Philosophy 224 Many Persons?.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
“Without confusion, without change, without division, without separation” Heresies about Christ: Part Two 7 November 2010.
Advertisements

Chapter 7 The Christian apologists: interacting with Gnosticism and other “heresies”
The early church councils: Christological controversy and definition
Chapter 9 Trinitarian debate.
Chapter 13 Eastern Christianity splits from the West.
Summa Theologica Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
Chapter 3 Light to the Gentiles
Chapter 4 Trinity: The Christian God
Towards the Doctrine of the Trinity 1.The ‘Spirit-fighters’. 2.The models of the trinity. 3.Apollinarian controversy. 4.The Second Ecumenical Council:
Chapter 6 The God of the Philosophers.  What is Scholastic Philosophy?  Answer: The Christian philosophy of the Middle Ages that combined faith and.
The Catholic Church and its Theory of Authority. The Papal Insignia.
 The One, the Many, and Inerrancy › The One (Divinity) in the Many (Humanity) › The One (Divinity) over the Many (Humanity) › The Many (Humanity) over.
Philosophy 224 Many Persons?. Beothius Boethius was a Roman statesman and philosopher of the Western Roman Empire. He was born in Rome in 480 CE and died,
INCARNATION A PROBLEM FOR SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY? 1d: Miracles.
Trinitarianism and Monotheism
The Creed 3 “..God The Father…” “IN THE NAME OF THE FATHER, AND OF THE SON, AND OF THE HOLY SPIRIT”
HUMAN NATURE IN THE CHRISTIAN TRADITION PAUL’S LETTERS PHILOSOPHY 224.
How the Cappadocians Understood the Trinity By Edwin Ramos Jr.
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons: Broad on Personal Belief.
Philosophy 224 Responding to the Challenge. Taylor, “The Concept of a Person” Taylor begins by noting something that is going to become thematic for us.
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons Pt. 2. Legenhausen, “Is God a Person?” Legenhausen uses the little observed fact that Islam is a religion in which the majority.
PHIL/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Ontological Argument.
MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY. STOICISM  The term "Stoicism" derives from the Greek word "stoa," referring to a colonnade, such as those built outside or inside.
Philosophy 224 Aristotle’s Vision of the Human. Aristotle ( B.C.E.) Unlike Socrates and Plato, Aristotle was not an Athenian. ◦ He was born in.
Phil/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 2: The Moral Argument.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 8: Augustine and Self-Consciousness.
Scholasticism St. Thomas Aquinas. Scholasticism System used by medieval intellectuals to apply reason or logical analysis to the Church's basic theological.
On the Doctrine of the Trinity. God is Love? If God is essentially self-emptying love (agape), then the question is raised: to whom or to what is God.
St. Thomas Aquinas--Introduction A product of the middle ages. Mankind seen as one community, christendom, subject to one eternal law and government.
High Medieval Western Theology. Western Theology How can we describe the intellectual trends of the age? How can we describe the intellectual trends of.
Theology of Athanasius and later developments 1.Athanasius of Alexandria, On the Incarnation. 2. The doctrine of the Trinity according to the Cappadocian.
Philosophy 219 Introduction to Moral Theory. Theoretical vs. Practical  One of the ways in which philosophers (since Aristotle) subdivide the field of.
Ontological Argument (Ontological is from the Greek word for being, named by Kant) Learning Objectives To know the specification content To know the meaning.
Why the Apostles’ Creed? History of the Apostles’ Creed Significance of the Apostles’ Creed A Rubric for the Creed Beginning of the Apostles’ Creed.
St. Thomas Aquinas Ronald F. White, Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy
Seeing the Father John 14:5-11.
Introduction to Moral Theory
High Medieval Western Theology
Systematic Theology I Theology Proper
St. Thomas Aquinas
Philosophical Anthropology
Ibn Rushd on religious faith & reason
A Mickey Mouse Guide to the Ontological Argument
Introduction to Moral Theory
What Makes Someone a Christian?
The Stoics were a school of Greek philosophy that started just after the time of Aristotle, and remained popular for about 400 years. human nature as part.
Catechism Essentials of Faith
Good News: Aging through a Theological Lens
Presentation of Business Ethics
What Makes Someone a Christian?
Introduction to Moral Theory
So you want Socratic Seminar?
THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY& THEOLOGY, NATURAL & SUPERNATURAL ENDS A SYNTHESIS OF THE PLATONIC-AUGUSTINIAN & THE ARISTOTELIAN.
What does it mean to be eternal?
God and Creation.
Philosophy 224 Divine Persons: Pt. 1.
Describe this object: Does it help describe it further by saying it exists?
What is a Theory of Human Nature?
The Big Picture Deductive arguments - origins of the ontological argument Deductive proofs; the concept of ‘a priori’. St Anselm - God as the greatest.
Boethius on the Problem of Freedom & Determinism
Metaphysics & Epistemology
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 3a Evaluating an argument
Does God have a plan or purpose for us?
Discipleship: An Introduction to Systematic Theology and Apologetics
Trinitarianism and Monotheism
Human Nature in the Christian Tradition Paul’s Letters
Catechism of the Catholic Church
A Personal approach from a Christian background
St. Anselm of Canterbury ( )
Get Real – Authentic Christianity
Presentation transcript:

Philosophy 224 Many Persons?

Boethius was a Roman statesman and philosopher of the Western Roman Empire. He was born in Rome in 480 CE and died, imprisoned, in Pavia in 524 CE. He was a learned man, who wrote a number of influential theological works, as well as commentaries on Aristotle’s logical works. He also made a number of original contributions to Aristotelian logic. Christian martyr, killed the story goes for his support of Justin against the Arian Osiligoth Theodoric. Beothius

The Person as a Natural Kind One of the most significant contributions Boethius makes to our account of Personhood is his argument that “person” is a natural kind. Natural Kind: real, rather than artificial or arbitrary grouping. This claim is implicit in the psyche-ologies of Plato and Aristotle, but Boethius spells it out. The Person as a Natural Kind

Reflecting on its status as a natural kind, Boethius then goes on to draw some significant conclusions. The first is to specify whether as a natural kind, personhood belongs to the order of substances or accidents. Substance: independently existing thing; Accident: things which inhere in substances. His position is that persons are substances. Substance or Accident

What kind of substance? Not all substances are persons, however. Persons are substances with specific qualities: life, sensibility, reason. Moreover, persons are always particular substances, rather than universals. Max, rather than Human Being. What kind of substance?

Boethius then proceeds, through an analysis of the relevant Greek philosophical terms, to explore the connections between the notions of essence, substance and person. His ultimate aim is a theological one: clarifying the essential, substantial and personal status of God. His conclusion: God is one essence (whatness or nature), three substances (substrates), and three persons (the Trinity). It’s all Greek to Me.

The key distinction for Boethius is that between essence or nature on the one hand and person on the other. “…Nature is the specific property of any substance, and Person is the individual substance of a rational nature” (35c2). This is a distinction that must be maintained for Boethius, because it has significant Christological implications. Ousia or Hypostasis

What Kind of Person is Christ Both human and divine, Christ poses a real puzzle for the doctrine of persons. Some had argued that Christ is two persons. Boethius denies this because it maintains a overly rigid understanding of the relationship between essence and person. According to him, Christ is one person in whom the two substances have been united (through the common element of reason). What Kind of Person is Christ

Archbishop of Canterbury, Doctor of the Church; born in 1033 at Aosta a Burgundian town near Lombardy, died 21 April, 1109. As significant a philosopher as he was a theologian, Anselm’s work is dominated by the then emerging question of the status of universals. A realist (as opposed to a nominalist), Anselm’s arguments, though more radical than would later become common, were central to the debate that raged at the heart of scholasticism. His most famous contribution to the history of philosophy was his ontological argument for the existence of God. St. Anselm

Despite Boethius’s best efforts, questions about the personhood of God and of Christ continued to animate significant theological debate for the next 500 years. Anselm weighs in with his own account, grounded in the sort of ontological consideration which animates his famous proof. In this case, it comes in the form of a reflection on the notion of a ‘supreme good’ (39c1). How Many persons?

Let’s Start with Three Persons Anselm assumes the trinitarian view point. The problem is how to account for it in a way that satisfies reason. Unlike Boethius, Anselm insists that the trinitarian account has to be grounded in an account of the substantial unity of God. This may not be so much a disagreement as a terminological difference, with Anselm using ‘substance’ in place of Boethius’s ‘essence.’ Let’s Start with Three Persons

What’s the deal with Incarnation? Anselm is responding in this piece to questions raised to the trinitarian doctrine on the basis of the specific nature of the divine persons. Christ was a man. If God and Christ are one, doesn’t that mean God was a man. Specifically, doesn’t that mean God farts (is incarnate)? What’s the deal with Incarnation?

Christ is the only one who farts. The answer lies for Anselm in the doctrine of the person. It’s not in God’s substance that the incarnation is to be understood, but in a specific person of God, Christ. “…the Son of God, who is one nature with the Father and a different person from the Father…” (40c1). Christ is the only one who farts.

Anselm also weighs in on the question of the character of the personhood of Christ. Like Boethius, Anselm insists that Christ be understood as one person. His argument is that we should understand Christ’s person like God’s person: “one nature is several persons, and the several persons are one nature…so in Christ the divine being is a person and the human being is a person, and yet there is one person and are not two persons” (42c1-2). Christ is one person.