Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Foundations PROPOSITIONS A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either True or False, but not the.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Foundations PROPOSITIONS A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either True or False, but not the."— Presentation transcript:

1 The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Foundations PROPOSITIONS A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either True or False, but not the both. Example: 1. Washington is the capital of United states of America, 2. Toronto is the capital of Canada. 3. 1+1 = 2 4. 2+2 = 3 Proposition 1 and 3 are True whereas 2 and 4 are False.

2 The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Foundations Consider the following sentences 1. What time is it? 2. Read this carefully. 3. x+1 = 2 4. x+y = 3 1 and 2 are not Propositions because they are not declarative sentences. 3 and 4 are not Propositions because they are neither True nor False. Truth value of proposition is true, denoted by T and truth value of proposition is false denoted F. The area of logic that deals with propositions is called the propositional calculus or propositional logic. Developed by the Greek philosopher Aristotle 2300 years back.

3 Logical Connectives OperatorSymbolUsage Negation  not Conjunction  and Disjunction  or Exclusive or  xor Conditional  if,then Biconditional  iff

4 Compound Propositions: Examples p = “Cruise ships only go on big rivers.” q = “Cruise ships go on the Hudson.” r = “The Hudson is a big river.”  r = “The Hudson is not a big river.” p  q = “Cruise ships only go on big rivers and go on the Hudson.” p  q  r = “If cruise ships only go on big rivers and go on the Hudson, then the Hudson is a big river.”

5 Negation This just turns a false proposition to true and the opposite for a true proposition. EG: p = “23 = 15 +7” p happens to be false, so  p is true.

6 Negation – truth table Logical operators are defined by truth tables –tables which give the output of the operator in the right-most column. Here is the truth table for negation: p pp FTFT TFTF

7 Conjunction Conjunction is a binary operator in that it operates on two propositions when creating compound proposition. On the other hand, negation is a unary operator (the only non-trivial one possible).

8 Conjunction Conjunction is supposed to encapsulate what happens when we use the word “and” in English. I.e., for “p and q ” to be true, it must be the case that BOTH p is true, as well as q. If one of these is false, than the compound statement is false as well.

9 Conjunction EG. p = “Clinton was the president.” q = “Hilary was the president.” r = “The meaning of is is important.” Assuming p and r are true, while q false. Out of p  q, p  r, q  r only p  r is true.

10 Conjunction – truth table pq pqpq TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TFFFTFFF

11 Disjunction – truth table Conversely, disjunction is true when at least one of the components is true: pq pqpq TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TTTFTTTF

12 Disjunction – Example EG. p = “Clinton was the president.” q = “Hilary was the president.” r = “The meaning of is is not important.” Assuming p is true, while q and r are false. Out of p  q, p  r, q  r only q  r is false.

13 Review NOT, AND, OR What is the disjumction --- or What is the conjunction – and Negation – not Construct the TT for all above

14 Disjunction – caveat A: The entrée is served with soup or salad. Most restaurants definitely don’t allow you to get both soup and salad so that the statement is false when both soup and salad is served. To address this situation, exclusive-or is introduced next.

15 Exclusive-Or – truth table pq p  q TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF FTTFFTTF

16 Conditional (Implication) This one is probably the least intuitive. It’s only partly akin to the English usage of “if, then” or “implies”. DEF: p  q is true if q is true, or if p is false. In the final case (p is true while q is false) p  q is false. Semantics: “p implies q ” is true if one can mathematically derive q from p.

17 Conditional -- truth table pq p  q TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TFTTTFTT

18 Biconditional Let P and Q be propositions. The biconditional P ↔ Q is the proposition that is True when P and Q have the same truth values, and is False otherwise. P if and only if Q P→Q and Q→ P P is necessary and sufficient for Q

19 Biconditional truth table PQ P ↔Q TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TFFTTFFT

20 Let P and Q be the propositions P: It is below freezing. Q: It is snowing. Express each of these propositions as an English sentences P  Q, P  Q,  P  Q, P  Q, P→Q, P↔Q Answers: It is below freezing and snowing. It is below freezing but not snowing. It is not below freezing and it is not snowing. It is below freezing or snowing. If it is below freezing then it is snowing. It is below freezing iff it is snowing

21 Propositional Equivalences

22 Tautologies, contradictions, contingencies DEF: A compound proposition is called a tautology if no matter what truth values its atomic propositions have, its own truth value is T. EG: p  ¬ p (Law of excluded middle) The opposite to a tautology, is a compound proposition that ’ s always false – a contradiction. EG: p  ¬ p On the other hand, a compound proposition whose truth value isn ’ t constant is called a contingency. EG: p  ¬ p

23 Tautologies and contradictions The easiest way to see if a compound proposition is a tautology/contradiction is to use a truth table. TFTF FTFT pp p TTTT p  p TFTF FTFT pp p FFFF p  p

24 Tautology example Demonstrate that [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q is a tautology in two ways: 1.Using a truth table – show that [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q is always true 2.Using a proof (will get to this later).

25 Tautology by truth table pq ¬p¬p p  q ¬ p  (p  q )[ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q TT TF FT FF

26 Tautology by truth table pq ¬p¬p p  q ¬ p  (p  q )[ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q TTF TFF FTT FFT

27 Tautology by truth table pq ¬p¬p p  q ¬ p  (p  q )[ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q TTFT TFFT FTTT FFTF

28 Tautology by truth table pq ¬p¬p p  q ¬ p  (p  q )[ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q TTFTF TFFTF FTTTT FFTFF

29 Tautology by truth table pq ¬p¬p p  q ¬ p  (p  q )[ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q TTFTFT TFFTFT FTTTTT FFTFFT

30 Logical Equivalences DEF: Two compound propositions p, q are logically equivalent if their biconditional joining p  q is a tautology. Logical equivalence is denoted by p  q. EG: The contrapositive of a logical implication is the reversal of the implication, while negating both components. I.e. the contrapositive of p  q is ¬ q  ¬ p. As we ’ ll see next: p  q  ¬ q  ¬ p

31 Logical Equivalence of Conditional and Contrapositive The easiest way to check for logical equivalence is to see if the truth tables of both variants have identical last columns: p  q qp Q: why does this work given definition of  ? ¬q¬p¬q¬p p ¬p¬pq ¬q¬q

32 Logical Equivalence of Conditional and Contrapositive The easiest way to check for logical equivalence is to see if the truth tables of both variants have identical last columns: TFTTTFTT TFTFTFTF TTFFTTFF p  q qp Q: why does this work given definition of  ? ¬q¬p¬q¬p p ¬p¬pq ¬q¬q

33 Logical Equivalence of Conditional and Contrapositive The easiest way to check for logical equivalence is to see if the truth tables of both variants have identical last columns: TFTTTFTT TFTFTFTF TTFFTTFF p  q qp Q: why does this work given definition of  ? TTFFTTFF ¬q¬p¬q¬p p ¬p¬p TFTFTFTF q ¬q¬q

34 Logical Equivalence of Conditional and Contrapositive The easiest way to check for logical equivalence is to see if the truth tables of both variants have identical last columns: TFTTTFTT TFTFTFTF TTFFTTFF p  q qp Q: why does this work given definition of  ? TTFFTTFF ¬q¬p¬q¬p p ¬p¬p TFTFTFTF q FTFTFTFT ¬q¬q

35 Logical Equivalence of Conditional and Contrapositive The easiest way to check for logical equivalence is to see if the truth tables of both variants have identical last columns: TFTTTFTT TFTFTFTF TTFFTTFF p  q qp Q: why does this work given definition of  ? TTFFTTFF ¬q¬p¬q¬p p FFTTFFTT ¬p¬p TFTFTFTF q FTFTFTFT ¬q¬q

36 Logical Equivalence of Conditional and Contrapositive The easiest way to check for logical equivalence is to see if the truth tables of both variants have identical last columns: TFTTTFTT TFTFTFTF TTFFTTFF p  q qp Q: why does this work given definition of  ? TFTTTFTT TTFFTTFF ¬q¬p¬q¬p p FFTTFFTT ¬p¬p TFTFTFTF q FTFTFTFT ¬q¬q

37 Logical Equivalences A: p  q by definition means that p  q is a tautology. Furthermore, the biconditional is true exactly when the truth values of p and of q are identical. So if the last column of truth tables of p and of q is identical, the biconditional join of both is a tautology.

38 Logical Non-Equivalence of Conditional and Converse The converse of a logical implication is the reversal of the implication. I.e. the converse of p  q is q  p. EG: The converse of “ If Donald is a duck then Donald is a bird. ” is “ If Donald is a bird then Donald is a duck. ” As we ’ ll see next: p  q and q  p are not logically equivalent.

39 Logical Non-Equivalence of Conditional and Converse pq p  qq  p(p  q)  (q  p)

40 Logical Non-Equivalence of Conditional and Converse pq p  qq  p(p  q)  (q  p) TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF

41 Logical Non-Equivalence of Conditional and Converse pq p  qq  p(p  q)  (q  p) TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TFTTTFTT

42 Logical Non-Equivalence of Conditional and Converse pq p  qq  p(p  q)  (q  p) TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TFTTTFTT TTFTTTFT

43 Logical Non-Equivalence of Conditional and Converse pq p  qq  p(p  q)  (q  p) TTFFTTFF TFTFTFTF TFTTTFTT TTFTTTFT TFFTTFFT

44 Derivational Proof Techniques When compound propositions involve more and more atomic components, the size of the truth table for the compound propositions increases Q1: How many rows are required to construct the truth-table of: ( (q  (p  r ))  (  (s  r)  t) )  (  q  r ) Q2: How many rows are required to construct the truth-table of a proposition involving n atomic components?

45 Derivational Proof Techniques A1: 32 rows, each additional variable doubles the number of rows A2: In general, 2 n rows Therefore, as compound propositions grow in complexity, truth tables become more and more unwieldy. Checking for tautologies/logical equivalences of complex propositions can become a chore, especially if the problem is obvious.

46 Derivational Proof Techniques EG: consider the compound proposition (p  p )  (  (s  r)  t) )  (  q  r ) Q: Why is this a tautology?

47 Derivational Proof Techniques A: Part of it is a tautology (p  p ) and the disjunction of True with any other compound proposition is still True: (p  p )  (  (s  r)  t ))  (  q  r )  T  (  (s  r)  t ))  (  q  r )  T Derivational techniques formalize the intuition of this example.

48 Tables of Logical Equivalences Identity laws Like adding 0 Domination laws Like multiplying by 0 Idempotent laws Delete redundancies Double negation “ I don ’ t like you, not ” Commutativity Like “ x+y = y+x ” Associativity Like “ (x+y)+z = y+(x+z) ” Distributivity Like “ (x+y)z = xz+yz ” De Morgan

49 Tables of Logical Equivalences Excluded middle Negating creates opposite Definition of implication in terms of Not and Or

50 DeMorgan Identities DeMorgan ’ s identities allow for simplification of negations of complex expressions Conjunctional negation:  (p 1  p 2  …  p n )  (  p 1  p 2  …  p n ) Disjunctional negation:  (p 1  p 2  …  p n )  (  p 1  p 2  …  p n )

51 Tautology example (1.2.8.a) Part 2 Demonstrate that [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q is a tautology in two ways: 1.Using a truth table (did above) 2.Using a proof.

52 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q

53 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive

54 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE

55 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity

56 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE

57 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE  [ ¬ ( ¬ p)  ¬ q ]  q DeMorgan

58 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE  [ ¬ ( ¬ p)  ¬ q ]  q DeMorgan  [p  ¬ q ]  q Double Negation

59 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE  [ ¬ ( ¬ p)  ¬ q ]  q DeMorgan  [p  ¬ q ]  q Double Negation  p  [ ¬ q  q ] Associative

60 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE  [ ¬ ( ¬ p)  ¬ q ]  q DeMorgan  [p  ¬ q ]  q Double Negation  p  [ ¬ q  q ] Associative  p  [q  ¬ q ] Commutative

61 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE  [ ¬ ( ¬ p)  ¬ q ]  q DeMorgan  [p  ¬ q ]  q Double Negation  p  [ ¬ q  q ] Associative  p  [q  ¬ q ] Commutative  p  T ULE

62 Tautology by proof [ ¬ p  (p  q )]  q  [( ¬ p  p)  ( ¬ p  q)]  qDistributive  [ F  ( ¬ p  q)]  q ULE  [ ¬ p  q ]  q Identity  ¬ [ ¬ p  q ]  q ULE  [ ¬ ( ¬ p)  ¬ q ]  q DeMorgan  [p  ¬ q ]  q Double Negation  p  [ ¬ q  q ] Associative  p  [q  ¬ q ] Commutative  p  T ULE  T Domination

63 Exercises Construct the truth table for the following Propositions: 1, (P  Q) →Q 2, (P  Q) →(P  Q) 3, (P→Q)  (  P→  Q) 4, (P  Q)  (P  Q) 5, (P↔Q)  (P↔  Q) Show that the following by constructing the truth table: 1, (P↔Q)  (P→Q)  (Q→P) 2, (P→Q)  P  Q 3, P  (Q  R)  (P  Q)  (P  R)

64 Exercises Show that (P  Q)→(P  Q) is a tautology. Show that [  P  (P  Q)]→Q is a tautology. Determine whether the proposition [  P  (P → Q)]→Q is a tautology or not. Determine whether the proposition [P  (P → Q)]→Q is a tautology or not. Determine whether the proposition [  Q  (P → Q)]→  Q is a tautology or not. Show that  (P→Q)→  Q is a tautology. Show that  (P→Q)→  P is a tautology. Show that  (P  (  P  Q)) and  P  Q are logically equivalent.


Download ppt "The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Foundations PROPOSITIONS A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either True or False, but not the."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google