Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Queer Cases Make Bad Law James C. Hathaway Jason Pobjoy October 2011.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Queer Cases Make Bad Law James C. Hathaway Jason Pobjoy October 2011."— Presentation transcript:

1 Queer Cases Make Bad Law James C. Hathaway Jason Pobjoy October 2011

2  1. How can an implausible risk be real?  2. Why avoid recognizing endogenous harm?  3. Does risk following from behavior warrant refugee status?

3  “... [A] huge gulf has opened up in attitudes to and understanding of gay persons between societies... It is one of the most demanding social issues of our time. Our own government has pledged to do what it can to resolve the problem, but it seems likely to grow and to remain with us for many years. In the meantime more and more gays and lesbians are likely to have to seek protection here, as protection is being denied to them by the state in their home countries. It is crucially important that they are provided with the protection that they are entitled to under the Convention - no more, if I may be permitted to coin a well-known phrase, but certainly no less.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [3].

4 The refugee definition  1. Alienage  2. Genuine risk  3. Serious harm  4. Failure of state protection  5. Nexus to civil or political status  6. Needs and deserves protection

5 “Duty of discretion” rejected  “… [I]t is no answer to a claim for protection as a refugee to say to an applicant that those adverse consequences could be avoided if the applicant were to hide the fact that he or she holds the beliefs in question. And to say to an applicant that he or she should be ‘discreet’ about such matters is simply to use gentler terms to convey the same meaning.” Appellant S395/2002 and S396/2002 v MIMA (2003) 216 CLR 473, [80].

6 “Duty of discretion” rejected  “Saying that an applicant for protection would live ‘discreetly’ in the country of nationality may be an accurate description of the way in which that person would go about his or her daily life. To say that a decision-maker “expects” that that person will live discreetly may also be accurate if it is read as a statement of what is thought likely to happen. But to say that an applicant for protection is ‘expected’ to live discreetly is both wrong and irrelevant to the task to be undertaken by the Tribunal if it is indeed as a statement of what the applicant must do.” Appellant S395/2002 and S396/2002 v MIMA (2003) 216 CLR 473, [82].

7 “Duty of discretion” rejected  “The underlying rationale of the Convention is…that people should be able to live freely, without fearing that they may suffer harm of the requisite intensity or duration because they are, say, black, or the descendants of some former dictator, or gay. In the absence of any indication to the contrary, the implication is that they must be free to live openly in this way without fear of persecution. By allowing them to live openly and free from that fear, the receiving state affords them protection which is a surrogate for the protection which their home state should have afforded them.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [3].

8 11. How can an implausible risk be real? 22. Why avoid recognizing endogenous harm? 33. Does risk following from behavior warrant refugee status?

9  “How can a gay man, who would have a well-founded fear of persecution if he were to live openly as a gay man on return to his country, be said to have a well-founded fear of persecution if on return he would in fact live discreetly, thereby probably escaping the attention of those who might harm him if they were aware of his sexual orientation?... [It] might be thought that this should lead to the conclusion that, if a gay man would live discreetly on return and thereby avoid being harmed or persecuted on account of his sexual orientation, he could not have a well-founded fear of persecution within the meaning of article 1A(2) of the Convention.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [109].

10 A counter-factual assumption of rationality?  “… [T]he appellant is now much more aware of the legal prohibitions on homosexuals in Iran and the potential punishments for breach of those prohibitions… We are satisfied that as a matter of fact he would behave discreetly.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [43].

11 A counter-factual assumption of rationality?  “… [I]n addition to conducting any relationship in private, [the applicant] would move to another part of the country where he would not be known.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [43].

12 A counter-factual assumption of rationality?  “… [W]hen faced with a real threat of persecution, the applicant would have no real choice: he would be compelled to act discreetly.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [59].

13 A counter-factual assumption of rationality?  “Most asylum-seekers will opt for the life of discretion in preference to persecution. This is no real choice. If they are returned, they will, in effect, be required to act discreetly.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [123].

14 A “well-founded fear”  “To the element of fear – a state of mind and a subjective condition – is added the qualification ‘well-founded.’ This implies that it is not only the frame of mind of the person concerned that determines his refugee status, but that the frame of mind must be supported by an objective situation. The term ‘well-founded fear therefore contains a subjective and an objective element...” UNHCR, Handbook (1979), [38].  “… [T]he Convention definition of refugee has been held to encompass both subjective and objective elements. The subjective question is whether the applicant… has a fear of persecution. If that question is answered in the affirmative, the following question, whether that fear is well-founded, is an objective one.” Minister for Immigration and Citizenship v SZJGV and SZJXO [2009] HCA 40, [53].

15 11. How can an implausible risk be real? 22. Why avoid recognizing endogenous harm? 33. Does risk following from behavior warrant refugee status?

16 The refugee definition  1. Alienage  2. Genuine risk  3. Serious harm  4. Failure of state protection  5. Nexus to civil or political status  6. Needs and deserves protection

17 Endogenous harm as persecutory harm  “If [Anne Frank] escaped and claimed asylum, the question would be whether she faced a real risk of persecution on return. The real Anne Frank would have been a refugee because she obviously did and therefore her example may not be helpful. But if (improbably) it was found that on return to Holland she would successfully avoid detection by hiding in the attic, the answer to the first stage of inquiry would be that she was not at real risk of persecution by the Nazis. But the second stage would be to ask whether permanent enforced confinement in her attic would itself amount to persecution. If it would, she would be a refugee.” The Secretary of State for the Home Department, Case for the Respondent (19 April 2010) (submissions filed in HJ and HT) at [68].

18 Endogenous harm as persecutory harm  “[e]ven if it could be imagined that Anne Frank, as an asylum seeker, would not objectively have been at risk of being discovered in the attic, she would nevertheless have had a well-founded fear of serious harm, a fear not eliminated by her decision to conceal her identity as a Jew and live in the attic.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [118].

19 Endogenous harm as persecutory harm  “Simply to re-state the Secretary of State’s argument shows that it is not possible to characterize it as anything other than absurd and unreal. It is plain that it remains the threat to Jews of the concentration camp and the gas chamber which constitutes the persecution.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [107].

20 Serious harm  “As Professor J C Hathaway… has explained, “persecution is most appropriately defined as the sustained or systemic failure of state protection in relation to one of the core entitlements which has been recognised by the international community.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [13].

21 Psychological harm as persecutory harm  “… [I]t is the threat of serious harm with its menacing implications that constitutes the persecutory conduct.” Appellant S395/2002 and S396/2002 v MIMA (2003) 216 CLR 473, [43] (emphasis added).

22 Psychological harm as persecutory harm  “The atmosphere is stifling, sluggish, leaden. Outside, you don’t hear a single bird, and a deathly, oppressive silence hangs over the house and clings to me as if it were going to drag me into the deepest regions of the underworld. At times like these, Father, Mother and Margot don’t matter to me in the least. I wander from room to room, climb up and down the stairs and feel like a songbird whose wings have been ripped off and who keeps hurling itself against the bars of its dark cage. “Let me out, where there’s fresh air and laughter!” a voice within me cries. I don’t even bother to reply any more, but lie down on the divan. Sleep makes the silence and the terrible fear go by more quickly, helps pass the time, since it’s impossible to kill it.” Anne Frank, The Diary of a Young Girl, 154.

23 Psychological harm as persecutory harm  “… [Self-repression] would be to die.” RG (Colombia) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2006] Imm AR 297, [17].

24 Psychological harm as persecutory harm  “… [S]uppressing sexual identity meant living as someone whom you were not, which resulted in an anxiety increase, paranoia and disassociation.” MK (Lesbians) [2009] UKAIT 0036, [68].

25 Serious harm  “As Professor J C Hathaway… has explained, “persecution is most appropriately defined as the sustained or systemic failure of state protection in relation to one of the core entitlements which has been recognised by the international community.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [13].

26 Cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment  “No one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment. In particular, no one shall be subjected without his free consent to medical or scientific experimentation.” Article 7, ICCPR (1976).

27 Cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment  “The prohibition in article 7 relates not only to acts that cause physical pain but also to acts that cause mental suffering to the victim.” General Comment No. 20 (2004), [5].

28 Cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment  “[There was] anguish and stress caused to the mother by the disappearance of her daughter and by the continuing uncertainty concerning her fate and whereabouts. The author has the right to know what has happened to her daughter. In these respects, she too is a victim of the violation of the Covenant suffered by her daughter in particular, of article 7.” Quinteros Almaeida v Uruguay (Communication No. 107/1981) at [14].

29 Persecution of a family member giving rise to psychological harm  “[There is]…a governing principle in favor of refugee status in cases where a parent and protector is faced with exposing her child to the clear risk of being subjected against her will to a practice that is a form of physical torture causing grave and permanent harm. Given the evidence…that Abay herself underwent the procedure at a young age; that Abay’s mother has already attempted to mutilate Abay’s older daughters, who still faced that prospect upon their marriage; that Abay would not be able to override any of her daughters’ future husbands or in-law’s wishes; and that the government of Ethiopia does not, as a practical matter, enforce laws intended to curb traditional practices, we conclude that Abay’s fear of taking her daughter into the lion’s den of female genital mutilation in Ethiopia and being forced to witness the pain and suffering of her daughter is well-founded. Accordingly, we find that Abay is also a “refugee” within the meaning of the Act.” Abay and Amare v Attorney General, 368 F. 3d 634 (6th Cir. 2004), 642.

30 Threats giving rise to psychological harm  “Threats alone, and particularly threats of death, can amount to persecution under certain circumstances. In [Mitev, 67 F.3d at 1331], we considered the possibility that living under threat of death by secret government forces might rise to this level…To live, day after day, knowing that government forces might secretly arrest and execute you is itself a form of mental anguish that can constitute persecution. Yet, logic dictates that for an unfulfilled threat to rise to the level of persecution, it must be something extraordinarily ominous. It cannot simply be a threat of death that, in context, is just a matter of words.” Suganthan Pathmakanthan v Eric H. Holder, Jr, Attorney General of the United States, 612 F.3d 618 (7th Cir. 2010) at [11]-[12] (emphasis added).

31 Discrimination giving rise to psychological harm  “If people are, from an early age, considered by the great majority of the people in the society in which they live too be “dirty,” are positively treated as if they are dirty, and if there is otherwise widespread and far- reaching discrimination against them, it requires no degree in psychology to accept that this may well be very harmful to mental well- being.” SCAT v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural and Indigenous Affairs [2003] FCA 80, [21].

32 Discrimination giving rise to psychological harm  “To suffer the insult and indignity of being regarded by one’s own community…as “dirty like contaminated” because one has suffered the gross ill-treatment of a particularly brutal and dehumanizing rape…is the very sort of cumulative denial of human dignity which to my mind is capable of amounting to persecution.” Regina (Hoxha) v Special Adjudicator; Regina (B) v Immigration Appeal Tribunal [2005] 1 WLR 1063, 1073.

33 Self-repression giving rise to psychological harm  “[T]he concept of persecution is broad enough to include governmental measures that compel an individual to engage in conduct that is not physically painful or harmful but is abhorrent to that individual’s deepest beliefs. An example of such conduct might be requiring a person to renounce his or her religious beliefs or to desecrate an object of religious importance.” Fatin v INS, 12 F.3d 1233 (3rd Cir. 1993), 1242.

34 11. How can an implausible risk be real? 22. Why avoid recognizing endogenous harm? 33. Does risk following from behavior warrant refugee status?

35  “In short, what is protected is the applicant’s right to live freely and openly as a gay man. That involves a wide spectrum of conduct, going well beyond conduct designed to attract sexual partners and maintain relationships with them. To illustrate the point with trivial stereotypical examples from British society: just as male heterosexuals are free to enjoy themselves playing rugby, drinking beer and talking about girls with their mates, so male homosexuals are to be free to enjoy themselves going to Kylie concerts, drinking exotically coloured cocktails and talking about boys with their straight female mates. Mutatis mutandis – and in many cases the adaptations would obviously be great – the same must apply to other societies. In other words, gay men are to be as free as their straight equivalents in the society concerned to live their lives in the way that is natural to them as gay men, without fear of persecution.” HJ (Iran) and HT (Cameroon) v SSHD [2010] UKSC 31, [78].

36  “[G]reat cases like hard cases make bad law. For great cases are called great, not by reason of their importance… but because of some accident of immediate overwhelming interest which appeals to the feelings and distorts the judgment.” Northern Securities Co. v United States, 193 US 197, 400-401.

37 Queer cases make bad law?  Duty of discretion (appropriately) rejected.  A de facto duty of discretion, based on a counter-factual assumption of rationality?  A finding of well-founded fear absent objective forward-looking risk, contradictory to the jurisprudence of all leading courts.  Psychological harm as persecutory harm.  A boundless range of activities falling within the protected interest of “sexual orientation”?


Download ppt "Queer Cases Make Bad Law James C. Hathaway Jason Pobjoy October 2011."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google