Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Presentation is loading. Please wait.

Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.

Similar presentations


Presentation on theme: "Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western."— Presentation transcript:

1 Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western

2 Basic Concepts All games have three basic elements:
Players Strategies Payoffs Players can make binding agreements in cooperative games, but can not in noncooperative games, which are studied in this chapter.

3 Players A player is a decision maker and can be anything from individuals to entire nations. Players have the ability to choose among a set of possible actions. Games are often characterized by the fixed number of players. Generally, the specific identity of a play is not important to the game.

4 Strategies A strategy is a course of action available to a player.
Strategies may be simple or complex. In noncooperative games each player is uncertain about what the other will do since players can not reach agreements among themselves.

5 Payoffs Payoffs are the final returns to the players at the conclusion of the game. Payoffs are usually measure in utility although sometimes measure monetarily. In general, players are able to rank the payoffs from most preferred to least preferred. Players seek the highest payoff available.

6 Equilibrium Concepts In the theory of markets an equilibrium occurred when all parties to the market had no incentive to change his or her behavior. When strategies are chosen, an equilibrium would also provide no incentives for the players to alter their behavior further. The most frequently used equilibrium concept is a Nash equilibrium.

7 Nash Equilibrium The most widely used approach to defining equilibrium in games is that proposed by Cournot and generalized in the 1950s by John Nash. A Nash equilibrium is a set of strategies, one for each player, that are each best responses against one another.

8 Nash Equilibrium In a two-player games, a Nash equilibrium is a pair of strategies (a*,b*) such that a* is an optimal strategy for A against b* and b* is an optimal strategy for B against A*. Players can not benefit from knowing the equilibrium strategy of their opponents. Not every game has a Nash equilibrium, and some games may have several.

9 The Prisoner’s Dilemma
The Prisoner’s Dilemma is a game in which the optimal outcome for the players is unstable. The name comes from the following situation. Two people are arrested for a crime. The district attorney has little evidence but is anxious to extract a confession.

10 The Prisoner’s Dilemma
The DA separates the suspects and tells each, “If you confess and your companion doesn’t, I can promise you a six-month sentence, whereas your companion will get ten years. If you both confess, you will each get a three year sentence.” Each suspect knows that if neither confess, they will be tried for a lesser crime and will receive two-year sentences.

11 The Prisoner’s Dilemma
The normal form (i.e. matrix) of the game is shown in Table 6-1. The confess strategy dominates for both players so it is a Nash equilibria. However, an agreement to remain silent (not to confess) would reduce their prison terms by one year each. This agreement would appear to be the rational solution.

12 TABLE 6-1: The Prisoner’s Dilemma

13 The Prisoner’s Dilemma: Extensive Form
The representation of the game as a tree is referred to as the extensive form. Action proceeds from top to bottom.

14 FIGURE 6-1: The Prisoner’s Dilemma: Extensive Form
. A . . Confess Silent B B Confess Silent Confess Silent -3, -3 -10, -1 -1, -10 -2, -2

15 TABLE 6-2: Solving for Nash Equilibrium in Prisoner’s Dilemma Using the Underlining Method
Step 1

16 TABLE 6-2: Solving for Nash Equilibrium in Prisoner’s Dilemma Using the Underlining Method
Step 2

17 TABLE 6-2: Solving for Nash Equilibrium in Prisoner’s Dilemma Using the Underlining Method
Step 3

18 TABLE 6-2: Solving for Nash Equilibrium in Prisoner’s Dilemma Using the Underlining Method
Step 4

19 TABLE 6-2: Solving for Nash Equilibrium in Prisoner’s Dilemma Using the Underlining Method
Step 5

20 Dominant Strategies A dominant strategy refers to the best response to any strategy chosen by the other player. When a player has a dominant strategy in a game, there is good reason to predict that this is how the player will play the game.

21 Mixed Strategies A mixed strategy refers to when the player randomly selects from several possible actions. By contrast, the strategies in which a player chooses one action or another with certainty are called pure strategies.

22 TABLE 6-3: Matching Pennies Game in Normal Form

23 FIGURE 6-2: Matching Pennies Game in Extensive Form
. A . . Heads Tails B B Heads Tails Heads Tails 1, -1 -1, 1 -1, 1 1, -1

24 TABLE 6-4: Solving for Pure-Strategy Nash Equilibrium in Matching Pennies Game

25 TABLE 6-5: Battle of the Sexes in Normal Form

26 FIGURE 6-3: Battle of the Sexes Game in Extensive Form
. A (Wife) . . Ballet Boxing B (Husband) B (Husband) Ballet Boxing Ballet Boxing 2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2

27 TABLE 6-6: Solving for Pure-Strategy Nash Equilibria in Battle of the Sexes

28 Best-Response Function
The function which gives the payoff-maximizing choice for one player in each of a continuum of actions of the other player is referred to as the best-response function.

29 TABLE 6-7: Computing the Wife’s Best Response to the Husband’s Mixed Strategy
(h)(2) + (1 – h)(0) = 2h (h)(0) + (1 – h)(1) = 1 - h

30 FIGURE 6-4: Best-Response Functions Allowing Mixed Strategies in the Battle of the Sexes
. h Husband’s best-response function Pure-strategy Nash equilibrium (both play Ballet) 1 Wife’s best-response function . 1/3 . Mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium w 2/3 1 Pure-strategy Nash equilibrium (both play Boxing)

31 The Problem of Multiple Equilibria
A rule that selects the highest total payoff would not distinguish between two pure-strategy equilibria. To select between these, one might follow T. Schelling’s suggestion and look for a focal point…a logical outcome on which to coordinate, based on information outside the game.

32 TABLE 6-8: Husband’s Contingent Strategies
Contingent Strategy Strategy written equivalently in conditional format Always go to Ballet Ballet / Ballet, Ballet / Boxing Follow his wife Ballet / Ballet, Boxing / Boxing Do the opposite Boxing / Ballet, Ballet / Boxing Always go to Boxing Boxing / Ballet, Boxing / Boxing

33 TABLE 6-9: Sequential Version of the Battle of the Sexes in Normal Form

34 FIGURE 6-5: Sequential Version of the Battle of the Sexes in Extensive Form
. A (Wife) . . Ballet Boxing B (Husband) B (Husband) Ballet Boxing Ballet Boxing 2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2

35 TABLE 6-10: Solving for Nash Equilibria in the Sequential Version of the Battle of the Sexes

36 Subgame-Perfect Equilibrium
Game theory offers a formal way of selecting the reasonable Nash equilibria in sequential games using the concept of subgame-perfect equilibrium. A proper subgame consists of the part of the game tree including an initial decision not connected to another in an oval and everything branching out below it.

37 FIGURE 6-6: Proper Subgames in the Battle of the Sexes
. Simultaneous Version A (Wife) . . Ballet Boxing B (Husband) B (Husband) Ballet Boxing Ballet Boxing 2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2

38 FIGURE 6-6 (cont.): Proper Subgames in the Battle of the Sexes
Sequential Version A (Wife) . . Ballet Boxing B (Husband) B (Husband) Ballet Boxing Ballet Boxing 2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2

39 Backward Induction A shortcut to finding the subgame-perfect equlibrium directly is to use backward induction. Backward induction solves for the equilibrium by working backwards from the end of the game to the beginning.

40 FIGURE 6-7: Backward Induction in the Sequential Battle of the Sexes
. A (Wife) . . Ballet Boxing B (Husband) B (Husband) Ballet Boxing Ballet Boxing 2, 1 0, 0 0, 0 1, 2 (Next Slide)

41 FIGURE 6-7: Backward Induction in the Sequential Battle of the Sexes
. A (Wife) Ballet Boxing . . B (Husband) B (Husband) plays Ballet plays Boxing 2, 1 1, 2

42 Indefinite Time Horizon
Use the following version of the Prisoners’ Dilemma: The game is played in the first period for certain, but for how many more periods after that the game is played is uncertain. Let r be the probability the game is repeated for another period. (1 – r) is the probability the repitions stop for good.

43 Indefinite Time Horizon
In equilibrium, both players play Silent and each earns –2 each period the game is played, implying a player’s expected payoff over the course of the game is (-2)(1 + r + r2 + r ) 6.1

44 Indefinite Time Horizon
If a player cheats and plays Confess, the cheater earns –1 in that period, but then both play Confess every period and from then on, each earning –3 for each period, for a total expected payoff of -1 + (-3)(r + r2 + r ) 6.2

45 Indefinite Time Horizon
For cooperation to be a subgame-perfect equilibrium, (6.1) must exceed (6.2). Adding 2 to both expressions, and then adding 3(r + r2 + r ) to both expressions, (6.1) exceeds (6.2) if r + r2 + r >

46 Continuous Actions Equations for the Tragedy of Commons:

47 FIGURE 6-8: Best-Response Functions in the Tragedy of the Commons
SB 120 A’s best-response function 60 Nash equilibrium 40 B’s best-response function SA 40 60 120

48 Continuous Actions Equations for the Tragedy of Commons After Equilibria are Shifted:

49 FIGURE 6-9: Shift in Equilibrium When A’s Benefit Increases
A’s best-response function shifts out Nash equilibrium shifts 40 36 B’s best-response function SA 40 48


Download ppt "Chapter 6 Game Theory © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western."

Similar presentations


Ads by Google