Kant.

Immanuel Kant Whenever I act for a given reason, I’m showing that I regard it as OK to act that way for that reason. So I’m endorsing a general practice of acting that way for that reason. Suppose I lie to get money. I’m thereby endorsing a general practice of lying to get money.

Immanuel Kant But the point of lying is to deceive someone, and lying can be a successful means of deceit only because truth-telling is the norm. So in order to lie I have to want most people most of the time to tell the truth. Thus by lying I’m committing myself simultaneously to lying being the rule and lying being the exception.

Immanuel Kant So by lying my will contradicts itself. Self-contradiction is irrational, regardless of what one’s goals are. So a prohibition on lying is rationally binding regardless of what one’s goals are – it’s a categorical imperative.

Immanuel Kant In general: it’s contrary to reason to make special exceptions for ourselves to rules we expect everyone else to follow. When you do that, you’re simultaneously endorsing the rule and endorsing the exception – and so contradicting yourself.

Kant’s Answer to the ODC If I seek the general welfare by sacrificing individuals, I thereby authorize anybody to do likewise – I authorize sacrifice as a general policy. But it wouldn’t work as a general policy – it would frustrate the goal. Therefore killing the one patient is contradictory.

Kant’s Answer to the ODC Note: what’s wrong with killing the one patient is not that a general policy of doing so would have bad results. Kant’s moral theory doesn’t depend on the goodness or badness of results. Rather, what’s wrong with it is that there’s an internal contradiction involved in willing it – you simultaneously affirm two mutually inconsistent principles.

Kant’s Answer to the ODC Analogy: what’s wrong with believing that 2 + 2 = 5? It’s not that believing 2 + 2 = 5 has bad results (even though it probably would) but rather that it’s inherently illogical, even apart from its results.

Who’s Right?