Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan
Advertisements

The Computational Difficulty of Manipulating an Election Tetiana Zinchenko 05/12/
VOTING. BINARY METHODS Choosing between only two alternatives at time Majority Rule Pairwise voting Condorcet Method Agenda Paradox.
Presented by: Katherine Goulde
Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Math 1010 ‘Mathematical Thought and Practice’ An active learning approach to a liberal arts mathematics course.
Voting and social choice Looking at a problem from the designers point of view.
How “impossible” is it to design a Voting rule? Angelina Vidali University of Athens.
IMPOSSIBILITY AND MANIPULABILITY Section 9.3 and Chapter 10.
Chapter 1: Methods of Voting
VOTING SYSTEMS Section 2.5.
Math for Liberal Studies.  In most US elections, voters can only cast a single ballot for the candidate he or she likes the best  However, most voters.
Making Group Decisions Mechanism design: study solution concepts
MAT 105 Spring  There are many more methods for determining the winner of an election with more than two candidates  We will only discuss a few.
Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010 Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010.
Excursions in Modern Mathematics Sixth Edition
MAT 105 Spring  As we have discussed, when there are only two candidates in an election, deciding the winner is easy  May’s Theorem states that.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Math for Liberal Studies.  There are many more methods for determining the winner of an election with more than two candidates  We will only discuss.
CPS Voting and social choice
How is this math? Mathematics is essentially the application of deductive reasoning to the study relations among patterns, structures, shapes, forms and.
Social choice (voting) Vincent Conitzer > > > >
Voting Geometry: A Mathematical Study of Voting Methods and Their Properties Alan T. Sherman Dept. of CSEE, UMBC March 27, 2006.
CPS Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Slide 15-1 Copyright © 2005 Pearson Education, Inc. SEVENTH EDITION and EXPANDED SEVENTH EDITION.
MAT 105 Spring  Harder than you might think  There are many examples in history where the results were disputed  We care about this because we.
Elections and Strategic Voting: Condorcet and Borda E. Maskin Harvard University.
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan An Introduction to Manipulability Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method The Manipulability.
Chapter 15 Section 1 - Slide 1 Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. AND.
Math for Liberal Studies.  We have seen many methods, all of them flawed in some way  Which method should we use?  Maybe we shouldn’t use any of them,
Let’s take a class vote. How many of you are registered to vote?
Voting Methods Examples of Voting Methods (other than majority rules) –Plurality –Borda Count –Hare System –Sequential Pairwise –Approval Voting.
Copyright 2013, 2010, 2007, Pearson, Education, Inc. Section 15.1 Voting Methods.
Warm-Up Rank the following soft drinks according to your preference (1 being the soft drink you like best and 4 being the one you like least)  Dr. Pepper.
How Should Presidents Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study.
The Mathematics of Voting Chapter 1. Preference Ballot A Ballot in which the voters are asked to rank the candidates in order of preference. 1. Brownies.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan Voting and Social Choice Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Other Voting Systems for Three.
Voting System Review Borda – Sequential Run-Off – Run-Off –
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem
 Harder than you might think  There are many examples in history where the results were disputed.
1.
Voting: Does the Majority Always Rule?
Voting and Apportionment
Choosing the Lesser Evil: Helping Students Understand Voting Systems
1 The Mathematics of Voting
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Applied Mechanism Design For Social Good
8.2 Voting Possibilities and Fairness Criteria
Algorithmic Analysis of Elections: Voting Rules and Manipulability (minicourse) Piotr Faliszewski AGH University Kraków, Poland.
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Introduction If we assume
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
1.3 The Borda Count Method.
Elections with More Than Two Candidates
Warm Up – 1/23 - Thursday How many people voted in the election?
VOTING.
Section 15.2 Flaws of Voting
5-2 Election Theory Flaws of Voting.
Voting systems Chi-Kwong Li.
Voting and social choice
MAT 105 Fall 2008 More Voting Methods.
CPS 173 Voting and social choice
Quiz – 1/24 - Friday How many people voted in the election?
Section 14.1 Voting Methods.
Flaws of the Voting Methods
CPS Voting and social choice
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Presentation transcript:

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan For All Practical Purposes Manipulation in Voting Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates Impossibility The Chair’s Paradox Mathematical Literacy in Today’s World, 7th ed. 1 © 2006, W.H. Freeman and Company

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Manipulation in Voting In the process of voting, you misrepresent your actual preferences on your ballot hoping to strategically achieve the election result that you prefer. Voting manipulation is often referred to as strategic voting. Insincere Ballot or Disingenuous Ballot An insincere ballot is the term given to a ballot that misrepresents a voter’s true preference. 2

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Manipulation in Voting Definition of Manipulability A voting system is said to be manipulable if there exist two sequences of preference list ballots and a voter (call the voter Bob) such that: Neither election results in a tie. The only ballot change is by Bob. Bob prefers (assuming that his ballot in the first election represents his true preferences) the outcome of the second election to that of the first election. A voting system is manipulable if there is at least one scenario in which some voter can achieve a more preferred election outcome by unilaterally changing his or her ballot. Unilateral change in a ballot is when there is only one voter changing his or her ballot. 3

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method May’s Theorem for Manipulability Among all two-candidate voting systems that never result in a tie, majority rule is the only one that treats all voters and both candidates equally and is monotone and nonmanipulable. Monotone means that a single voter’s change in ballot from a vote for the loser to a vote for the winner has no effect on the election outcome. For the two-candidate case, monotonicity and nonmanipulability mean the exact the same thing. Thus, a majority-rule voting system cannot be manipulated. Since Condorcet’s method is based on majority rule and we know majority rule is nonmanipulable, then it follows that Condorcet’s method is nonmanipulable also. 4

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method The Nonmanipulabilty of Condorcet’s Method Condorcet’s method is nonmanipulable in the sense that a voter can never unilaterally change an election result from one candidate to another candidate that he or she prefers. Example: Election with Three Candidates, A, B, C Using Condorcet’s method, suppose you, as one of the voters, prefer candidate A to candidate B, but B wins the election With B winning, Condorcet’s method means that B defeated every other candidate in a one-on-one contest, based on the ballots cast. Even with your original ballot with A over B, candidate B still won more than half of the other voters that ranked B over A for this contest. If you change your ballot to prefer B over A, then B would still defeat A —and this is not what your original true preference was. Note: Using Condorcet’s method, you could change the election by changing your ballot to result in a tie or some other candidate; but you can never change the election to have your true preference (your first choice of all the candidates) win if that candidate lost. 5

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates Nonmanipulability of the Borda Count—Three Candidates The Borda count cannot be manipulated with three candidates. A voter cannot unilaterally change an election outcome from one single winner to another single winner that he/she truly preferred in the first election. Manipulability of the Borda Count—Four or More Candidates The Borda count can be manipulated with four or more candidates and two or more voters. There exists an election in which a voter can unilaterally change the election outcome from one single winner to another single winner that he or she truly preferred originally in the first election. Election 1: Voters’ true preferences Borda scores: A=4, B=5, C=3, D=0 B wins. Election 2: Voter 1 wants A to win and he manipulates list. New Borda scores: A=4, B=3, C=3, D=2 A wins. Election 1 Rank Voters (2) First A B Second C Third Fourth D Election 2 Rank Voters (2) First A B Second D C Third Fourth Points 3 2 1 Points 3 2 1 6

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates Agenda Manipulation of Sequential Pairwise Voting Suppose we have four candidates and three voters who we know will be submitting the following preference lists ballots. Now suppose we have agenda-setting power and we get to choose the order in which the one-on-one contests will take place. With the power to set the agenda, we can arrange for whichever candidate we want the winner to be. Agenda Manipulation – Those in control of procedures can manipulate the agenda by restricting alternatives [candidates] or by arranging the order in which they are brought up. For example: Candidates that appear later in the agenda are favored over those that appear early in the agenda. Agenda B, C, D, A: A wins. Rank Voters (3) First A C B Second D Third Fourth 7

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Other Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates The Group Manipulability of Plurality Voting Plurality voting cannot be manipulated by a single individual. However, it is group manipulable, meaning that there are elections in which a group of voters can change their ballots so that the new winner is preferred to the old winner by everyone in the group, assuming that the original ballots represent the true preferences of each voter in the group. Since only first-place votes are considered, a voter cannot manipulate the vote to get his/her true preference to win. However, insincere voting can take place when someone does not want to vote for his/her true preference because it may in a sense be “throwing away your vote,” as some accuse Nader voters in Florida of doing in the 2000 election. Voting Systems for Three or More Candidates Other voting systems that are manipulable by a single voter, even in the case of three voters and three candidates are the plurality run-off rule, the Hare system, and sequential pairwise voting. 8

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Impossibility Four Desirable Properties of Condorcet’s Method: Elections never result in ties. It satisfies the Pareto condition. It is nonmanipulable. It is not a dictatorship. However, for Condorcet’s voting paradox, we know there are elections that produce no winner at all. Question: Is there a voting system that satisfies all four of these properties and (unlike Condorcet’s method) always yields a winner? Even if we try to loosen the rules (examples: break ties with a fixed ordering list, let the Cordorcet’s winner be the candidate with the best “win-loss record” in one-on-one contests, or Copeland’s rule), the answer is still NO. Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem – With three or more candidates and any number of voters, there does not exist—and there never will exist—a voting system that always produces a winner, never has ties, satisfies the Pareto condition, is nonmanipulable, and is not a dictatorship. 9

Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems The Chair’s Paradox The chair paradox can occur if the voter with tie-breaking power (the “chair”) ends up with his/her least-preferred candidate as the election winner. Example: Suppose we have three candidates—A, B, and C—and three voters whom we’ll call the chair, you, and me. The chair will have tie-breaking power—if each candidate gets one vote, the candidate the chair votes for wins. Otherwise, a candidate would need two out of three votes to win the election. Why is this paradoxical? Because the chair had the most power, but the eventual winner of the election was his least-preferred candidate! Chair You Me A C B 10