Bottom-up parsing Pumping Theorem for CFLs

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Context-Free and Noncontext-Free Languages
Advertisements

The Pumping Lemma for CFL’s
Theory of Computation CS3102 – Spring 2014 A tale of computers, math, problem solving, life, love and tragic death Nathan Brunelle Department of Computer.
Pushdown Automata Chapter 12. Recognizing Context-Free Languages Two notions of recognition: (1) Say yes or no, just like with FSMs (2) Say yes or no,
Pushdown Automata Part II: PDAs and CFG Chapter 12.
1 Introduction to Computability Theory Lecture7: The Pumping Lemma for Context Free Languages Prof. Amos Israeli.
Lecture 15UofH - COSC Dr. Verma 1 COSC 3340: Introduction to Theory of Computation University of Houston Dr. Verma Lecture 15.
Transparency No. P2C5-1 Formal Language and Automata Theory Part II Chapter 5 The Pumping Lemma and Closure properties for Context-free Languages.
CS5371 Theory of Computation Lecture 9: Automata Theory VII (Pumping Lemma, Non-CFL)
Transparency No. P2C5-1 Formal Language and Automata Theory Part II Chapter 5 The Pumping Lemma and Closure properties for Context-free Languages.
1 Background Information for the Pumping Lemma for Context-Free Languages Definition: Let G = (V, T, P, S) be a CFL. If every production in P is of the.
Today Chapter 2: (Pushdown automata) Non-CF languages CFL pumping lemma Closure properties of CFL.
FORMAL LANGUAGES, AUTOMATA AND COMPUTABILITY
INHERENT LIMITATIONS OF COMPUTER PROGRAMS CSci 4011.
Pushdown Automata (PDA) Part 2 While I am distributing graded exams: Design a PDA to accept L = { a m b n : m  n; m, n > 0} MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation.
CSE 3813 Introduction to Formal Languages and Automata Chapter 8 Properties of Context-free Languages These class notes are based on material from our.
Pushdown Automata (PDA) Intro
Context-Free and Noncontext-Free Languages Chapter 13 1.
1 L= { w c w R : w  {a, b}* } is accepted by the PDA below. Use a construction like the one for intersection for regular languages to design a PDA that.
1 CD5560 FABER Formal Languages, Automata and Models of Computation Lecture 11 Midterm Exam 2 -Context-Free Languages Mälardalen University 2005.
Pushdown Automata Chapters Generators vs. Recognizers For Regular Languages: –regular expressions are generators –FAs are recognizers For Context-free.
Cs3102: Theory of Computation Class 8: Non-Context-Free Languages Spring 2010 University of Virginia David Evans.
Context-Free and Noncontext-Free Languages Chapter 13 1.
Closure Properties Lemma: Let A 1 and A 2 be two CF languages, then the union A 1  A 2 is context free as well. Proof: Assume that the two grammars are.
Non-CF Languages The language L = { a n b n c n | n  0 } does not appear to be context-free. Informal: A PDA can compare #a’s with #b’s. But by the time.
Context-Free and Noncontext-Free Languages Chapter 13.
Chapter 8 Properties of Context-free Languages These class notes are based on material from our textbook, An Introduction to Formal Languages and Automata,
Transparency No. P2C5-1 Formal Language and Automata Theory Part II Chapter 5 The Pumping Lemma and Closure properties for Context-free Languages.
Donghyun (David) Kim Department of Mathematics and Physics North Carolina Central University 1 Chapter 2 Context-Free Languages Some slides are in courtesy.
CSCI 4325 / 6339 Theory of Computation Zhixiang Chen Department of Computer Science University of Texas-Pan American.
Pushdown Automata Chapter 12. Recognizing Context-Free Languages Two notions of recognition: (1) Say yes or no, just like with FSMs (2) Say yes or no,
 2004 SDU Lecture8 NON-Context-free languages.  2004 SDU 2 Are all languages context free? Ans: No. # of PDAs on  < # of languages on  Pumping lemma:
Bottom-up parsing Pumping Theorem for CFLs MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation.
Complexity and Computability Theory I Lecture #12 Instructor: Rina Zviel-Girshin Lea Epstein.
MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation How many regular/non-regular languages are there? Closure properties of Regular Languages (if there is time) Pumping.
Context-Free and Noncontext-Free Languages Chapter 13.
Closed book, closed notes
Properties of Context-Free Languages
CSE 105 theory of computation
Deterministic FA/ PDA Sequential Machine Theory Prof. K. J. Hintz
PDAs Accept Context-Free Languages
Lecture 17 Oct 25, 2011 Section 2.1 (push-down automata)
PARSE TREES.
Lecture 14 Grammars – Parse Trees– Normal Forms
Context-Free Languages
Summary.
Non-Context-Free Languages
Chapter Fourteen: The Context-Free Frontier
Definition: Let G = (V, T, P, S) be a CFL
Context-Free Grammars
COSC 3340: Introduction to Theory of Computation
Pumping Lemma for Context-free Languages
Properties of Context-Free Languages
The Pumping Lemma for CFL’s
Compilers Principles, Techniques, & Tools Taught by Jing Zhang
MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation
COSC 3340: Introduction to Theory of Computation
CS21 Decidability and Tractability
Chapter 2 Context-Free Language - 02
MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation
CS21 Decidability and Tractability
Pumping Theorem Examples
Pushdown Automata (PDA) Part 2
Recap lecture 42 Row language, nonterminals defined from summary table, productions defined by rows, rules for defining productions, all possible productions.
CSE 105 theory of computation
Pumping Theorem for CFLs
MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation
MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation
Intro to Theory of Computation
Presentation transcript:

Bottom-up parsing Pumping Theorem for CFLs MA/CSSE 474 Theory of Computation Bottom-up parsing Pumping Theorem for CFLs Exam next Friday!

Recap: Going One Way Lemma: Each context-free language is accepted by some PDA. Proof (by construction): The idea: Let the stack do the work. Two approaches: Top down Bottom up

Example from Yesterday L = {anbmcpdq : m + n = p + q} 0 (p, , ), (q, S) (1) S  aSd 1 (q, , S), (q, aSd) (2) S  T 2 (q, , S), (q, T) (3) S  U 3 (q, , S), (q, U) (4) T  aTc 4 (q, , T), (q, aTc) (5) T  V 5 (q, , T), (q, V) (6) U  bUd 6 (q, , U), (q, bUd) (7) U  V 7 (q, , U), (q, V) (8) V  bVc 8 (q, , V), (q, bVc) (9) V   9 (q, , V), (q, ) 10 (q, a, a), (q, ) 11 (q, b, b), (q, ) input = a a b c c d 12 (q, c, c), (q, ) 13 (q, d, d), (q, ) trans state unread input stack Trace through the first few steps, and suggest that students do the rest for practice

The Other Way to Build a PDA - Directly L = {anbmcpdq : m + n = p + q} (1) S  aSd (6) U  bUd (2) S  T (7) U  V (3) S  U (8) V  bVc (4) T  aTc (9) V   (5) T  V input = a a b c d d a//a b//a c/a/ d/a/ b//a c/a/ d/a/ 1 2 3 4 c/a/ d/a/ d/a/

Notice the Nondeterminism Machines constructed with the algorithm are often nondeterministic, even when they needn't be. This happens even with trivial languages. Example: AnBn = {anbn: n  0} A grammar for AnBn is: A PDA M for AnBn is: (0) ((p, , ), (q, S)) [1] S  aSb (1) ((q, , S), (q, aSb)) [2] S   (2) ((q, , S), (q, )) (3) ((q, a, a), (q, )) (4) ((q, b, b), (q, )) But transitions 1 and 2 make M nondeterministic. A directly constructed machine for AnBn can be deterministic. Constructing deterministic top-down parsers major topic in CSSE 404.

Bottom-Up PDA Parse the string: id + id * id The idea: Let the stack keep track of what has been found. Discover a rightmost derivation in reverse order. Start with the sentence and try to "pull it back" (reduce) to S. (1) E  E + T (2) E  T (3) T  T  F (4) T  F (5) F  (E) (6) F  id Reduce Transitions: (1) (p, , T + E), (p, E) (2) (p, , T), (p, E) (3) (p, , F  T), (p, T) (4) (p, , F), (p, T) (5) (p, , )E( ), (p, F) (6) (p, , id), (p, F) Shift Transitions: (7) (p, id, ), (p, id) (8) (p, (, ), (p, () (9) (p, ), ), (p, )) (10) (p, +, ), (p, +) (11) (p, , ), (p, ) Parse the string: id + id * id A bottom-up parser is sometimes called a shift-reduce parser. Show how it works on id + id * id State stack remaining input transition to use p  id + id * id 7 p id + id * id 6 p F + id * id 4 p T + id * id 2 p E + id * id 10 p +E id * id 7 p id+E * id 6 p F+E * id 4 p T+E * id 11 p *T+E id 7 p id*T+E  6 p F*T+E  3 p T+E  1 p E  0 q   When the right side of a production is on the top of the stack, we can replace it by the left side of that production… …or not! That's where the nondeterminism comes in: choice between shift and reduce; choice between two reductions.

A Bottom-Up Parser The outline of M is: M = ({p, q}, , V, , p, {q}), where  contains: ● The shift transitions: ((p, c, ), (p, c)), for each c  . ● The reduce transitions: ((p, , (s1s2…sn.)R), (p, X)), for each rule X  s1s2…sn. in G. Undoes an application of this rule. ● The finish-up transition: ((p, , S), (q, )). Top-down parser discovers a leftmost derivation of the input string (If any). Bottom-up parser discovers a rightmost derivation (in reverse order)

Acceptance by PDA  derived from CFG Much more complex than the other direction. Nonterminals in the grammar we build from the PDA M are based on a combination of M's states and stack symbols. It gets very messy. Takes 10 dense pages in the textbook. I think we can use our limited course time better.

How Many Context-Free Languages Are There? (we had a slide just like this for regular languages) Theorem: There is a countably infinite number of CFLs. Proof: ● Upper bound: we can lexicographically enumerate all the CFGs. ● Lower bound: {a}, {aa}, {aaa}, … are all CFLs. The number of languages is uncountable. Thus there are more languages than there are context-free languages. So there must be some languages that are not context-free.

Languages That Are and Are Not Context-Free a*b* is regular. AnBn = {anbn : n  0} is context-free but not regular. AnBnCn = {anbncn : n  0} is not context-free. Is every regular language also context-free? Yes. A Regular grammar is a CFG. A FSM is a PDA that does not use its stack.

Showing that L is Context-Free Techniques for showing that a language L is context-free: 1. Exhibit a context-free grammar for L. 2. Exhibit a PDA for L. 3. Use the closure properties of context-free languages. Unfortunately, these are weaker than they are for regular languages. union,reverse, concatenation, Kleene star intersection of CFL with a regular language NOT intersection, complement, set difference

CFL Pumping Theorem

Showing that L is Not Context-Free Recall the basis for the pumping theorem for regular languages: A DFSM M. If a string is longer than the number of M's states… For a CFL, we will use the grammar instead of the PDA, but the idea is the same: If the string is long enough, something is repeated, and can be pumped. Why would it be hard to use a PDA to show that long strings from a CFL can be pumped?

Some Tree Geometry Basics The height h of a tree is the length of the longest path from the root to any leaf. The branching factor b of a tree is the largest number of children associated with any node in the tree. Theorem: The length of the yield (concatenation of leaf nodes) of any tree T with height h and branching factor b is  bh. Done in CSSE 230. We are not talking about binary trees here, we are talking about trees where different nodes may have different numbers of children

A Review of Parse Trees A parse tree, (a.k.a. derivation tree) derived from a grammar G = (V, , R, S), is a rooted, ordered tree in which: ● Every leaf node is labeled with an element of   {}, ● The root node is labeled S, ● Every interior node is labeled with an element of N(i.e., V - ), ● If m is a non-leaf node labeled X and the children of m (left-to-right on the tree) are labeled x1, x2, …, xn, then the rule X  x1 x2 … xn is in R. Comment on last statement: If this were not true, it would not be a parse tree for a string in G.

From Grammars to Trees Given a context-free grammar G: ● Let n be the number of nonterminal symbols in G. ● Let b be the branching factor of G Suppose that a tree T is generated by G and no nonterminal appears more than once on any path: The maximum height of T is: The maximum length of T’s yield is: Branching factor of G: largestnumber of symbols on the right side of a rule in R. Answers: n , bn.

The Context-Free Pumping Theorem We use parse trees, not machines, as the basis for our argument. Let L = L(G), and let wL. Let T be a parse tree for w such that has the smallest possible number of nodes among all trees based on a derivation of w from G. Suppose L(G) contains a string w such that |w| is greater than bn. Then its parse tree must look like (for some nonterminal X): X[1] is the lowest place in the tree for which this happens. I.e., there is no other X in the derivation of x from X[2]. Recall: If no nonterminal appears twice in a path, then the length of the string is <= bn So there has to be an X like this. Pick a path with at least two Xs and let X[1] and X[2] be the two lowest occurrences of X in the tree. x is the yield from X[2] v and y are the rest of the yield from X[1] u and z are the rest of w The Pumping Theorem is sometimes called the "uvxyz theorem"

The Context-Free Pumping Theorem There is another derivation in G: S * uXz * uxz, in which, at X[1], the nonrecursive rule that leads to x is used instead of the recursive one that leads to vXy. So uxz is also in L(G). Derivation of w At X[1] We derive x instead of vXwy

The Context-Free Pumping Theorem There are infinitely many derivations in G, such as: S * uXz * uvXyz * uvvXyyz * uvvxyyz Those derivations produce the strings: uv2xy2z, uv3xy3z, uv4xy4z, … So all of those strings are also in L(G).

The Context-Free Pumping Theorem If rule1 is X  Xa, we could have v = . If rule1 is X  aX, we could have y = . But it is not possible that both v and y are . If they were, then the derivation S * uXz * uxz would also yield w and it would create a parse tree with fewer nodes. But that contradicts the assumption that we started with a parse tree for w with the smallest possible number of nodes.

The Context-Free Pumping Theorem The height of the subtree rooted at [1] is at most: So |vxy|  . Answers: n+1, bn+1

The Context-Free Pumping Theorem If L is a context-free language, then k  1 ( strings w  L, where |w|  k (u, v, x, y, z ( w = uvxyz, vy  , |vxy|  k, and q  0 (uvqxyqz is in L)))). Write it in contrapositive form. Try to do this before going on. Now we want to write it in contrapositive form, so we can use it to show a language is NOT context-free. k  1 ( string w  L, where |w|  k (u, v, x, y, z (w = uvxyz, vy  , |vxy|  k, and q  0 (uvqxyqz is not in L)))).

Pumping Theorem contrapositive We want to write it in contrapositive form, so we can use it to show a language is NOT context-free. Original: If L is a context-free language, then k  1 ( strings w  L, where |w|  k (u, v, x, y, z (w = uvxyz, vy  , |vxy|  k, and q  0 (uvqxyqz is in L)))). Contrapositive: If k  1 ( string w  L, where |w|  k (u, v, x, y, z (w = uvxyz, q  0 (uvqxyqz is not in L)))), then L is not a CFL.

Regular vs. CF Pumping Theorems Similarities: ● We don't get to choose k. ● We choose w, the string to be pumped, based on k. ● We don't get to choose how w is broken up (into xyz or uvxyz) ● We choose a value for q that shows that w isn’t pumpable. ● We may apply closure theorems before we start. Things that are different in CFL Pumping Theorem: ● Two regions, v and y, must be pumped in tandem. ● We don’t know anything about where in the strings v and y will fall in the string w. All we know is that they are reasonably “close together”, i.e., |vxy|  k. ● Either v or y may be empty, but not both.