Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan
Advertisements

VOTING. BINARY METHODS Choosing between only two alternatives at time Majority Rule Pairwise voting Condorcet Method Agenda Paradox.
Voting Methods Continued
Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Algorithmic Game Theory Uri Feige Robi Krauthgamer Moni Naor Lecture 9: Social Choice Lecturer: Moni Naor.
Math 1010 ‘Mathematical Thought and Practice’ An active learning approach to a liberal arts mathematics course.
The Voting Problem: A Lesson in Multiagent System Based on Jose Vidal’s book Fundamentals of Multiagent Systems Henry Hexmoor SIUC.
Mark Wang John Sturm Sanjeev Kulkarni Paul Cuff.  Basic Background – What is the problem?  Condorcet = IIA  Survey Data  Pairwise Boundaries = No.
IMPOSSIBILITY AND MANIPULABILITY Section 9.3 and Chapter 10.
Chapter 1: Methods of Voting
VOTING SYSTEMS Section 2.5.
Math for Liberal Studies.  We have studied the plurality and Condorcet methods so far  In this method, once again voters will be allowed to express.
MAT 105 Fall  Harder than you might think  There are many examples in history where the results were disputed  We care about this because we.
Math for Liberal Studies.  In most US elections, voters can only cast a single ballot for the candidate he or she likes the best  However, most voters.
MAT 105 Spring  There are many more methods for determining the winner of an election with more than two candidates  We will only discuss a few.
Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010 Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010.
Excursions in Modern Mathematics Sixth Edition
MAT 105 Spring  As we have discussed, when there are only two candidates in an election, deciding the winner is easy  May’s Theorem states that.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Math for Liberal Studies.  There are many more methods for determining the winner of an election with more than two candidates  We will only discuss.
CPS Voting and social choice
How is this math? Mathematics is essentially the application of deductive reasoning to the study relations among patterns, structures, shapes, forms and.
Social choice (voting) Vincent Conitzer > > > >
Section 1.1, Slide 1 Copyright © 2014, 2010, 2007 Pearson Education, Inc. Section 11.2, Slide 1 11 Voting Using Mathematics to Make Choices.
MAT 105 Spring  We have studied the plurality and Condorcet methods so far  In this method, once again voters will be allowed to express their.
Voting Geometry: A Mathematical Study of Voting Methods and Their Properties Alan T. Sherman Dept. of CSEE, UMBC March 27, 2006.
Arrow’s Theorem The search for the perfect election decision procedure.
CPS Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Slide 15-1 Copyright © 2005 Pearson Education, Inc. SEVENTH EDITION and EXPANDED SEVENTH EDITION.
MAT 105 Spring  Harder than you might think  There are many examples in history where the results were disputed  We care about this because we.
The Mathematics of Voting Chapter 1. Voting theory: application of methods that affect the outcome of an election. Sec 1: Preference Ballots and Schedules.
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan An Introduction to Manipulability Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method The Manipulability.
Chapter 15 Section 1 - Slide 1 Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. AND.
Math for Liberal Studies.  We have seen many methods, all of them flawed in some way  Which method should we use?  Maybe we shouldn’t use any of them,
Let’s take a class vote. How many of you are registered to vote?
Decisions How do we make choices?. Types of Decisions Individual—our opinion is our decision. Group—Individual opinions are expressed by voting(at least.
Warm-Up Rank the following soft drinks according to your preference (1 being the soft drink you like best and 4 being the one you like least)  Dr. Pepper.
The Mathematics of Voting Chapter 1. Preference Ballot A Ballot in which the voters are asked to rank the candidates in order of preference. 1. Brownies.
The mathematics of voting The paradoxes of democracy.
Excursions in Modern Mathematics, 7e: Copyright © 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. 1 The Mathematics of Voting 1.1Preference Ballots and Preference.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan Voting and Social Choice Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Other Voting Systems for Three.
Voting System Review Borda – Sequential Run-Off – Run-Off –
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem
 Harder than you might think  There are many examples in history where the results were disputed.
1.
Voting: Does the Majority Always Rule?
Voting and Apportionment
1 The Mathematics of Voting
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
1.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
8.2 Voting Possibilities and Fairness Criteria
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Introduction If we assume
Elections with More Than Two Candidates
Social Choice Theory [Election Theory]
VOTING.
Section 15.2 Flaws of Voting
5-2 Election Theory Flaws of Voting.
Voting systems Chi-Kwong Li.
Voting and social choice
MAT 105 Fall 2008 More Voting Methods.
Quiz – 1/24 - Friday How many people voted in the election?
Section 14.1 Voting Methods.
Flaws of the Voting Methods
CPS Voting and social choice
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Presentation transcript:

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan For All Practical Purposes Voting and Social Choice Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates Plurality Voting Borda Count Sequential Pairwise Voting Hare System Insurmountable Difficulties: Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem A Better Approach? Approval Voting Mathematical Literacy in Today’s World, 7th ed. 1 © 2006, W.H. Freeman and Company

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Voting and Social Choice Social Choice Theory Social choice deals with how groups can best arrive at decisions. The problem with social choice is finding good procedures that will turn individual preferences for different candidates into a single choice by the whole group. Example: Selecting a winner of an election using a good procedure that will result in an outcome that “reflects the will of the people” Preference List Ballot A preference list ballot consists of a rank ordering of candidates showing the preferences of one of the individuals who is voting. A vertical list is used with the most preferred candidate on top and the least preferred on the bottom. Throughout the chapter, we assume the number of voters is odd (to help simplify and focus on the theory). Furthermore, in the real world, the number of voters is often so large that ties seldom occur. 2

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Majority rule for elections with only two candidates (and an odd number of voters) is a voting system in which the candidate preferred by more than half the voters is the winner. Three Desirable Properties of Majority Rule All voters are treated equally. Both candidates are treated equally. It is monotone. May’s Theorem – Among all two-candidate voting systems that never result in a tie, majority rule is the only one that treats all voters and both candidates equally and is monotone. Monotone means that if a new election were held and a single voter were to change his or her ballot from voting for the losing candidate to voting for the winning candidate (and everyone else voted the same), the outcome would be the same. 3

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method This method requires that each candidate go head-to-head with each of the other candidates. Condorcet’s Voting Paradox – With three or more candidates, there are elections in which Condorcet’s method yields no winners. A beats B, 2 out of 3; and B beats C, 2 out of 3; and C beats A, 2 out of 3 — No winner! Rank Number of Voters (3) First A B C Second B C A Third C A B For the two candidates in each contest, record who would win (using majority rule) from each ballot cast. To satisfy Condorcet, the winning candidate must defeat every other candidate one-on-one. The Marquis de Condorcet (1743 – 1794) was the first to realize the voting paradox: If A is better than B, and B is better than C, then A must be better than C. Sometimes C is better than A—not logical! 4

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates When there are three or more candidates, it is more unlikely to have a candidate win with a majority vote. Many other voting methods exist, consisting of reasonable ways to choose a winner; however, they all have shortcomings. We will examine four more popular voting systems for three or more candidates: Four voting systems, along with their shortcomings: Plurality Voting and the Condorcet Winning Criterion The Borda Count and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives Sequential Pairwise Voting and the Pareto Condition The Hare System and Monotonicity 5

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Plurality Voting and the Condorcet Winning Criterion Only first-place votes are considered. Even if a preference list ballot is submitted, only the voters’ first choice will be counted—it could have just been a single vote cast. The candidate with the most votes wins. The winner does not need a majority of votes, but simply have more votes than the other candidates. Example: Find the plurality vote of the 3 candidates and 13 voters. Number of Voters (13) Rank 5 4 3 1 First A C B Second Third The candidate with the most first-place votes wins. Count each candidate’s first-place votes only. (A has the most.) A = 5, B = 4, C = 4 A wins. 6

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Plurality Voting and the Condorcet Winning Criterion Example: 2000 Presidential Election (Plurality fails CWC.) Condorcet Winner Criterion (CWC) is satisfied if either is true: If there is no Condorcet winner (often the case) - or - If the winner of the election is also the Condorcet winner This election came down to which of Bush or Gore would carry Florida. Result: George W. Bush won by a few hundred votes. Gore, however, was considered the Condorcet winner: It is assumed if Al Gore was pitted against any one of the other three candidates, (Bush, Buchanan, Nader), Gore would have won. Manipulability occurs when voters misrepresents their preference rather than “throw away” their vote. 7

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Borda Count and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives The Borda Count Borda Count is a rank method of voting that assigns points in a nonincreasing manner to the ordered candidates on each voter’s preference list ballot and then add these points to arrive at a group’s final ranking. For n candidates, assign points as follows: First-place vote is worth n − 1 points, second-place vote is worth n − 2 points, and so on down to…Last place vote is worth n − n = 0, zero points. The candidate’s total points are referred to as his/her Borda score. Example: Total the Borda score of each candidate. A = 2 + 2 + 2 + 0 + 0 = 6 B = 1 + 1 + 1 + 2 + 2 = 7 C = 0 + 0 + 0 + 1 + 1 = 2 B has the most, B wins. Rank Number of Voters (5) Points First A B 2 Second C 1 Third Another way: Count the occurrences of letters below the candidate—for example, there are 7 “boxes” below B 8

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Borda Count and Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (Borda fails IIA.) A voting system is said to satisfy independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) if it is impossible for candidate B to move from nonwinner status to winner status unless at least one voter reverses the order in which he or she had B and the winning candidate ranked. If B was a loser, B should never become a winner, unless he moves ahead of the winner (reverses order) in a voter’s preference list. Example showing that Borda count fails to satisfy IIA: B went from loser to winner and did not switch with A! Suppose the last two voters change their ballots (reverse the order of just the losers). This should not change the winner. Original Borda Score: A=6, B=5, C=4 New Borda Score: A= 6, B=7, C=2 Rank Number of Voters (5) First A C Second B Third Rank Number of Voters (5) First A B Second C Third 9

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Sequential Pairwise Voting and the Pareto Condition Sequential pairwise voting starts with an agenda and pits the first candidate against the second in a one-on-one contest. The losers are deleted and the winner then moves on to confront the third candidate in the list, one on one. This process continues throughout the entire agenda, and the one remaining at the end wins. Example: Who would be the winner using the agenda A, B, C, D for the following preference list ballots of three voters? Using the agenda A, B, C, D, start with A vs. B and record (with tally marks) who is preferred for each ballot list (column). Rank Number of Voters (3) First A C B Second D Third Fourth A vs. B II I A vs. C I II C vs. D I II Candidate D wins for this agenda. A wins; B is deleted. C wins; A is deleted. D wins; C is deleted. 10

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Sequential Pairwise Voting and the Pareto Condition Pareto Condition (Sequential Pairwise fails Pareto.) Pareto condition states that if everyone prefers one candidate (in this case, B) to another candidate (D), then this latter candidate (D) should not be among the winners of the election. Pareto condition is named after Vilfredo Pareto (1848 – 1923), Italian economist. From the last example: D was the winner for the agenda A, B, C, D. However, each voter (each of the three preference lists columns) preferred B over D. If everyone preferred B to D, then D should not have been the winner! Not fair! Rank Number of Voters (3) First A C B Second D Third Fourth Different agenda orders can change the outcomes. For example, agenda D, C, B, A results in A as the winner. 11

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream The Hare System and Monotonicity The Hare system proceeds to arrive at a winner by repeatedly deleting candidates that are “least preferred” (meaning at the top of the fewest ballots). If a single candidate remains after all others have been eliminated, he/she alone is the winner. If two or more candidates remain and they all would be eliminated in the next round, then these candidates would tie. For the Hare system, delete the candidate with the least first-place votes: A = 5, B = 4, and C = 4 Since B and C are tied for the least first place votes, they are both deleted and A wins. Number of Voters (13) Rank 5 4 3 1 First A C B Second Third 12

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream The Hare System and Monotonicity Monotonicity (The Hare system fails monotonicity.) Monotonicity says that if a candidate is a winner and a new election is held in which the only ballot change made is for some voter to move the former winning candidate higher on his or her ballot, then the original winner should remain a winner. In a new election, if a voter moves a winner higher up on his preference list, the outcome should still have the same winner. Number of Voters (13) Rank 5 4 3 1 First A C B Second Third In the previous example, A won. For the last voter, move A up higher on the list (A and B switch places). Round 1: B is deleted. Round 2: C moves up to replace B on the third column. However, C wins—this is a glaring defect! The Hare system, introduced by Thomas Hare in 1861, was known by names such as the “single transferable vote system.” In 1962, John Stuart Mill described the Hare system as being “among the greatest improvements yet made in the theory and practice of government.” 13

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Insurmountable Difficulties: Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem Kenneth Arrow, an economist in 1951, proved that finding an absolutely fair and decisive voting system is impossible. With three or more candidates and any number of voters, there does not exist—and there never will exist—a voting system that always produces a winner, satisfies the Pareto condition and independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA), and is not a dictatorship. If you had an odd number of voters, there does not exist—and there never will exist—a voting system that satisfies both the CWC and IIA and that always produces at least one winner in every election. Kenneth Arrow 14

Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream A Better Approach Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream A Better Approach? Approval Voting Approval Voting Under approval voting, each voter is allowed to give one vote to as many of the candidates as he or she finds acceptable. No limit is set on the number of candidates for whom an individual can vote; however, preferences cannot be expressed. Voters show disapproval of other candidates simply by not voting for them. The winner under approval voting is the candidate who receives the largest number of approval votes. This approach is also appropriate in situations where more than one candidate can win, for example, in electing new members to an exclusive society such as the National Academy of Sciences or the Baseball Hall of Fame. Approval voting is also used to elect the secretary general of the United Nations. Approval voting was proposed independently by several analysts in 1970s. 15